\documentclass{article} \input{preamble-articles} \title{Notes on the smash product} \date{\today} \usepackage{fullpage} \newcommand{\pmap}{\to} \newcommand{\lpmap}{\xrightarrow} \renewcommand{\smash}{\wedge} \renewcommand{\phi}{\varphi} \renewcommand{\epsilon}{\varepsilon} \newcommand{\tr}{\cdot} \renewcommand{\o}{\ensuremath{\circ}} \newcommand{\auxl}{\mathsf{auxl}} \newcommand{\auxr}{\mathsf{auxr}} \newcommand{\gluel}{\mathsf{gluel}} \newcommand{\gluer}{\mathsf{gluer}} \newcommand{\sy}{^{-1}} \newcommand{\const}{\ensuremath{\mathbf{0}}\xspace} \begin{document} \maketitle \section{Pointed Types} \begin{defn} We work in the $(\infty,1)$-category of pointed types. \begin{itemize} \item The objects are pointed types $A$, types together with a basepoint $a_0:A$. \item 1-cells are pointed maps $f:A\to B$ which are maps with a chosen path $f_0:f(a_0)=b_0$. We write $A\pmap B$ for pointed maps and $A\pmap B\pmap C$ means $A\pmap (B\pmap C)$. \item 2-cells pointed homotopies. A pointed homotopy $h:f\sim g$ is a homotopy with a chosen 2-path $h(a_0) \tr g_0 = f_0$. \item As 3-cells (or higher cells) we take equalities between 2-cells (or higher cells). \end{itemize} \end{defn} \begin{rmk} \item All types, maps and homotopies in these notes are pointed, unless explicitly mentioned otherwise. Whenever we say that a diagram of $n$-cells commutes we mean it in the sense that there is an $(n+1)$-cell witnessing it. \item Pointed homotopies are equivalent to equalities of pointed types: $(f\sim g)\equiv (f=g)$. So we could have chosen to define our 2-cells as equalities between 1-cells. We choose not to, since the aforementioned equivalence requires function extensionality. In a type theory where function extensionality doesn't compute (like Lean) it is better to define the type of pointed homotopies manually so that the underlying homotopy of a 2-cell is definitionally equal to the homotopy we started with. In diagrams, we will denote pointed homotopies by equalities, but we always mean pointed homotopies. \item The type $A\to B$ of pointed maps from $A$ to $B$ is itself pointed, with as basepoint the constant map $0\equiv0_{A,B}:A\to B$ which has as underlying function $\lam{a:A}b_0$. We have $0\o g \sim 0$ and $f \o 0 \sim 0$. \item A pointed equivalence is a pointed map $f : A \to B$ whose underlying map is an equivalence. In this case, we can find a pointed map $f\sy:B\to A$ with pointed homotopies $f\o f\sy\sim0$ and $f\sy\o f\sim0$. \end{rmk} \begin{lem} Given maps $f:A'\pmap A$ and $g:B\pmap B'$. Then there are maps $(f\pmap C):(A\pmap C)\pmap(A'\pmap C)$ and $(C\pmap g):(C\pmap B)\pmap(C\pmap B')$ given by precomposition with $f$, resp. postcomposition with $g$. The map $\lam{g}C\pmap g$ preserves the basepoint, giving rise to a map $$(C\pmap ({-})):(B\pmap B')\pmap(C\pmap B)\pmap(C\pmap B').$$ Also, the following square commutes \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (A\pmap B) \arrow[r,"A\pmap g"]\arrow[d,"f\pmap B"] & (A\pmap B')\arrow[d,"f\pmap B'"] \\ (A'\pmap B) \arrow[r,"A'\pmap g"] & (A'\pmap B') \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \end{lem} \section{Smash Product} \begin{defn} The smash of $A$ and $B$ is the HIT generated by the point constructor $(a,b)$ for $a:A$ and $b:B$ and two auxilliary points $\auxl,\auxr:A\smash B$ and path constructors $\gluel_a:(a,b_0)=\auxl$ and $\gluer_b:(a_0,b)=\auxr$ (for $a:A$ and $b:B$). $A\smash B$ is pointed with point $(a_0,b_0)$. \end{defn} \begin{rmk} \item This definition of $A\smash B$ is basically the pushout of $\bool\leftarrow A+B\to A \times B$. A more traditional definition of $A\smash B$ is the pushout $\unit\leftarrow A\vee B\to A \times B$. Here $\vee$ denotes the wedge product, which can be equivalently described as either the pushout $A\leftarrow \unit\to B$ or $\unit\leftarrow \bool\to A + B$. These two definitions of $A\smash B$ are equivalent, because in the following diagram the top-left square and the top rectangle are pushout squares, hence the top-right square is a pushout square by applying the pushout lemma. Another application of the pushout lemma now states that the two definitions of $A\smash B$ are equivalent. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} \bool \arrow[r]\arrow[d] & A+B \arrow[r]\arrow[d] & \bool \arrow[d] \\ \unit \arrow[r] & A\vee B \arrow[r]\arrow[d] & \unit \arrow[d] \\ & A\times B \arrow[r] & A\smash B \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \end{rmk} \begin{lem}\mbox{}\label{lem:smash-general} \begin{itemize} \item The smash is functorial: if $f:A\pmap A'$ and $g:B\pmap B'$ then $f\smash g:A\smash B\pmap A'\smash B'$. We write $A\smash g$ or $f\smash B$ if one of the functions is the identity function. \item Smash preserves composition, which gives rise to the interchange law: $i:(f' \o f)\smash (g' \o g) \sim f' \smash g' \o f \smash g$ \item If $p:f\sim f'$ and $q:g\sim g'$ then $p\smash q:f\smash g\sim f'\smash g'$. This operation preserves reflexivities, symmetries and transitivies. \item There are homotopies $f\smash0\sim0$ and $0\smash g\sim 0$ such that the following diagrams commute for given homotopies $p : f\sim f'$ and $q : g\sim g'$. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} f\smash 0 \arrow[rr, equals,"p\smash1"]\arrow[dr,equals] & & f'\smash 0\arrow[dl,equals] \\ & 0 & \end{tikzcd} \qquad \begin{tikzcd} 0\smash g\arrow[rr, equals,"1\smash q"]\arrow[dr,equals] & & 0\smash g'\arrow[dl,equals] \\ & 0 & \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \end{itemize} \end{lem} \begin{lem}\label{lem:smash-coh} Suppose that we have maps $A_1\lpmap{f_1}A_2\lpmap{f_2}A_3$ and $B_1\lpmap{g_1}B_2\lpmap{g_2}B_3$ and suppose that either $f_1$ or $f_2$ is constant. Then there are two homotopies $(f_2 \o f_1)\smash (g_2 \o g_1)\sim 0$, one which uses interchange and one which doesn't. These two homotopies are equal. Specifically, the following two diagrams commute: \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (f_2 \o 0)\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[dd,equals] & (f_2 \smash g_2)\o (0 \smash g_1)\arrow[d,equals] \\ & (f_2 \smash g_2)\o 0\arrow[d,equals] \\ 0\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r,equals] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \qquad \begin{tikzcd} (0 \o f_1)\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[dd,equals] & (0 \smash g_2)\o (f_1 \smash g_1)\arrow[d,equals] \\ & 0\o (f_1 \smash g_1)\arrow[d,equals] \\ 0\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r,equals] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \end{lem} \begin{proof} We will only do the case where $f_1\jdeq 0$, i.e. fill the diagram on the left. The other case is similar (and slightly easier). First apply induction on the paths that $f_2$, $g_1$ and $g_2$ respect the basepoint. In this case $f_2\o0$ is definitionally equal to $0$, and the canonical proof that $f_2\o 0\sim0$ is (definitionally) equal to reflexivity. This means that the homotopy $(f_2 \o 0)\smash (g_2 \o g_1)\sim0\smash (g_2 \o g_1)$ is also equal to reflexivity, and also the path that $f_2 \smash g_2$ respects the basepoint is reflexivity, hence the homotopy $(f_2 \smash g_2)\o 0\sim0$ is also reflexivity. This means we need to fill the following square, where $q$ is the proof that $0\smash f\sim 0$. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (f_2 \o 0)\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r, equals,"i"]\arrow[d,equals,"1"] & (f_2 \smash g_2)\o (0 \smash g_1)\arrow[d,equals,"(f_2\smash g_2)\o q"] \\ 0\smash (g_2 \o g_1) \arrow[r,equals,"q"] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \end{center} For the underlying homotopy, take $x : A_1\smash B_1$ and apply induction on $x$. Suppose $x\equiv(a,b)$ for $a:A_1$ and $b:B_1$. Then we have to fill the square (denote the basepoints of $A_i$ and $B_i$ by $a_i$ and $b_i$ and we suppress the arguments of $\gluer$). Now $\mapfunc{h\smash k}(\gluer_z)=\gluer_{k(z)}$, so by general groupoid laws we see that the path on the bottom is equal to the path on the right, which means we can fill the square. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (f_2(a_2),g_2(g_1(b)))\arrow[r, equals,"1"] \arrow[d,equals,"1"] & % \arrow[d,equals,"\gluer_{g_2(g_1(b))}\tr\gluer_{g_2(g_1(b_1))}\sy"] & (f_2(a_2),g_2(g_1(b)))\arrow[d,equals,"\mapfunc{f_2\smash g_2}(\gluer\tr\gluer\sy)"] \\ (a_3,g_2(g_1(b))) \arrow[r,equals,"\gluer\tr\gluer\sy"] & (a_3,b_3) \end{tikzcd} \end{center} If $x$ is either $\auxl$ or $\auxr$ it is similar but easier. For completeness, we will write down the square we have to fill in the case that $x$ is $\auxr$. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} \auxr \arrow[r, equals,"1"] \arrow[d,equals,"1"] & \auxr \arrow[d,equals,"\mapfunc{f_2\smash g_2}(\gluer_{b_2}\sy)"] \\ \auxr \arrow[r,equals,"\gluer_{g_2(b_2)}\sy"] & (a_3,b_3) \end{tikzcd} \end{center} If $x$ varies over $\gluer_b$, we need to fill the cube below. The front and the back are the squares we just filled, the left square is a degenerate square, and the other three squares are the squares in the definition of $q$ and $i$ to show that they respect $\gluer_b$ (and on the right we apply $f_2\smash g_2$ to that square). \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} & \auxr \arrow[rr, equals,"1"] \arrow[dd,equals,near start,"1"] & & \auxr \arrow[dd,equals,"\mapfunc{f_2\smash g_2}(\gluer_{b_2}\sy)"] \\ (f_2(a_2),g_2(g_1(b)))\arrow[rr, equals, near start, crossing over, "1"] \arrow[dd,equals,"1"] \arrow[ur,equals] & & (f_2(a_2),g_2(g_1(b))) \arrow[ur,equals] & \\ & \auxr \arrow[rr,equals,near start, "\gluer_{g_2(b_2)}\sy"] & & (a_3,b_3) \\ (a_3,g_2(g_1(b))) \arrow[rr,equals,"\gluer\tr\gluer\sy"] \arrow[ur,equals] & & (a_3,b_3) \arrow[from=uu, equals, crossing over, very near start, "\mapfunc{f_2\smash g_2}(\gluer\tr\gluer\sy)"] \arrow[ur,equals] & \end{tikzcd} \end{center} After canceling applications of $\mapfunc{h\smash k}(\gluer_z)=\gluer_{k(z)}$ on various sides of the squares (TODO). If $x$ varies over $\gluel_a$ the proof is very similar. Only in the end we need to fill the following cube instead (TODO). \end{proof} \begin{thm}\label{thm:smash-functor-right} Given pointed types $A$, $B$ and $C$, the functorial action of the smash product induces a map $$({-})\smash C:(A\pmap B)\pmap(A\smash C\pmap B\smash C)$$ which is natural in $A$, $B$ and $C$. (note: $(A\smash C\pmap B\smash C)$ is both covariant and contravariant in $C$). \end{thm} \begin{proof} First note that $\lam{f}f\smash C$ preserves the basepoint so that the map is indeed pointed. We show that this map is natural in each of its arguments individually, which means we need to fill the following squares for $f : A' \to A$ $g:B\to B'$ and $h:C\to C'$. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (A\pmap B) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash C"]\arrow[d,"f\pmap B"] & (A\smash C\pmap B\smash C)\arrow[d,"f\smash C\pmap B\smash C"] \\ (A'\pmap B) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash C"] & (A'\smash C\pmap B\smash C) \end{tikzcd} \begin{tikzcd} (A\pmap B) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash C"]\arrow[d,"A\pmap g"] & (A\smash C\pmap B\smash C)\arrow[d,"A\smash C\pmap g\smash C"] \\ (A\pmap B') \arrow[r,"({-})\smash C"] & (A\smash C\pmap B'\smash C) \end{tikzcd} \begin{tikzcd}[column sep=large] (A\pmap B) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash C"]\arrow[d,"({-})\smash C'"] & (A\smash C\pmap B\smash C)\arrow[d,"A\smash C\pmap B\smash h"] \\ (A\smash C'\pmap B\smash C') \arrow[r,"A\smash h\pmap B\smash C'"] & (A\smash C\pmap B\smash C') \end{tikzcd} \end{center} Let $k:A\pmap B$. Then as homotopy the naturality in $A$ becomes $(k\o f)\smash C=k\smash C\o f\smash C$. To prove an equality between pointed maps, we need to give a pointed homotopy, which is given by interchange. To show that this homotopy is pointed, we need to fill the following square (after reducing out the applications of function extensinality), which follows from \autoref{lem:smash-coh}. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (0 \o f)\smash C \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[dd,equals] & (0 \smash C)\o (f \smash C)\arrow[d,equals] \\ & 0 \o (f \smash C)\arrow[d,equals] \\ 0\smash C \arrow[r,equals] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \end{center} The naturality in $B$ is almost the same: for the underlying homotopy we need to show $(g \o k)\smash C = g\smash C \o k\smash C$. For the pointedness we need to fill the following square, which follows from \autoref{lem:smash-coh}. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (g \o 0)\smash C \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[dd,equals] & (g \smash C)\o (0 \smash C)\arrow[d,equals] \\ & (g\smash C) \o 0\arrow[d,equals] \\ 0\smash C \arrow[r,equals] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \end{center} The naturality in $C$ is a bit harder. For the underlying homotopy we need to show $B\smash h\o k\smash C=k\smash C'\o A\smash h$. This follows by applying interchange twice: $$B\smash h\o k\smash C\sim(\idfunc[B]\o k)\smash(h\o\idfunc[C])\sim(k\o\idfunc[A])\smash(\idfunc[C']\o h)\sim k\smash C'\o A\smash h.$$ To show that this homotopy is pointed, we need to fill the following square: \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} B\smash h\o 0\smash C \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[d,equals] & (\idfunc[B]\o 0)\smash(h\o\idfunc[C]) \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[d,equals] & (0\o\idfunc[A])\smash(\idfunc[C']\o h)\arrow[r, equals]\arrow[d,equals] & 0\smash C'\o A\smash h\arrow[d,equals] \\ B\smash h\o 0 \arrow[d,equals] & 0\smash(h\o\idfunc[C]) \arrow[r, equals]\arrow[d,equals] & 0\smash(\idfunc[C']\o h) \arrow[d,equals] & 0\o A\smash h\arrow[d,equals] \\ B\smash h\o 0 \arrow[r, equals] & 0 \arrow[r, equals] & 0 \arrow[r, equals] & 0 \end{tikzcd} \end{center} The left and the right squares are filled by \autoref{lem:smash-coh}. The squares in the middle are filled by (corollaries of) \autoref{lem:smash-general}. \end{proof} \section{Adjunction} \begin{lem} There is a unit $\eta_{A,B}\equiv\eta:A\pmap B\pmap A\smash B$ and counit $\epsilon_{B,C}\equiv\epsilon : (B\pmap C)\smash B \pmap C$ which are natural in both arguments and satisfy the unit-counit laws: $$(A\to\epsilon_{A,B})\o \eta_{A\to B,A}\sim \idfunc[A\to B]\qquad \epsilon_{B,B\smash C}\o \eta_{A,B}\smash B\sim\idfunc[A\smash B].$$ \end{lem} \begin{proof} We define $\eta ab=(a,b)$. Then $\eta a$ respects the basepoint because $(a,b_0)=(a_0,b_0)$. Also, $\eta$ itself respects the basepoint. To show this, we need to show that $\eta a_0\sim0$. The underlying maps are homotopic, since $(a_0,b)=(a_0,b_0)$. To show that this homotopy is pointed, we need to show that the two given proofs of $(a_0,b_0)=(a_0,b_0)$ are equal, but they are both equal to reflexivity: $$\gluel_{a_0}\tr\gluel_{a_0}\sy=1=\gluer_{b_0}\tr\gluer_{b_0}\sy.$$ This defines the unit. To define the counit, given $x:(B\pmap C)\smash B$. We construct $\epsilon x:C$ by induction on $x$. If $x\jdeq(f,b)$ we set $\epsilon(f,b)\defeq f(b)$. If $x$ is either $\auxl$ or $\auxr$ then we set $\epsilon x\defeq c_0:C$. If $x$ varies over $\gluel_f$ then we need to show that $f(b_0)=c_0$, which is true by $f_0$. If $x$ varies over $\gluer_b$ we need to show that $0(b)=c_0$ which is true by reflexivity. $\epsilon$ is trivially a pointed map, which defines the counit. Now we need to show that the unit and counit are natural. (TODO). Finally we need to show that unit-counit laws. For the underlying homotopy of the first one, let $f:A\to B$. We need to show that $p:\epsilon\o\eta f\sim f$. For the underlying homotopy of $p$, let $a:A$, and we need to show that $\epsilon(f,a)=f(a)$, which is true by reflexivity. To show that $p$ is a pointed homotopy, we need to show that $p(a_0)\tr f_0=\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\eta f)_0\tr \epsilon_0$, which reduces to $f_0=\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluel_f\tr\gluel_0\sy)$, but we can reduce the right hand side: (note: $0_0$ denotes the proof that $0(a_0)=b_0$, which is reflexivity) $$\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluel_f\tr\gluel_0\sy)=\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluel_f)\tr(\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluel_0))\sy=f_0\tr 0_0\sy=f_0.$$ Now we need to show that $p$ itself respects the basepoint of $A\to B$, i.e. that the composite $\epsilon\o\eta0\sim\epsilon\o0\sim0$ is equal to $p$ for $f\equiv 0_{A,B}$. The underlying homotopies are the same for $a : A$; on the one side we have $\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluer_{a}\tr\gluer_{a_0}\sy)$ and on the other side we have reflexivity (note: this typechecks, since $0_{A,B}a\equiv0_{A,B}a_0$). These paths are equal, since $$\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluer_{a}\tr\gluer_{a_0}\sy)=\mapfunc{\epsilon}(\gluer_{a})\tr(\mapfunc\epsilon(\gluer_{a_0}))\sy=1\cdot1\sy\equiv1.$$ Both pointed homotopies are pointed in the same way, which requires some path-algebra, and we skip the proof here. For the underlying homotopy of the second one, we need to show for $x:A\smash B$ that $\epsilon(\eta\smash B(x))=x$, which we prove by induction to $x$. (TODO). \end{proof} \begin{defn} The function $e\jdeq e_{A,B,C}:(A\pmap B\pmap C)\pmap(A\smash B\pmap C)$ is defined as the composite $$(A\pmap B\pmap C)\lpmap{({-})\smash B}(A\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B)\lpmap{A\smash B \pmap\epsilon}(A\smash B\pmap C)).$$ \end{defn} \begin{lem} $e$ is invertible, hence gives a pointed equivalence $$(A\pmap B\pmap C)\simeq(A\smash B\pmap C).$$ \end{lem} \begin{proof} Define $$\inv{e}_{A,B,C}:(A\smash B\pmap C)\lpmap{B\pmap({-})}((B\pmap A\smash B)\pmap (B\pmap C))\lpmap{\eta\pmap(B\pmap C)}(A\pmap B\pmap C).$$ It is easy to show that $e$ and $\inv{e}$ are inverses as unpointed maps from the unit-counit laws and naturality of $\eta$ and $\epsilon$. \end{proof} \begin{lem}\label{e-natural} $e$ is natural in $A$, $B$ and $C$. \end{lem} \begin{rmk} \item Instead of showing that $e$ is natural, we could instead show that $e^{-1}$ is natural. In that case we need to show that the map $A\to({-}):(B\to C)\to(A\to B)\to(A\to C)$ is natural in $A$, $B$ and $C$. This might actually be easier, since we don't need to work with any higher inductive type to prove that. \end{rmk} \begin{proof} \textbf{$e$ is natural in $A$}. Suppose that $f:A'\pmap A$. Then the following diagram commutes. The left square commutes by naturality of $({-})\smash B$ in the first argument and the right square commutes because composition on the left commutes with composition on the right. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (A\pmap B\pmap C) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash B"]\arrow[d,"f\pmap B\pmap C"] & (A\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B) \arrow[r,"A\smash B\pmap\epsilon"]\arrow[d,"f\smash B\pmap\cdots"] & (A\smash B\pmap C)\arrow[d,"f\smash B\pmap C"] \\ (A'\pmap B\pmap C) \arrow[r,"({-})\smash B"] & (A'\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B) \arrow[r,"A\smash B\pmap\epsilon"] & (A'\smash B\pmap C) \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \textbf{$e$ is natural in $C$}. Suppose that $f:C\pmap C'$. Then in the following diagram the left square commutes by naturality of $({-})\smash B$ in the second argument (applied to $B\pmap f$) and the right square commutes by applying the functor $A\smash B \pmap({-})$ to the naturality of $\epsilon$ in the second argument. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd} (A\pmap B\pmap C) \arrow[r]\arrow[d] & (A\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B) \arrow[r]\arrow[d] & (A\smash B\pmap C)\arrow[d] \\ (A\pmap B\pmap C') \arrow[r] & (A\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C')\smash B) \arrow[r] & (A\smash B\pmap C') \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \textbf{$e$ is natural in $B$}. Suppose that $f:B'\pmap B$. The diagram looks weird since $({-})\smash B$ is both contravariant and covariant in $B$. Then we get the following diagram. The front square commutes by naturality of $({-})\smash B$ in the second argument (applied to $f\pmap C$). The top square commutes by naturality of $({-})\smash B$ in the third argument, the back square commutes because composition on the left commutes with composition on the right, and finally the right square commutes by applying the functor $A\smash B' \pmap({-})$ to the naturality of $\epsilon$ in the first argument. \begin{center} \begin{tikzcd}[row sep=scriptsize, column sep=-4em] & (A\smash B\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B) \arrow[rr] \arrow[dd] & & (A\smash B'\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B)\arrow[dd] \\ (A\pmap B\pmap C) \arrow[ur] \arrow[rr, crossing over] \arrow[dd] & & (A\smash B'\pmap (B\pmap C)\smash B') \arrow[ur] \\ & (A\smash B\pmap C)\arrow[rr] & & (A\smash B'\pmap C) \\ (A\pmap B'\pmap C) \arrow[rr] & & (A\smash B'\pmap (B'\pmap C)\smash B') \arrow[ur] \arrow[from=uu, crossing over]\\ \end{tikzcd} \end{center} \end{proof} \begin{thm} The smash product is associative: there is an equivalence $f : A \smash (B \smash C) \simeq (A \smash B) \smash C$ which is natural in $A$, $B$ and $C$. \end{thm} \begin{proof} Let $\phi_X$ be the composite of the following equivalences: \begin{align*} A \smash (B \smash C)\to X&\simeq A \to B\smash C\to X\\ &\simeq A \to B\to C\to X\\ &\simeq A \smash B\to C\to X\\ &\simeq (A \smash B)\smash C\to X. \end{align*} $\phi_X$ is natural in $A,B,C,X$ by repeatedly applying \autoref{e-natural}. Let $f\defeq\phi_{A \smash (B \smash C)}(\idfunc)$ and $f\sy\defeq\phi\sy_{(A \smash B) \smash C}(\idfunc)$. Now these maps are inverses by naturality of $\phi$ in $X$: $$f\sy\o f\equiv f\sy\o \phi(\idfunc)\sim \phi(f\sy\o\idfunc)\sim \phi(\phi\sy(\idfunc))\sim\idfunc.$$ The other composition is the identity by a similar argument. Lastly, $f$ is natural in $A$, $B$ and $C$, since $\phi_X$ is. \end{proof} \section{Notes on the formalization} The order of arguments are different in the formalization here and there. Also, some smashes are commuted. This is because some unfortunate choices have been made in the formalization. Reversing these choices is possible, but probably more work than it's worth (the final result is exactly the same). \end{document}