path induction post
All checks were successful
ci/woodpecker/push/woodpecker Pipeline was successful
All checks were successful
ci/woodpecker/push/woodpecker Pipeline was successful
This commit is contained in:
parent
f50ec75e01
commit
5216167465
1 changed files with 135 additions and 0 deletions
|
@ -0,0 +1,135 @@
|
|||
---
|
||||
title: "Path induction eliminator: a GADT perspective"
|
||||
slug: 2023-10-23-path-induction-gadt-perspective
|
||||
date: 2023-10-23
|
||||
tags: ["type-theory"]
|
||||
draft: true
|
||||
---
|
||||
|
||||
<details>
|
||||
<summary>Imports</summary>
|
||||
|
||||
```
|
||||
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality
|
||||
open import Data.Nat
|
||||
open import Data.Bool
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
</details>
|
||||
|
||||
> [!NOTE]
|
||||
> This content is a writeup from a weekend discussion session for the fall 2023 special-topics course CSCI 8980 at the University of Minnesota taught by [Favonia], who provided the examples.
|
||||
> This post is primarily a summary of the concepts discussed.
|
||||
|
||||
An important concept in [Martin-Löf Type Theory][mltt] is the internal equality[^1] type $\mathrm{Id}$.
|
||||
Like all inductive types, it comes with the typical rules used to introduce types:
|
||||
|
||||
[^1]:
|
||||
"Internal" here is used to mean something expressed within the type theory itself, rather than in the surrounding meta-theory, which is considered "external."
|
||||
For more info, see [this][equality] page.
|
||||
|
||||
- Formation rule
|
||||
- Introduction rule
|
||||
- Elimination rule
|
||||
- Computation rule
|
||||
|
||||
There's something quite peculiar about the elimination rule in particular (commonly known as "path induction", or just $J$).
|
||||
Let's take a look at its definition, in Agda-ish syntax:
|
||||
|
||||
```agda
|
||||
J : {A : Set}
|
||||
→ (C : (x y : A) → x ≡ y → Set)
|
||||
→ (c : (x : A) → C x x refl)
|
||||
→ (x y : A) → (p : x ≡ y) → C x y p
|
||||
J C c x x refl = c x
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
<details>
|
||||
<summary>What does this mean?</summary>
|
||||
|
||||
An _eliminator_ rule defines how a type is used.
|
||||
It's the primitive that often powers programming language features like pattern matching.
|
||||
We can break this function down into each of the parameters it takes:
|
||||
|
||||
- $C$ is short for "motive".
|
||||
Think of $J$ as producing an $\mathrm{Id} \rightarrow C$ function, but we have to include the other components or else it's not complete.
|
||||
- $c$ tells you how to handle the _only_ constructor to $\mathrm{Id}$, which is $\mathrm{refl}$.
|
||||
Think of this as a kind of pattern match on the $\mathrm{refl}$ case, since $\mathrm{Id}$ is just a regular inductive type.
|
||||
- $x, y, p$ these are just a part of the final $\mathrm{Id} \rightarrow C$ function.
|
||||
|
||||
How $J$ is computed depends on your type theory's primitives; in HoTT you would define it in terms of something like transport.
|
||||
|
||||
</details>
|
||||
|
||||
There's something odd about this: the $c$ case only defines what happens in the case of $C(x, x, \mathrm{refl})$, but the final $J$ definition extends to arbitrary $C(x, y, p)$.
|
||||
How can this be the case?
|
||||
|
||||
A good way to think about this is using [generalized algebraic data types][gadt], or GADTs.
|
||||
A GADT is similar to a normal inductive data type, but it can be indexed by a type.
|
||||
This is similar to polymorphism on data types, but much more powerful.
|
||||
Consider the following non-generalized data type:
|
||||
|
||||
```agda
|
||||
data List (A : Set) : Set where
|
||||
Nil : List A
|
||||
Cons : A → List A → List A
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
I could write functions with this, but either polymorphically (accepts `A : Set` as a parameter, with no knowledge of what the type is) or monomorphically (as a specific `List Int` or `List Bool` or something).
|
||||
What I couldn't do would be something like this:
|
||||
|
||||
```text
|
||||
sum : (A : Set) → List A → A
|
||||
sum Int Nil = 0
|
||||
sum Int (Cons hd tl) = hd + (sum tl)
|
||||
sum A Nil = {! !}
|
||||
sum A (Cons hd tl) = {! !}
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Once I've chosen to go polymorphic, there's no option to know anything about the type, and I can only operate generally on it[^2].
|
||||
|
||||
[^2]:
|
||||
As another example, if you have a polymorphic function with the type signature $\forall A . A \rightarrow A$, there's no implementation other than the $\mathrm{id}$ function, because there's no other knowledge about the type.
|
||||
For more info, see [Theorems for Free][free]
|
||||
|
||||
With GADTs, this changes.
|
||||
The key here is that different constructors of the data type can return different types of the same type family.
|
||||
|
||||
```
|
||||
data Wrap : Set → Set where
|
||||
N : ℕ → Wrap ℕ
|
||||
B : Bool → Wrap Bool
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Note that in the definition, I've moved the parameter from the left side to the right.
|
||||
This means I'm no longer committing to a fully polymorphic `A`, which is now allowed to be assigned anything freely.
|
||||
In particular, it's able to take different values for different constructors.
|
||||
|
||||
This allows me to write functions that are polymorphic over _all_ types, while still having the ability to refer to specific types.
|
||||
|
||||
```agda
|
||||
unwrap : {A : Set} → Wrap A → A
|
||||
unwrap (N n) = n
|
||||
unwrap (B b) = b
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Note that the type signature of `unwrap` remains fully polymorphic, while each of the cases has full type information.
|
||||
This is sound because we know exactly what indexes `Wrap` could take, and the fact that there are no other ways to construct a `Wrap` means we won't ever run into a case where we would be stuck on a case we don't know how to handle.
|
||||
|
||||
In a sense, each of the pattern match "arms" is giving more information about the polymorphic return type.
|
||||
In the `N` case, it can _only_ return `Wrap ℕ`, and in the `B` case, it can _only_ return `Wrap Bool`.
|
||||
|
||||
The same thing applies to the $\mathrm{Id}$ type, since $\mathrm{Id}$ is pretty much just a generalized and dependent data type.
|
||||
The singular constructor `refl` is only defined on the index `Id A x x`, but the type has a more general `Id A x y`.
|
||||
So the eliminator only needs to handle the case of an element of $A$ equal to itself, because that's the "only" constructor for $\mathrm{Id}$ in the first place[^3].
|
||||
|
||||
[^3]: Not true in [homotopy type theory][hott], where the titular _univalence_ axiom creates terms in the identity type using equivalences.
|
||||
|
||||
Hopefully now the path induction type doesn't seem as "magical" to you anymore!
|
||||
|
||||
[mltt]: https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/Martin-L%C3%B6f+dependent+type+theory
|
||||
[equality]: https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/equality#notions_of_equality_in_type_theory
|
||||
[gadt]: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Generalized_algebraic_data_type
|
||||
[free]: https://www2.cs.sfu.ca/CourseCentral/831/burton/Notes/July14/free.pdf
|
||||
[favonia]: https://favonia.org/
|
||||
[hott]: https://homotopytypetheory.org/book/
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue