+++ title = "Proving true ≢ false" slug = "proving-true-from-false" date = 2023-04-21 tags = ["type-theory", "agda"] math = true +++
Imports These are some imports that are required for code on this page to work properly. ```agda {-# OPTIONS --cubical #-} open import Cubical.Foundations.Prelude open import Data.Bool open import Data.Unit open import Data.Empty ¬_ : Set → Set ¬ A = A → ⊥ infix 4 _≢_ _≢_ : ∀ {A : Set} → A → A → Set x ≢ y = ¬ (x ≡ y) ```
The other day, I was trying to prove `true ≢ false` in Agda. I would write the statement like this: ``` true≢false : true ≢ false ``` For many "obvious" statements, it suffices to just write `refl` since the two sides are trivially true via rewriting. For example: ``` open import Data.Nat 1+2≡3 : 1 + 2 ≡ 3 1+2≡3 = refl ``` This is saying that using the way addition is defined, we can just rewrite the left side so it becomes judgmentally equal to the right: ``` -- For convenience, here's the definition of addition: -- _+_ : Nat → Nat → Nat -- zero + m = m -- suc n + m = suc (n + m) ``` - 1 + 2 - suc zero + suc (suc zero) - suc (zero + suc (suc zero)) - suc (suc (suc zero)) - 3 However, in cubical Agda, naively using `refl` with the inverse statement doesn't work. I've commented it out so the code on this page can continue to compile. ``` -- true≢false = refl ``` It looks like it's not obvious to the interpreter that this statement is actually true. Why is that --- Well, in constructive logic / constructive type theory, proving something is false is actually a bit different. You see, the definition of the `not` operator, or $\neg$, was: ``` -- ¬_ : Set → Set -- ¬ A = A → ⊥ ``` > The code is commented out because it was already defined at the top of the > page in order for the code to compile. This roughly translates to, "give me any proof of A, and I'll produce a value of the bottom type." Since the bottom type $\bot$ is a type without values, being able to produce a value represents logical falsehood. So we're looking for a way to ensure that any proof of `true ≢ false` must lead to $\bot$. The strategy here is we define some kind of "type-map". Every time we see `true`, we'll map it to some arbitrary inhabited type, and every time we see `false`, we'll map it to empty. ``` bool-map : Bool → Type bool-map true = ⊤ bool-map false = ⊥ ``` This way, we can use the fact that transporting over a path (the path supposedly given to us as the witness that true ≢ false) will produce a function from the inhabited type we chose to the empty type! ``` true≢false p = transport (λ i → bool-map (p i)) tt ``` I used `true` here, but I could equally have just used anything else: ``` bool-map2 : Bool → Type bool-map2 true = 1 ≡ 1 bool-map2 false = ⊥ true≢false2 : true ≢ false true≢false2 p = transport (λ i → bool-map2 (p i)) refl ``` --- Let's make sure this isn't broken by trying to apply this to something that's actually true: ``` 2-map : ℕ → Type 2-map 2 = ⊤ 2-map 2 = ⊥ 2-map else = ⊤ -- 2≢2 : 2 ≢ 2 -- 2≢2 p = transport (λ i → 2-map (p i)) tt ``` I commented the lines out because they don't compile, but if you tried to compile it, it would fail with: ```text ⊤ !=< ⊥ when checking that the expression transport (λ i → 2-map (p i)) tt has type ⊥ ``` That's because with identical terms, you can't simultaneously assign them to different values, or else it would not be a proper function.