added mention of Sigma to Quantifiers

This commit is contained in:
wadler 2018-03-18 13:09:38 -03:00
parent 8b7519220f
commit 63f65333e3
2 changed files with 77 additions and 13 deletions

View file

@ -91,6 +91,8 @@ left-hand side we refer to it as a *destructor*. We also refer
to `proj₁` and `proj₂` as destructors, since they play a similar role.
Other terminology refers to constructor as *introducing* a conjunction,
and to a destructor as *eliminating* a conjunction.
Indeed, `proj₁` and `proj₂` are sometimes given the names
`×-elim₁` and `×-elim₂`.
Applying each destructor and reassembling the results with the
constructor is the identity over products.

View file

@ -61,21 +61,25 @@ is a term of type `A` then we may conclude that `B M` holds.
\end{code}
As with `→-elim`, the rule corresponds to function application.
Ordinary function types arise as the special case of dependent
function types where the range does not depend on a variable drawn
from the domain. When an ordinary function is viewed as evidence of
implication, both its domain and range are viewed as types of
evidence, whereas when a dependent function is viewed as evidence of a
universal, its domain is viewed as a data type and its range is viewed
as a type of evidence. This is just a matter of interpretation, since
in Agda data types and types of evidence are indistinguishable.
Function types arise as a special case of dependent function types,
where the range does not depend on a variable drawn from the domain.
When a function is viewed as evidence of implication, both its
argument and result are viewed as evidence, whereas when a dependent
function is viewed as evidence of a universal, its argument is viewed
as an element of a data type and its result is viewed as evidence of
a proposition that depends on the argument. This difference is largely
a matter of interpretation, since in Agda data types and types of
evidence are indistinguishable.
Dependent function types are sometimes referred to as dependent products,
because if `A` is a finite type with values `{ x₁ , ⋯ , xᵢ }`, and if
each of the types `B x₁ , ⋯ B xᵢ` has `m₁ , ⋯ , mᵢ` distinct members,
then `∀ (x : A) → B x` has `m₁ ×× mᵢ` members. Because of the
association of `Π` with products, sometimes the notation `∀ (x : A) → B x`
is replaced by a notation such as `Π[ x ∈ A ] (B x)`.
then `∀ (x : A) → B x` has `m₁ ×× mᵢ` members. Because of this
association, sometimes the notation `∀ (x : A) → B x`
is replaced by a notation such as `Π[ x ∈ A ] (B x)`,
where `Π` stands for product. However, we will stick with the name
dependent function, because (as we will see) dependent product is ambiguous.
### Exercise (`∀-distrib-×`)
@ -116,6 +120,26 @@ Evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)` holds is of the form
`(M , N)` where `M` is a term of type `A`, and `N` is evidence
that `B M` holds.
Equivalently, we could also declare existentials as a record type.
\begin{code}
record ∃′ {A : Set} (B : A → Set) : Set where
field
proj₁ : A
proj₂ : B proj₁
\end{code}
Here record construction
record
{ proj₁ = M
; proj₂ = N
}
corresponds to the term
( M , N )
where `M` is a term of type `A` and `N` is a term of type `B M`.
Given evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)` holds, and
given evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B x → C` holds, where `C` does
not contain `x` as a free variable, we may conclude that `C` holds.
@ -131,11 +155,47 @@ instantiate that proof that `∀ (x : A) → B x → C` to any value
`M` of type `A` and any `N` of type `B M`, and exactly such values
are provided by the evidence for `∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)`.
Products arise a special case of existentials, where the second
component does not depend on a variable drawn from the first
component. When a product is viewed as evidence of a conjunction,
both of its components are viewed as evidence, whereas when viewed as
evidence of an existential, the first component is viewed as an
element of a datatype and the second component is viewed as evidence
of a proposition that depends on the first component. This difference
is largely a matter of interpretation, since in Agda data types and
types of evidence are indistinguishable.
Existentials are sometimes referred to as dependent sums,
because if `A` is a finite type with values `{ x₁ , ⋯ , xᵢ }`, and if
each of the types `B x₁ , ⋯ B xᵢ` has `m₁ , ⋯ , mᵢ` distinct members,
then `∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)` has `m₁ + ⋯ + mᵢ` members. Because of this
association, sometimes the notation `∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)`
is replaced by a notation such as `Σ[ x ∈ A ] (B x)`,
where `Σ` stands for sum.
Existentials are sometimes referred to as dependent products, since
products arise as a special case. However, that choice of names is
doubly confusing, because universals also have
a claim to the name dependent product, and because existentials
have a claim to the name dependent sum.
Agda makes it possible to define our own syntactic abbreviations.
\begin{code}
syntax ∃ (λ x → B) = ∃[ x ] B
∃-syntax = ∃
syntax ∃-syntax (λ x → B) = ∃[ x ] B
\end{code}
This allows us to write `∃[ x ] (B x)` in place of `∃ (λ x → B x)`.
We could also define a syntax that makes the argument explicit.
\begin{code}
Σ-syntax = ∃
syntax Σ-syntax {A} (λ x → B) = Σ[ x ∈ A ] B
\end{code}
Both forms of syntax are provided by the Agda standard library.
We will usually use the first, as it is more compact.
As an example, recall the definitions of `even` and `odd` from
Chapter [Relations](Relations).
@ -277,6 +337,8 @@ a contradiction.
The two inverse proofs are straightforward, where one direction
requires extensionality.
### Exercise (`∃-distrib-⊎`)
Show that universals distribute over conjunction.
@ -294,7 +356,7 @@ Show that an existential of conjunctions implies a conjunction of existentials.
\end{code}
Does the converse hold? If so, prove; if not, explain why.
### Exercise (`∃¬-Implies-¬∀)
### Exercise (`∃¬-Implies-¬∀`)
Show `∃[ x ] ¬ B x → ¬ (∀ x → B x)`.