added StlcPropOld
This commit is contained in:
parent
c1c997589d
commit
66132f1dbb
3 changed files with 769 additions and 3 deletions
|
@ -6,7 +6,7 @@ permalink : /StlcOld
|
|||
|
||||
<div class="foldable">
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
open import Maps using (Id; id; _≟_; PartialMap; module PartialMap)
|
||||
open import MapsOld using (Id; id; _≟_; PartialMap; module PartialMap)
|
||||
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
|
||||
open import Data.Maybe using (Maybe; just; nothing)
|
||||
open import Data.Nat using (ℕ; suc; zero; _+_)
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -13,8 +13,8 @@ open import Data.Product using (∃; ∃₂; _,_; ,_)
|
|||
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
|
||||
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_; Dec; yes; no)
|
||||
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; _≢_; refl)
|
||||
open import Maps
|
||||
open import Stlc
|
||||
open import MapsOld
|
||||
open import StlcOld
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
|
|
766
src/StlcPropOld.lagda
Normal file
766
src/StlcPropOld.lagda
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,766 @@
|
|||
---
|
||||
title : "StlcProp: Properties of STLC"
|
||||
layout : page
|
||||
permalink : /StlcProp
|
||||
---
|
||||
|
||||
<div class="foldable">
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
open import Function using (_∘_)
|
||||
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
|
||||
open import Data.Maybe using (Maybe; just; nothing)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (∃; ∃₂; _,_; ,_)
|
||||
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
|
||||
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_; Dec; yes; no)
|
||||
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; _≢_; refl)
|
||||
open import MapsOld
|
||||
open import StlcOld
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
In this chapter, we develop the fundamental theory of the Simply
|
||||
Typed Lambda Calculus---in particular, the type safety
|
||||
theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Canonical Forms
|
||||
|
||||
As we saw for the simple calculus in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }})
|
||||
chapter, the first step in establishing basic properties of reduction and types
|
||||
is to identify the possible _canonical forms_ (i.e., well-typed closed values)
|
||||
belonging to each type. For $$bool$$, these are the boolean values $$true$$ and
|
||||
$$false$$. For arrow types, the canonical forms are lambda-abstractions.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
CanonicalForms : Term → Type → Set
|
||||
CanonicalForms t bool = t ≡ true ⊎ t ≡ false
|
||||
CanonicalForms t (A ⇒ B) = ∃₂ λ x t′ → t ≡ abs x A t′
|
||||
|
||||
canonicalForms : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t ∶ A → Value t → CanonicalForms t A
|
||||
canonicalForms (abs t′) abs = _ , _ , refl
|
||||
canonicalForms true true = inj₁ refl
|
||||
canonicalForms false false = inj₂ refl
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
## Progress
|
||||
|
||||
As before, the _progress_ theorem tells us that closed, well-typed
|
||||
terms are not stuck: either a well-typed term is a value, or it
|
||||
can take a reduction step. The proof is a relatively
|
||||
straightforward extension of the progress proof we saw in the
|
||||
[Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }}) chapter. We'll give the proof in English
|
||||
first, then the formal version.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
progress : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t ∶ A → Value t ⊎ ∃ λ t′ → t ==> t′
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : A$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- The last rule of the derivation cannot be `var`,
|
||||
since a variable is never well typed in an empty context.
|
||||
|
||||
- The `true`, `false`, and `abs` cases are trivial, since in
|
||||
each of these cases we can see by inspecting the rule that $$t$$
|
||||
is a value.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `app`, then $$t$$ has the
|
||||
form $$t_1\;t_2$$ for som e$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$, where we know that
|
||||
$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ are also well typed in the empty context; in particular,
|
||||
there exists a type $$B$$ such that $$\vdash t_1 : A\to T$$ and
|
||||
$$\vdash t_2 : B$$. By the induction hypothesis, either $$t_1$$ is a
|
||||
value or it can take a reduction step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then consider $$t_2$$, which by the other
|
||||
induction hypothesis must also either be a value or take a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- Suppose $$t_2$$ is a value. Since $$t_1$$ is a value with an
|
||||
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence $$t_1\;t_2$$
|
||||
can take a step by `red`.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t_2$$ can take a step, and hence so can $$t_1\;t_2$$
|
||||
by `app2`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ can take a step, then so can $$t_1 t_2$$ by `app1`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `if`, then $$t = \text{if }t_1
|
||||
\text{ then }t_2\text{ else }t_3$$, where $$t_1$$ has type $$bool$$. By
|
||||
the IH, $$t_1$$ either is a value or takes a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then since it has type $$bool$$ it must be
|
||||
either $$true$$ or $$false$$. If it is $$true$$, then $$t$$ steps
|
||||
to $$t_2$$; otherwise it steps to $$t_3$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t_1$$ takes a step, and therefore so does $$t$$ (by `if`).
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
progress (var x ())
|
||||
progress true = inj₁ true
|
||||
progress false = inj₁ false
|
||||
progress (abs t∶A) = inj₁ abs
|
||||
progress (app t₁∶A⇒B t₂∶B)
|
||||
with progress t₁∶A⇒B
|
||||
... | inj₂ (_ , t₁⇒t₁′) = inj₂ (_ , app1 t₁⇒t₁′)
|
||||
... | inj₁ v₁
|
||||
with progress t₂∶B
|
||||
... | inj₂ (_ , t₂⇒t₂′) = inj₂ (_ , app2 v₁ t₂⇒t₂′)
|
||||
... | inj₁ v₂
|
||||
with canonicalForms t₁∶A⇒B v₁
|
||||
... | (_ , _ , refl) = inj₂ (_ , red v₂)
|
||||
progress (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶A else t₃∶A)
|
||||
with progress t₁∶bool
|
||||
... | inj₂ (_ , t₁⇒t₁′) = inj₂ (_ , if t₁⇒t₁′)
|
||||
... | inj₁ v₁
|
||||
with canonicalForms t₁∶bool v₁
|
||||
... | inj₁ refl = inj₂ (_ , iftrue)
|
||||
... | inj₂ refl = inj₂ (_ , iffalse)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 3 stars, optional (progress_from_term_ind)
|
||||
Show that progress can also be proved by induction on terms
|
||||
instead of induction on typing derivations.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
progress′ : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t ∶ A → Value t ⊎ ∃ λ t′ → t ==> t′
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
## Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
The other half of the type soundness property is the preservation
|
||||
of types during reduction. For this, we need to develop some
|
||||
technical machinery for reasoning about variables and
|
||||
substitution. Working from top to bottom (from the high-level
|
||||
property we are actually interested in to the lowest-level
|
||||
technical lemmas that are needed by various cases of the more
|
||||
interesting proofs), the story goes like this:
|
||||
|
||||
- The _preservation theorem_ is proved by induction on a typing
|
||||
derivation, pretty much as we did in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }})
|
||||
chapter. The one case that is significantly different is the one for the
|
||||
$$red$$ rule, whose definition uses the substitution operation. To see that
|
||||
this step preserves typing, we need to know that the substitution itself
|
||||
does. So we prove a...
|
||||
|
||||
- _substitution lemma_, stating that substituting a (closed)
|
||||
term $$s$$ for a variable $$x$$ in a term $$t$$ preserves the type
|
||||
of $$t$$. The proof goes by induction on the form of $$t$$ and
|
||||
requires looking at all the different cases in the definition
|
||||
of substitition. This time, the tricky cases are the ones for
|
||||
variables and for function abstractions. In both cases, we
|
||||
discover that we need to take a term $$s$$ that has been shown
|
||||
to be well-typed in some context $$\Gamma$$ and consider the same
|
||||
term $$s$$ in a slightly different context $$\Gamma'$$. For this
|
||||
we prove a...
|
||||
|
||||
- _context invariance_ lemma, showing that typing is preserved
|
||||
under "inessential changes" to the context $$\Gamma$$---in
|
||||
particular, changes that do not affect any of the free
|
||||
variables of the term. And finally, for this, we need a
|
||||
careful definition of...
|
||||
|
||||
- the _free variables_ of a term---i.e., those variables
|
||||
mentioned in a term and not in the scope of an enclosing
|
||||
function abstraction binding a variable of the same name.
|
||||
|
||||
To make Agda happy, we need to formalize the story in the opposite
|
||||
order...
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
### Free Occurrences
|
||||
|
||||
A variable $$x$$ _appears free in_ a term _t_ if $$t$$ contains some
|
||||
occurrence of $$x$$ that is not under an abstraction labeled $$x$$.
|
||||
For example:
|
||||
|
||||
- $$y$$ appears free, but $$x$$ does not, in $$\lambda x : A\to B. x\;y$$
|
||||
- both $$x$$ and $$y$$ appear free in $$(\lambda x:A\to B. x\;y) x$$
|
||||
- no variables appear free in $$\lambda x:A\to B. \lambda y:A. x\;y$$
|
||||
|
||||
Formally:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
data _FreeIn_ (x : Id) : Term → Set where
|
||||
var : x FreeIn var x
|
||||
abs : ∀ {y A t} → y ≢ x → x FreeIn t → x FreeIn abs y A t
|
||||
app1 : ∀ {t₁ t₂} → x FreeIn t₁ → x FreeIn app t₁ t₂
|
||||
app2 : ∀ {t₁ t₂} → x FreeIn t₂ → x FreeIn app t₁ t₂
|
||||
if1 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₁ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
|
||||
if2 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₂ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
|
||||
if3 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₃ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
A term in which no variables appear free is said to be _closed_.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
Closed : Term → Set
|
||||
Closed t = ∀ {x} → ¬ (x FreeIn t)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 1 star (free-in)
|
||||
If the definition of `_FreeIn_` is not crystal clear to
|
||||
you, it is a good idea to take a piece of paper and write out the
|
||||
rules in informal inference-rule notation. (Although it is a
|
||||
rather low-level, technical definition, understanding it is
|
||||
crucial to understanding substitution and its properties, which
|
||||
are really the crux of the lambda-calculus.)
|
||||
|
||||
### Substitution
|
||||
To prove that substitution preserves typing, we first need a
|
||||
technical lemma connecting free variables and typing contexts: If
|
||||
a variable $$x$$ appears free in a term $$t$$, and if we know $$t$$ is
|
||||
well typed in context $$\Gamma$$, then it must be the case that
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
freeInCtxt : ∀ {x t A Γ} → x FreeIn t → Γ ⊢ t ∶ A → ∃ λ B → Γ x ≡ just B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on the proof that $$x$$ appears
|
||||
free in $$t$$, that, for all contexts $$\Gamma$$, if $$t$$ is well
|
||||
typed under $$\Gamma$$, then $$\Gamma$$ assigns some type to $$x$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `var`, then $$t = x$$, and from
|
||||
the assumption that $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$ we have
|
||||
immediately that $$\Gamma$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `app1`, then $$t = t_1\;t_2$$ and $$x$$
|
||||
appears free in $$t_1$$. Since $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$,
|
||||
we can see from the typing rules that $$t_1$$ must also be, and
|
||||
the IH then tells us that $$\Gamma$$ assigns $$x$$ a type.
|
||||
|
||||
- Almost all the other cases are similar: $$x$$ appears free in a
|
||||
subterm of $$t$$, and since $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$, we
|
||||
know the subterm of $$t$$ in which $$x$$ appears is well typed
|
||||
under $$\Gamma$$ as well, and the IH gives us exactly the
|
||||
conclusion we want.
|
||||
|
||||
- The only remaining case is `abs`. In this case $$t =
|
||||
\lambda y:A.t'$$, and $$x$$ appears free in $$t'$$; we also know that
|
||||
$$x$$ is different from $$y$$. The difference from the previous
|
||||
cases is that whereas $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$, its
|
||||
body $$t'$$ is well typed under $$(\Gamma, y:A)$$, so the IH
|
||||
allows us to conclude that $$x$$ is assigned some type by the
|
||||
extended context $$(\Gamma, y:A)$$. To conclude that $$\Gamma$$
|
||||
assigns a type to $$x$$, we appeal the decidable equality for names
|
||||
`_≟_`, noting that $$x$$ and $$y$$ are different variables.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
freeInCtxt var (var _ x∶A) = (_ , x∶A)
|
||||
freeInCtxt (app1 x∈t₁) (app t₁∶A _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₁ t₁∶A
|
||||
freeInCtxt (app2 x∈t₂) (app _ t₂∶A) = freeInCtxt x∈t₂ t₂∶A
|
||||
freeInCtxt (if1 x∈t₁) (if t₁∶A then _ else _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₁ t₁∶A
|
||||
freeInCtxt (if2 x∈t₂) (if _ then t₂∶A else _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₂ t₂∶A
|
||||
freeInCtxt (if3 x∈t₃) (if _ then _ else t₃∶A) = freeInCtxt x∈t₃ t₃∶A
|
||||
freeInCtxt {x} (abs {y} y≠x x∈t) (abs t∶B)
|
||||
with freeInCtxt x∈t t∶B
|
||||
... | x∶A
|
||||
with y ≟ x
|
||||
... | yes y=x = ⊥-elim (y≠x y=x)
|
||||
... | no _ = x∶A
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
Next, we'll need the fact that any term $$t$$ which is well typed in
|
||||
the empty context is closed (it has no free variables).
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (∅⊢-closed)
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
∅⊢-closed : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t ∶ A → Closed t
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
<div class="hidden">
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t ∶ A → Closed t
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (var x ())
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (app t₁∶A⇒B t₂∶A) (app1 x∈t₁) = ∅⊢-closed′ t₁∶A⇒B x∈t₁
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (app t₁∶A⇒B t₂∶A) (app2 x∈t₂) = ∅⊢-closed′ t₂∶A x∈t₂
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ true ()
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ false ()
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶A else t₃∶A) (if1 x∈t₁) = ∅⊢-closed′ t₁∶bool x∈t₁
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶A else t₃∶A) (if2 x∈t₂) = ∅⊢-closed′ t₂∶A x∈t₂
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶A else t₃∶A) (if3 x∈t₃) = ∅⊢-closed′ t₃∶A x∈t₃
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (abs {x = x} t′∶A) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t′) with freeInCtxt y∈t′ t′∶A
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (abs {x = x} t′∶A) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t′) | A , y∶A with x ≟ y
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (abs {x = x} t′∶A) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t′) | A , y∶A | yes x=y = x≠y x=y
|
||||
∅⊢-closed′ (abs {x = x} t′∶A) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t′) | A , () | no _
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
Sometimes, when we have a proof $$\Gamma\vdash t : A$$, we will need to
|
||||
replace $$\Gamma$$ by a different context $$\Gamma'$$. When is it safe
|
||||
to do this? Intuitively, it must at least be the case that
|
||||
$$\Gamma'$$ assigns the same types as $$\Gamma$$ to all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in $$t$$. In fact, this is the only condition that
|
||||
is needed.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
replaceCtxt : ∀ {Γ Γ′ t A}
|
||||
→ (∀ {x} → x FreeIn t → Γ x ≡ Γ′ x)
|
||||
→ Γ ⊢ t ∶ A
|
||||
→ Γ′ ⊢ t ∶ A
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of
|
||||
$$\Gamma \vdash t \in T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was `var`, then $$t = x$$
|
||||
and $$\Gamma x = T$$. By assumption, $$\Gamma' x = T$$ as well, and
|
||||
hence $$\Gamma' \vdash t : T$$ by `var`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule was `abs`, then $$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, with
|
||||
$$T = A\to B$$ and $$\Gamma, y : A \vdash t' : B$$. The
|
||||
induction hypothesis is that, for any context $$\Gamma''$$, if
|
||||
$$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma''$$ assign the same types to all the
|
||||
free variables in $$t'$$, then $$t'$$ has type $$B$$ under
|
||||
$$\Gamma''$$. Let $$\Gamma'$$ be a context which agrees with
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t$$; we must show
|
||||
$$\Gamma' \vdash \lambda y:A. t' : A\to B$$.
|
||||
|
||||
By $$abs$$, it suffices to show that $$\Gamma', y:A \vdash t' : t'$$.
|
||||
By the IH (setting $$\Gamma'' = \Gamma', y:A$$), it suffices to show
|
||||
that $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$ agree on all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in $$t'$$.
|
||||
|
||||
Any variable occurring free in $$t'$$ must be either $$y$$ or
|
||||
some other variable. $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$
|
||||
clearly agree on $$y$$. Otherwise, note that any variable other
|
||||
than $$y$$ that occurs free in $$t'$$ also occurs free in
|
||||
$$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, and by assumption $$\Gamma$$ and
|
||||
$$\Gamma'$$ agree on all such variables; hence so do $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and
|
||||
$$\Gamma', y:A$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule was `app`, then $$t = t_1\;t_2$$, with
|
||||
$$\Gamma \vdash t_1:A\to T$$ and $$\Gamma \vdash t_2:A$$.
|
||||
One induction hypothesis states that for all contexts $$\Gamma'$$,
|
||||
if $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with $$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t_1$$,
|
||||
then $$t_1$$ has type $$A\to T$$ under $$\Gamma'$$; there is a similar IH
|
||||
for $$t_2$$. We must show that $$t_1\;t_2$$ also has type $$T$$ under
|
||||
$$\Gamma'$$, given the assumption that $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$ on all the free variables in $$t_1\;t_2$$. By `app`, it
|
||||
suffices to show that $$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ each have the same type
|
||||
under $$\Gamma'$$ as under $$\Gamma$$. But all free variables in
|
||||
$$t_1$$ are also free in $$t_1\;t_2$$, and similarly for $$t_2$$;
|
||||
hence the desired result follows from the induction hypotheses.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
replaceCtxt f (var x x∶A) rewrite f var = var x x∶A
|
||||
replaceCtxt f (app t₁∶A⇒B t₂∶A)
|
||||
= app (replaceCtxt (f ∘ app1) t₁∶A⇒B) (replaceCtxt (f ∘ app2) t₂∶A)
|
||||
replaceCtxt {Γ} {Γ′} f (abs {.Γ} {x} {A} {B} {t′} t′∶B)
|
||||
= abs (replaceCtxt f′ t′∶B)
|
||||
where
|
||||
f′ : ∀ {y} → y FreeIn t′ → (Γ , x ∶ A) y ≡ (Γ′ , x ∶ A) y
|
||||
f′ {y} y∈t′ with x ≟ y
|
||||
... | yes _ = refl
|
||||
... | no x≠y = f (abs x≠y y∈t′)
|
||||
replaceCtxt _ true = true
|
||||
replaceCtxt _ false = false
|
||||
replaceCtxt f (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶A else t₃∶A)
|
||||
= if replaceCtxt (f ∘ if1) t₁∶bool
|
||||
then replaceCtxt (f ∘ if2) t₂∶A
|
||||
else replaceCtxt (f ∘ if3) t₃∶A
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
Now we come to the conceptual heart of the proof that reduction
|
||||
preserves types---namely, the observation that _substitution_
|
||||
preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
Formally, the so-called _Substitution Lemma_ says this: Suppose we
|
||||
have a term $$t$$ with a free variable $$x$$, and suppose we've been
|
||||
able to assign a type $$T$$ to $$t$$ under the assumption that $$x$$ has
|
||||
some type $$U$$. Also, suppose that we have some other term $$v$$ and
|
||||
that we've shown that $$v$$ has type $$U$$. Then, since $$v$$ satisfies
|
||||
the assumption we made about $$x$$ when typing $$t$$, we should be
|
||||
able to substitute $$v$$ for each of the occurrences of $$x$$ in $$t$$
|
||||
and obtain a new term that still has type $$T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
_Lemma_: If $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$ and $$\vdash v : U$$, then
|
||||
$$\Gamma \vdash [x:=v]t : T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ : ∀ {Γ x A t v B}
|
||||
→ ∅ ⊢ v ∶ A
|
||||
→ Γ , x ∶ A ⊢ t ∶ B
|
||||
→ Γ , x ∶ A ⊢ [ x := v ] t ∶ B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
One technical subtlety in the statement of the lemma is that
|
||||
we assign $$v$$ the type $$U$$ in the _empty_ context---in other
|
||||
words, we assume $$v$$ is closed. This assumption considerably
|
||||
simplifies the $$abs$$ case of the proof (compared to assuming
|
||||
$$\Gamma \vdash v : U$$, which would be the other reasonable assumption
|
||||
at this point) because the context invariance lemma then tells us
|
||||
that $$v$$ has type $$U$$ in any context at all---we don't have to
|
||||
worry about free variables in $$v$$ clashing with the variable being
|
||||
introduced into the context by $$abs$$.
|
||||
|
||||
The substitution lemma can be viewed as a kind of "commutation"
|
||||
property. Intuitively, it says that substitution and typing can
|
||||
be done in either order: we can either assign types to the terms
|
||||
$$t$$ and $$v$$ separately (under suitable contexts) and then combine
|
||||
them using substitution, or we can substitute first and then
|
||||
assign a type to $$ $$x:=v$$ t $$---the result is the same either
|
||||
way.
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on $$t$$, that for all $$T$$ and
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$, if $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$ and $$\vdash v : U$$, then $$\Gamma
|
||||
\vdash $$x:=v$$t : T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ is a variable there are two cases to consider,
|
||||
depending on whether $$t$$ is $$x$$ or some other variable.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t = x$$, then from the fact that $$\Gamma, x:U \vdash x :
|
||||
T$$ we conclude that $$U = T$$. We must show that $$[x:=v]x =
|
||||
v$$ has type $$T$$ under $$\Gamma$$, given the assumption that
|
||||
$$v$$ has type $$U = T$$ under the empty context. This
|
||||
follows from context invariance: if a closed term has type
|
||||
$$T$$ in the empty context, it has that type in any context.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ is some variable $$y$$ that is not equal to $$x$$, then
|
||||
we need only note that $$y$$ has the same type under $$\Gamma,
|
||||
x:U$$ as under $$\Gamma$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ is an abstraction $$\lambda y:t_{11}. t_{12}$$, then the IH tells us,
|
||||
for all $$\Gamma'$$ and $$T'$$, that if $$\Gamma',x:U \vdash t_{12}:T'$$
|
||||
and $$\vdash v:U$$, then $$\Gamma' \vdash [x:=v]t_{12}:T'$$.
|
||||
|
||||
The substitution in the conclusion behaves differently
|
||||
depending on whether $$x$$ and $$y$$ are the same variable.
|
||||
|
||||
First, suppose $$x = y$$. Then, by the definition of
|
||||
substitution, $$[x:=v]t = t$$, so we just need to show $$\Gamma \vdash
|
||||
t : T$$. But we know $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$, and, since $$y$$
|
||||
does not appear free in $$\lambda y:t_{11}. t_{12}$$, the context invariance
|
||||
lemma yields $$\Gamma \vdash t : T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
Second, suppose $$x \neq y$$. We know $$\Gamma,x:U,y:t_{11} \vdash
|
||||
t_{12}:t_{12}$$ by inversion of the typing relation, from which
|
||||
$$\Gamma,y:t_{11},x:U \vdash t_{12}:t_{12}$$ follows by the context invariance
|
||||
lemma, so the IH applies, giving us $$\Gamma,y:t_{11} \vdash
|
||||
[x:=v]t_{12}:t_{12}$$. By $$abs$$, $$\Gamma \vdash \lambda y:t_{11}.
|
||||
[x:=v]t_{12}:t_{11}\to t_{12}$$, and by the definition of substitution (noting
|
||||
that $$x \neq y$$), $$\Gamma \vdash \lambda y:t_{11}. [x:=v]t_{12}:t_{11}\to
|
||||
t_{12}$$ as required.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ is an application $$t_1 t_2$$, the result follows
|
||||
straightforwardly from the definition of substitution and the
|
||||
induction hypotheses.
|
||||
|
||||
- The remaining cases are similar to the application case.
|
||||
|
||||
One more technical note: This proof is a rare case where an
|
||||
induction on terms, rather than typing derivations, yields a
|
||||
simpler argument. The reason for this is that the assumption
|
||||
$$update Gamma x U \vdash t : T$$ is not completely generic, in the
|
||||
sense that one of the "slots" in the typing relation---namely the
|
||||
context---is not just a variable, and this means that Agda's
|
||||
native induction tactic does not give us the induction hypothesis
|
||||
that we want. It is possible to work around this, but the needed
|
||||
generalization is a little tricky. The term $$t$$, on the other
|
||||
hand, _is_ completely generic.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ {Γ} {x} v∶A (var y y∈Γ) with x ≟ y
|
||||
... | yes x=y = {!!}
|
||||
... | no x≠y = {!!}
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A (abs t′∶B) = {!!}
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A (app t₁∶A⇒B t₂∶A) =
|
||||
app ([:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A t₁∶A⇒B) ([:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A t₂∶A)
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A true = true
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A false = false
|
||||
[:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A (if t₁∶bool then t₂∶B else t₃∶B) =
|
||||
if [:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A t₁∶bool
|
||||
then [:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A t₂∶B
|
||||
else [:=]-preserves-⊢ v∶A t₃∶B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
### Main Theorem
|
||||
|
||||
We now have the tools we need to prove preservation: if a closed
|
||||
term $$t$$ has type $$T$$ and takes a step to $$t'$$, then $$t'$$
|
||||
is also a closed term with type $$T$$. In other words, the small-step
|
||||
reduction relation preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
Theorem preservation : forall t t' T,
|
||||
empty \vdash t : T →
|
||||
t ==> t' →
|
||||
empty \vdash t' : T.
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : T$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- We can immediately rule out $$var$$, $$abs$$, $$T_True$$, and
|
||||
$$T_False$$ as the final rules in the derivation, since in each of
|
||||
these cases $$t$$ cannot take a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$app$$, then $$t = t_1
|
||||
t_2$$. There are three cases to consider, one for each rule that
|
||||
could have been used to show that $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step to $$t'$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sapp1$$, with $$t_1$$ stepping to
|
||||
$$t_1'$$, then by the IH $$t_1'$$ has the same type as $$t_1$$, and
|
||||
hence $$t_1' t_2$$ has the same type as $$t_1 t_2$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- The $$Sapp2$$ case is similar.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sred$$, then $$t_1 =
|
||||
\lambda x:t_{11}.t_{12}$$ and $$t_1 t_2$$ steps to $$$$x:=t_2$$t_{12}$$; the
|
||||
desired result now follows from the fact that substitution
|
||||
preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$if$$, then $$t = if t_1
|
||||
then t_2 else t_3$$, and there are again three cases depending on
|
||||
how $$t$$ steps.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ steps to $$t_2$$ or $$t_3$$, the result is immediate, since
|
||||
$$t_2$$ and $$t_3$$ have the same type as $$t$$.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t$$ steps by $$Sif$$, and the desired conclusion
|
||||
follows directly from the induction hypothesis.
|
||||
|
||||
Proof with eauto.
|
||||
remember (@empty ty) as Gamma.
|
||||
intros t t' T HT. generalize dependent t'.
|
||||
induction HT;
|
||||
intros t' HE; subst Gamma; subst;
|
||||
try solve $$inversion HE; subst; auto$$.
|
||||
- (* app
|
||||
inversion HE; subst...
|
||||
(* Most of the cases are immediate by induction,
|
||||
and $$eauto$$ takes care of them
|
||||
+ (* Sred
|
||||
apply substitution_preserves_typing with t_{11}...
|
||||
inversion HT_1...
|
||||
Qed.
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, recommended (subject_expansion_stlc)
|
||||
An exercise in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }}) chapter asked about the
|
||||
subject expansion property for the simple language of arithmetic and boolean
|
||||
expressions. Does this property hold for STLC? That is, is it always the case
|
||||
that, if $$t ==> t'$$ and $$has_type t' T$$, then $$empty \vdash t : T$$? If
|
||||
so, prove it. If not, give a counter-example not involving conditionals.
|
||||
|
||||
(* FILL IN HERE
|
||||
|
||||
## Type Soundness
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (type_soundness)
|
||||
Put progress and preservation together and show that a well-typed
|
||||
term can _never_ reach a stuck state.
|
||||
|
||||
Definition stuck (t:tm) : Prop :=
|
||||
(normal_form step) t /\ ~ value t.
|
||||
|
||||
Corollary soundness : forall t t' T,
|
||||
empty \vdash t : T →
|
||||
t ==>* t' →
|
||||
~(stuck t').
|
||||
Proof.
|
||||
intros t t' T Hhas_type Hmulti. unfold stuck.
|
||||
intros $$Hnf Hnot_val$$. unfold normal_form in Hnf.
|
||||
induction Hmulti.
|
||||
(* FILL IN HERE Admitted.
|
||||
(** $$$$
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Uniqueness of Types
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 3 stars (types_unique)
|
||||
Another nice property of the STLC is that types are unique: a
|
||||
given term (in a given context) has at most one type.
|
||||
Formalize this statement and prove it.
|
||||
|
||||
(* FILL IN HERE
|
||||
(** $$$$
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Additional Exercises
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 1 star (progress_preservation_statement)
|
||||
Without peeking at their statements above, write down the progress
|
||||
and preservation theorems for the simply typed lambda-calculus.
|
||||
$$$$
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation1)
|
||||
Suppose we add a new term $$zap$$ with the following reduction rule
|
||||
|
||||
--------- (ST_Zap)
|
||||
t ==> zap
|
||||
|
||||
and the following typing rule:
|
||||
|
||||
---------------- (T_Zap)
|
||||
Gamma \vdash zap : T
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of these rules? For each property, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation2)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add a new term $$foo$$ with the following
|
||||
reduction rules:
|
||||
|
||||
----------------- (ST_Foo1)
|
||||
(\lambda x:A. x) ==> foo
|
||||
|
||||
------------ (ST_Foo2)
|
||||
foo ==> true
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation3)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we remove the rule $$Sapp1$$ from the $$step$$
|
||||
relation. Which of the following properties of the STLC remain
|
||||
true in the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation4)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the
|
||||
reduction relation:
|
||||
|
||||
---------------------------------- (ST_FunnyIfTrue)
|
||||
(if true then t_1 else t_2) ==> true
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation5)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing
|
||||
relation:
|
||||
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_1 : bool→bool→bool
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_2 : bool
|
||||
------------------------------ (T_FunnyApp)
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_1 t_2 : bool
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation6)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing
|
||||
relation:
|
||||
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_1 : bool
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_2 : bool
|
||||
--------------------- (T_FunnyApp')
|
||||
Gamma \vdash t_1 t_2 : bool
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation7)
|
||||
Suppose we add the following new rule to the typing relation
|
||||
of the STLC:
|
||||
|
||||
------------------- (T_FunnyAbs)
|
||||
\vdash \lambda x:bool.t : bool
|
||||
|
||||
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
|
||||
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise: STLC with Arithmetic
|
||||
|
||||
To see how the STLC might function as the core of a real
|
||||
programming language, let's extend it with a concrete base
|
||||
type of numbers and some constants and primitive
|
||||
operators.
|
||||
|
||||
To types, we add a base type of natural numbers (and remove
|
||||
booleans, for brevity).
|
||||
|
||||
Inductive ty : Type :=
|
||||
| TArrow : ty → ty → ty
|
||||
| TNat : ty.
|
||||
|
||||
To terms, we add natural number constants, along with
|
||||
successor, predecessor, multiplication, and zero-testing.
|
||||
|
||||
Inductive tm : Type :=
|
||||
| tvar : id → tm
|
||||
| tapp : tm → tm → tm
|
||||
| tabs : id → ty → tm → tm
|
||||
| tnat : nat → tm
|
||||
| tsucc : tm → tm
|
||||
| tpred : tm → tm
|
||||
| tmult : tm → tm → tm
|
||||
| tif0 : tm → tm → tm → tm.
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 4 stars (stlc_arith)
|
||||
Finish formalizing the definition and properties of the STLC extended
|
||||
with arithmetic. Specifically:
|
||||
|
||||
- Copy the whole development of STLC that we went through above (from
|
||||
the definition of values through the Type Soundness theorem), and
|
||||
paste it into the file at this point.
|
||||
|
||||
- Extend the definitions of the $$subst$$ operation and the $$step$$
|
||||
relation to include appropriate clauses for the arithmetic operators.
|
||||
|
||||
- Extend the proofs of all the properties (up to $$soundness$$) of
|
||||
the original STLC to deal with the new syntactic forms. Make
|
||||
sure Agda accepts the whole file.
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue