Moved the Agda Software Foundations files to their own repository.

This commit is contained in:
Pepijn Kokke 2017-03-10 11:42:57 +00:00
parent 9a9020cbaf
commit 6c6ebb0a0a
No known key found for this signature in database
GPG key ID: EF467CD387487CB8
8 changed files with 17702 additions and 0 deletions

145
Basics.lagda Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,145 @@
---
title : "Basics: Functional Programming in Agda"
layout : default
hide-implicit : false
extra-script : [agda-extra-script.html]
extra-style : [agda-extra-style.html]
---
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
module Basics where
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; refl)
\end{code}
</div>
# Basics: Functional Programming in Agda
The functional programming style brings programming closer to
simple, everyday mathematics: If a procedure or method has no side
effects, then (ignoring efficiency) all we need to understand
about it is how it maps inputs to outputs -- that is, we can think
of it as just a concrete method for computing a mathematical
function. This is one sense of the word "functional" in
"functional programming." The direct connection between programs
and simple mathematical objects supports both formal correctness
proofs and sound informal reasoning about program behavior.
The other sense in which functional programming is "functional" is
that it emphasizes the use of functions (or methods) as
*first-class* values -- i.e., values that can be passed as
arguments to other functions, returned as results, included in
data structures, etc. The recognition that functions can be
treated as data in this way enables a host of useful and powerful
idioms.
Other common features of functional languages include *algebraic
data types* and *pattern matching*, which make it easy to
construct and manipulate rich data structures, and sophisticated
*polymorphic type systems* supporting abstraction and code reuse.
Agda shares all of these features.
This chapter introduces the most essential elements of Agda.
## Enumerated Types
One unusual aspect of Agda is that its set of built-in
features is *extremely* small. For example, instead of providing
the usual palette of atomic data types (booleans, integers,
strings, etc.), Agda offers a powerful mechanism for defining new
data types from scratch, from which all these familiar types arise
as instances.
Naturally, the Agda distribution comes with an extensive standard
library providing definitions of booleans, numbers, and many
common data structures like lists and hash tables. But there is
nothing magic or primitive about these library definitions. To
illustrate this, we will explicitly recapitulate all the
definitions we need in this course, rather than just getting them
implicitly from the library.
To see how this definition mechanism works, let's start with a
very simple example.
### Days of the Week
The following declaration tells Agda that we are defining
a new set of data values -- a *type*.
\begin{code}
data Day : Set where
monday : Day
tuesday : Day
wednesday : Day
thursday : Day
friday : Day
saturday : Day
sunday : Day
\end{code}
The type is called `day`, and its members are `monday`,
`tuesday`, etc. The second and following lines of the definition
can be read "`monday` is a `day`, `tuesday` is a `day`, etc."
Having defined `day`, we can write functions that operate on
days.
\begin{code}
nextWeekday : Day -> Day
nextWeekday monday = tuesday
nextWeekday tuesday = wednesday
nextWeekday wednesday = thursday
nextWeekday thursday = friday
nextWeekday friday = monday
nextWeekday saturday = monday
nextWeekday sunday = monday
\end{code}
One thing to note is that the argument and return types of
this function are explicitly declared. Like most functional
programming languages, Agda can often figure out these types for
itself when they are not given explicitly -- i.e., it performs
*type inference* -- but we'll include them to make reading
easier.
Having defined a function, we should check that it works on
some examples. There are actually three different ways to do this
in Agda.
First, we can use the Emacs command `C-c C-n` to evaluate a
compound expression involving `nextWeekday`. For instance, `nextWeekday
friday` should evaluate to `monday`. If you have a computer handy, this
would be an excellent moment to fire up Agda and try this for yourself.
Load this file, `Basics.lagda`, load it using `C-c C-l`, submit the
above example to Agda, and observe the result.
Second, we can record what we *expect* the result to be in the
form of an Agda type:
\begin{code}
test_nextWeekday : nextWeekday (nextWeekday saturday) ≡ tuesday
\end{code}
This declaration does two things: it makes an assertion (that the second
weekday after `saturday` is `tuesday`), and it gives the assertion a name
that can be used to refer to it later.
Having made the assertion, we must also verify it. We do this by giving
a term of the above type:
\begin{code}
test_nextWeekday = refl
\end{code}
There is no essential difference between the definition for
`test_nextWeekday` here and the definition for `nextWeekday` above,
except for the new symbol for equality `≡` and the constructor `refl`.
The details of these are not important for now (we'll come back to them in
a bit), but essentially `refl` can be read as "The assertion we've made
can be proved by observing that both sides of the equality evaluate to the
same thing, after some simplification."
Third, we can ask Agda to *compile* some program involving our definition,
This facility is very interesting, since it gives us a way to construct
*fully certified* programs. We'll come back to this topic in later chapters.

457
Basics.md Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,457 @@
---
title : "Basics: Functional Programming in Agda"
layout : default
hide-implicit : false
extra-script : [agda-extra-script.html]
extra-style : [agda-extra-style.html]
---
<div class="hidden">
<!--{% raw %}--><pre class="Agda">
<a name="226" class="Keyword"
>module</a
><a name="232"
> </a
><a name="233" href="Basics.html#1" class="Module"
>Basics</a
><a name="239"
> </a
><a name="240" class="Keyword"
>where</a
><a name="245"
>
</a
><a name="249" class="Keyword"
>open</a
><a name="253"
> </a
><a name="254" class="Keyword"
>import</a
><a name="260"
> </a
><a name="261" href="https://agda.github.io/agda-stdlib/Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality.html#1" class="Module"
>Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality</a
><a name="298"
> </a
><a name="299" class="Keyword"
>using</a
><a name="304"
> </a
><a name="305" class="Symbol"
>(</a
><a name="306" href="Agda.Builtin.Equality.html#55" class="Datatype Operator"
>_&#8801;_</a
><a name="309" class="Symbol"
>;</a
><a name="310"
> </a
><a name="311" href="Agda.Builtin.Equality.html#112" class="InductiveConstructor"
>refl</a
><a name="315" class="Symbol"
>)</a
>
</pre><!--{% endraw %}-->
</div>
# Basics: Functional Programming in Agda
The functional programming style brings programming closer to
simple, everyday mathematics: If a procedure or method has no side
effects, then (ignoring efficiency) all we need to understand
about it is how it maps inputs to outputs -- that is, we can think
of it as just a concrete method for computing a mathematical
function. This is one sense of the word "functional" in
"functional programming." The direct connection between programs
and simple mathematical objects supports both formal correctness
proofs and sound informal reasoning about program behavior.
The other sense in which functional programming is "functional" is
that it emphasizes the use of functions (or methods) as
*first-class* values -- i.e., values that can be passed as
arguments to other functions, returned as results, included in
data structures, etc. The recognition that functions can be
treated as data in this way enables a host of useful and powerful
idioms.
Other common features of functional languages include *algebraic
data types* and *pattern matching*, which make it easy to
construct and manipulate rich data structures, and sophisticated
*polymorphic type systems* supporting abstraction and code reuse.
Agda shares all of these features.
This chapter introduces the most essential elements of Agda.
## Enumerated Types
One unusual aspect of Agda is that its set of built-in
features is *extremely* small. For example, instead of providing
the usual palette of atomic data types (booleans, integers,
strings, etc.), Agda offers a powerful mechanism for defining new
data types from scratch, from which all these familiar types arise
as instances.
Naturally, the Agda distribution comes with an extensive standard
library providing definitions of booleans, numbers, and many
common data structures like lists and hash tables. But there is
nothing magic or primitive about these library definitions. To
illustrate this, we will explicitly recapitulate all the
definitions we need in this course, rather than just getting them
implicitly from the library.
To see how this definition mechanism works, let's start with a
very simple example.
### Days of the Week
The following declaration tells Agda that we are defining
a new set of data values -- a *type*.
<!--{% raw %}--><pre class="Agda">
<a name="2656" class="Keyword"
>data</a
><a name="2660"
> </a
><a name="2661" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2664"
> </a
><a name="2665" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2666"
> </a
><a name="2667" class="PrimitiveType"
>Set</a
><a name="2670"
> </a
><a name="2671" class="Keyword"
>where</a
><a name="2676"
>
</a
><a name="2681" href="Basics.html#2681" class="InductiveConstructor"
>monday</a
><a name="2687"
> </a
><a name="2691" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2692"
> </a
><a name="2693" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2696"
>
</a
><a name="2701" href="Basics.html#2701" class="InductiveConstructor"
>tuesday</a
><a name="2708"
> </a
><a name="2711" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2712"
> </a
><a name="2713" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2716"
>
</a
><a name="2721" href="Basics.html#2721" class="InductiveConstructor"
>wednesday</a
><a name="2730"
> </a
><a name="2731" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2732"
> </a
><a name="2733" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2736"
>
</a
><a name="2741" href="Basics.html#2741" class="InductiveConstructor"
>thursday</a
><a name="2749"
> </a
><a name="2751" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2752"
> </a
><a name="2753" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2756"
>
</a
><a name="2761" href="Basics.html#2761" class="InductiveConstructor"
>friday</a
><a name="2767"
> </a
><a name="2771" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2772"
> </a
><a name="2773" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2776"
>
</a
><a name="2781" href="Basics.html#2781" class="InductiveConstructor"
>saturday</a
><a name="2789"
> </a
><a name="2791" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2792"
> </a
><a name="2793" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="2796"
>
</a
><a name="2801" href="Basics.html#2801" class="InductiveConstructor"
>sunday</a
><a name="2807"
> </a
><a name="2811" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="2812"
> </a
><a name="2813" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
>
</pre><!--{% endraw %}-->
The type is called `day`, and its members are `monday`,
`tuesday`, etc. The second and following lines of the definition
can be read "`monday` is a `day`, `tuesday` is a `day`, etc."
Having defined `day`, we can write functions that operate on
days.
<!--{% raw %}--><pre class="Agda">
<a name="3097" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3108"
> </a
><a name="3109" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="3110"
> </a
><a name="3111" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="3114"
> </a
><a name="3115" class="Symbol"
>-&gt;</a
><a name="3117"
> </a
><a name="3118" href="Basics.html#2661" class="Datatype"
>Day</a
><a name="3121"
>
</a
><a name="3124" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3135"
> </a
><a name="3136" href="Basics.html#2681" class="InductiveConstructor"
>monday</a
><a name="3142"
> </a
><a name="3146" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3147"
> </a
><a name="3148" href="Basics.html#2701" class="InductiveConstructor"
>tuesday</a
><a name="3155"
>
</a
><a name="3158" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3169"
> </a
><a name="3170" href="Basics.html#2701" class="InductiveConstructor"
>tuesday</a
><a name="3177"
> </a
><a name="3180" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3181"
> </a
><a name="3182" href="Basics.html#2721" class="InductiveConstructor"
>wednesday</a
><a name="3191"
>
</a
><a name="3194" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3205"
> </a
><a name="3206" href="Basics.html#2721" class="InductiveConstructor"
>wednesday</a
><a name="3215"
> </a
><a name="3216" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3217"
> </a
><a name="3218" href="Basics.html#2741" class="InductiveConstructor"
>thursday</a
><a name="3226"
>
</a
><a name="3229" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3240"
> </a
><a name="3241" href="Basics.html#2741" class="InductiveConstructor"
>thursday</a
><a name="3249"
> </a
><a name="3251" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3252"
> </a
><a name="3253" href="Basics.html#2761" class="InductiveConstructor"
>friday</a
><a name="3259"
>
</a
><a name="3262" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3273"
> </a
><a name="3274" href="Basics.html#2761" class="InductiveConstructor"
>friday</a
><a name="3280"
> </a
><a name="3284" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3285"
> </a
><a name="3286" href="Basics.html#2681" class="InductiveConstructor"
>monday</a
><a name="3292"
>
</a
><a name="3295" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3306"
> </a
><a name="3307" href="Basics.html#2781" class="InductiveConstructor"
>saturday</a
><a name="3315"
> </a
><a name="3317" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3318"
> </a
><a name="3319" href="Basics.html#2681" class="InductiveConstructor"
>monday</a
><a name="3325"
>
</a
><a name="3328" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="3339"
> </a
><a name="3340" href="Basics.html#2801" class="InductiveConstructor"
>sunday</a
><a name="3346"
> </a
><a name="3350" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="3351"
> </a
><a name="3352" href="Basics.html#2681" class="InductiveConstructor"
>monday</a
>
</pre><!--{% endraw %}-->
One thing to note is that the argument and return types of
this function are explicitly declared. Like most functional
programming languages, Agda can often figure out these types for
itself when they are not given explicitly -- i.e., it performs
*type inference* -- but we'll include them to make reading
easier.
Having defined a function, we should check that it works on
some examples. There are actually three different ways to do this
in Agda.
First, we can use the Emacs command `C-c C-n` to evaluate a
compound expression involving `nextWeekday`. For instance, `nextWeekday
friday` should evaluate to `monday`. If you have a computer handy, this
would be an excellent moment to fire up Agda and try this for yourself.
Load this file, `Basics.lagda`, load it using `C-c C-l`, submit the
above example to Agda, and observe the result.
Second, we can record what we *expect* the result to be in the
form of an Agda type:
<!--{% raw %}--><pre class="Agda">
<a name="4316" href="Basics.html#4316" class="Function Operator"
>test_nextWeekday</a
><a name="4332"
> </a
><a name="4333" class="Symbol"
>:</a
><a name="4334"
> </a
><a name="4335" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="4346"
> </a
><a name="4347" class="Symbol"
>(</a
><a name="4348" href="Basics.html#3097" class="Function"
>nextWeekday</a
><a name="4359"
> </a
><a name="4360" href="Basics.html#2781" class="InductiveConstructor"
>saturday</a
><a name="4368" class="Symbol"
>)</a
><a name="4369"
> </a
><a name="4370" href="Agda.Builtin.Equality.html#55" class="Datatype Operator"
>&#8801;</a
><a name="4371"
> </a
><a name="4372" href="Basics.html#2701" class="InductiveConstructor"
>tuesday</a
>
</pre><!--{% endraw %}-->
This declaration does two things: it makes an assertion (that the second
weekday after `saturday` is `tuesday`), and it gives the assertion a name
that can be used to refer to it later.
Having made the assertion, we must also verify it. We do this by giving
a term of the above type:
<!--{% raw %}--><pre class="Agda">
<a name="4693" href="Basics.html#4316" class="Function Operator"
>test_nextWeekday</a
><a name="4709"
> </a
><a name="4710" class="Symbol"
>=</a
><a name="4711"
> </a
><a name="4712" href="Agda.Builtin.Equality.html#112" class="InductiveConstructor"
>refl</a
>
</pre><!--{% endraw %}-->
There is no essential difference between the definition for
`test_nextWeekday` here and the definition for `nextWeekday` above,
except for the new symbol for equality `≡` and the constructor `refl`.
The details of these are not important for now (we'll come back to them in
a bit), but essentially `refl` can be read as "The assertion we've made
can be proved by observing that both sides of the equality evaluate to the
same thing, after some simplification."
Third, we can ask Agda to *compile* some program involving our definition,
This facility is very interesting, since it gives us a way to construct
*fully certified* programs. We'll come back to this topic in later chapters.

345
Maps.lagda Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,345 @@
---
title : "Maps: Total and Partial Maps"
layout : default
hide-implicit : false
extra-script : [agda-extra-script.html]
extra-style : [agda-extra-style.html]
permalink : "sf/Maps.html"
---
# Maps: Total and Partial Maps
Maps (or dictionaries) are ubiquitous data structures, both in
software construction generally and in the theory of programming
languages in particular; we're going to need them in many places in
the coming chapters. They also make a nice case study using ideas
we've seen in previous chapters, including building data structures
out of higher-order functions (from [Basics](sf/Basics.html)
and [Poly](sf/Poly.html) and the use of reflection to streamline
proofs (from [IndProp](sf/IndProp.html).
We'll define two flavors of maps: _total_ maps, which include a
"default" element to be returned when a key being looked up
doesn't exist, and _partial_ maps, which return an `Maybe` to
indicate success or failure. The latter is defined in terms of
the former, using `nothing` as the default element.
## The Agda Standard Library
One small digression before we start.
Unlike the chapters we have seen so far, this one does not
import the chapter before it (and, transitively, all the
earlier chapters). Instead, in this chapter and from now, on
we're going to import the definitions and theorems we need
directly from Agda's standard library stuff. You should not notice
much difference, though, because we've been careful to name our
own definitions and theorems the same as their counterparts in the
standard library, wherever they overlap.
\begin{code}
open import Function using (_∘_)
open import Data.Bool using (Bool; true; false)
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
open import Data.Maybe using (Maybe; just; nothing)
open import Data.Nat using ()
open import Relation.Nullary using (Dec; yes; no)
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality
\end{code}
Documentation for the standard library can be found at
<https://agda.github.io/agda-stdlib/>.
## Identifiers
First, we need a type for the keys that we use to index into our
maps. For this purpose, we again use the type Id` from the
[Lists](sf/Lists.html) chapter. To make this chapter self contained,
we repeat its definition here, together with the equality comparison
function for ids and its fundamental property.
\begin{code}
data Id : Set where
id : → Id
\end{code}
\begin{code}
_≟_ : (x y : Id) → Dec (x ≡ y)
id x ≟ id y with x Data.Nat.≟ y
id x ≟ id y | yes x=y rewrite x=y = yes refl
id x ≟ id y | no x≠y = no (x≠y ∘ id-inj)
where
id-inj : ∀ {x y} → id x ≡ id y → x ≡ y
id-inj refl = refl
\end{code}
## Total Maps
Our main job in this chapter will be to build a definition of
partial maps that is similar in behavior to the one we saw in the
[Lists](sf/Lists.html) chapter, plus accompanying lemmas about their
behavior.
This time around, though, we're going to use _functions_, rather
than lists of key-value pairs, to build maps. The advantage of
this representation is that it offers a more _extensional_ view of
maps, where two maps that respond to queries in the same way will
be represented as literally the same thing (the same function),
rather than just "equivalent" data structures. This, in turn,
simplifies proofs that use maps.
We build partial maps in two steps. First, we define a type of
_total maps_ that return a default value when we look up a key
that is not present in the map.
\begin{code}
TotalMap : Set → Set
TotalMap A = Id → A
\end{code}
Intuitively, a total map over anfi element type $$A$$ _is_ just a
function that can be used to look up ids, yielding $$A$$s.
\begin{code}
module TotalMap where
\end{code}
The function `empty` yields an empty total map, given a
default element; this map always returns the default element when
applied to any id.
\begin{code}
empty : ∀ {A} → A → TotalMap A
empty x = λ _ → x
\end{code}
More interesting is the `update` function, which (as before) takes
a map $$m$$, a key $$x$$, and a value $$v$$ and returns a new map that
takes $$x$$ to $$v$$ and takes every other key to whatever $$m$$ does.
\begin{code}
update : ∀ {A} → TotalMap A -> Id -> A -> TotalMap A
update m x v y with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = v
... | no x≠y = m y
\end{code}
This definition is a nice example of higher-order programming.
The `update` function takes a _function_ $$m$$ and yields a new
function $$\lambda x'.\vdots$$ that behaves like the desired map.
For example, we can build a map taking ids to bools, where `id
3` is mapped to `true` and every other key is mapped to `false`,
like this:
\begin{code}
examplemap : TotalMap Bool
examplemap = update (update (empty false) (id 1) false) (id 3) true
\end{code}
This completes the definition of total maps. Note that we don't
need to define a `find` operation because it is just function
application!
\begin{code}
test_examplemap0 : examplemap (id 0) ≡ false
test_examplemap0 = refl
test_examplemap1 : examplemap (id 1) ≡ false
test_examplemap1 = refl
test_examplemap2 : examplemap (id 2) ≡ false
test_examplemap2 = refl
test_examplemap3 : examplemap (id 3) ≡ true
test_examplemap3 = refl
\end{code}
To use maps in later chapters, we'll need several fundamental
facts about how they behave. Even if you don't work the following
exercises, make sure you thoroughly understand the statements of
the lemmas! (Some of the proofs require the functional
extensionality axiom, which is discussed in the [Logic]
chapter and included in the Agda standard library.)
#### Exercise: 1 star, optional (apply-empty)
First, the empty map returns its default element for all keys:
\begin{code}
postulate
apply-empty : ∀ {A x v} → empty {A} v x ≡ v
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
apply-empty : ∀ {A x v} → empty {A} v x ≡ v
apply-empty = refl
\end{code}
</div>
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-eq)
Next, if we update a map $$m$$ at a key $$x$$ with a new value $$v$$
and then look up $$x$$ in the map resulting from the `update`, we get
back $$v$$:
\begin{code}
postulate
update-eq : ∀ {A v} (m : TotalMap A) (x : Id)
→ (update m x v) x ≡ v
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
update-eq : ∀ {A v} (m : TotalMap A) (x : Id)
→ (update m x v) x ≡ v
update-eq m x with x ≟ x
... | yes x=x = refl
... | no x≠x = ⊥-elim (x≠x refl)
\end{code}
</div>
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-neq)
On the other hand, if we update a map $$m$$ at a key $$x$$ and
then look up a _different_ key $$y$$ in the resulting map, we get
the same result that $$m$$ would have given:
\begin{code}
update-neq : ∀ {A v} (m : TotalMap A) (x y : Id)
→ x ≢ y → (update m x v) y ≡ m y
update-neq m x y x≠y with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = ⊥-elim (x≠y x=y)
... | no _ = refl
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-shadow)
If we update a map $$m$$ at a key $$x$$ with a value $$v_1$$ and then
update again with the same key $$x$$ and another value $$v_2$$, the
resulting map behaves the same (gives the same result when applied
to any key) as the simpler map obtained by performing just
the second `update` on $$m$$:
\begin{code}
postulate
update-shadow : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : TotalMap A) (x y : Id)
→ (update (update m x v1) x v2) y ≡ (update m x v2) y
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
update-shadow : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : TotalMap A) (x y : Id)
→ (update (update m x v1) x v2) y ≡ (update m x v2) y
update-shadow m x y
with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = refl
... | no x≠y = update-neq m x y x≠y
\end{code}
</div>
#### Exercise: 2 stars (update-same)
Prove the following theorem, which states that if we update a map to
assign key $$x$$ the same value as it already has in $$m$$, then the
result is equal to $$m$$:
\begin{code}
postulate
update-same : ∀ {A} (m : TotalMap A) (x y : Id)
→ (update m x (m x)) y ≡ m y
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
update-same : ∀ {A} (m : TotalMap A) (x y : Id)
→ (update m x (m x)) y ≡ m y
update-same m x y
with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y rewrite x=y = refl
... | no x≠y = refl
\end{code}
</div>
#### Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (update-permute)
Prove one final property of the `update` function: If we update a map
$$m$$ at two distinct keys, it doesn't matter in which order we do the
updates.
\begin{code}
postulate
update-permute : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : TotalMap A) (x1 x2 y : Id)
→ x1 ≢ x2 → (update (update m x2 v2) x1 v1) y
≡ (update (update m x1 v1) x2 v2) y
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
update-permute : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : TotalMap A) (x1 x2 y : Id)
→ x1 ≢ x2 → (update (update m x2 v2) x1 v1) y
≡ (update (update m x1 v1) x2 v2) y
update-permute {A} {v1} {v2} m x1 x2 y x1≠x2
with x1 ≟ y | x2 ≟ y
... | yes x1=y | yes x2=y = ⊥-elim (x1≠x2 (trans x1=y (sym x2=y)))
... | no x1≠y | yes x2=y rewrite x2=y = update-eq m y
... | yes x1=y | no x2≠y rewrite x1=y = sym (update-eq m y)
... | no x1≠y | no x2≠y =
trans (update-neq m x2 y x2≠y) (sym (update-neq m x1 y x1≠y))
\end{code}
</div>
## Partial maps
Finally, we define _partial maps_ on top of total maps. A partial
map with elements of type `A` is simply a total map with elements
of type `Maybe A` and default element `nothing`.
\begin{code}
PartialMap : Set → Set
PartialMap A = TotalMap (Maybe A)
\end{code}
\begin{code}
module PartialMap where
\end{code}
\begin{code}
empty : ∀ {A} → PartialMap A
empty = TotalMap.empty nothing
\end{code}
\begin{code}
update : ∀ {A} (m : PartialMap A) (x : Id) (v : A) → PartialMap A
update m x v = TotalMap.update m x (just v)
\end{code}
We can now lift all of the basic lemmas about total maps to
partial maps.
\begin{code}
update-eq : ∀ {A v} (m : PartialMap A) (x : Id)
→ (update m x v) x ≡ just v
update-eq m x = TotalMap.update-eq m x
\end{code}
\begin{code}
update-neq : ∀ {A v} (m : PartialMap A) (x y : Id)
→ x ≢ y → (update m x v) y ≡ m y
update-neq m x y x≠y = TotalMap.update-neq m x y x≠y
\end{code}
\begin{code}
update-shadow : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : PartialMap A) (x y : Id)
→ (update (update m x v1) x v2) y ≡ (update m x v2) y
update-shadow m x y = TotalMap.update-shadow m x y
\end{code}
\begin{code}
update-same : ∀ {A v} (m : PartialMap A) (x y : Id)
→ m x ≡ just v
→ (update m x v) y ≡ m y
update-same m x y mx=v rewrite sym mx=v = TotalMap.update-same m x y
\end{code}
\begin{code}
update-permute : ∀ {A v1 v2} (m : PartialMap A) (x1 x2 y : Id)
→ x1 ≢ x2 → (update (update m x2 v2) x1 v1) y
≡ (update (update m x1 v1) x2 v2) y
update-permute m x1 x2 y x1≠x2 = TotalMap.update-permute m x1 x2 y x1≠x2
\end{code}

4467
Maps.md Normal file

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff

735
Stlc.lagda Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,735 @@
---
title : "Stlc: The Simply Typed Lambda-Calculus"
layout : default
hide-implicit : false
extra-script : [agda-extra-script.html]
extra-style : [agda-extra-style.html]
permalink : "sf/Stlc.html"
---
\begin{code}
module Stlc where
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
open import Maps using (Id; id; _≟_; PartialMap; module PartialMap)
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
open import Data.Maybe using (Maybe; just; nothing)
open import Data.Nat using (; suc; zero; _+_)
open import Data.Product using (∃; ∄; _,_)
open import Function using (_∘_; _$_)
open import Relation.Nullary using (Dec; yes; no)
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; _≢_; refl)
\end{code}
</div>
# The Simply Typed Lambda-Calculus
The simply typed lambda-calculus (STLC) is a tiny core
calculus embodying the key concept of _functional abstraction_,
which shows up in pretty much every real-world programming
language in some form (functions, procedures, methods, etc.).
We will follow exactly the same pattern as in the previous chapter
when formalizing this calculus (syntax, small-step semantics,
typing rules) and its main properties (progress and preservation).
The new technical challenges arise from the mechanisms of
_variable binding_ and _substitution_. It which will take some
work to deal with these.
## Overview
The STLC is built on some collection of _base types_:
booleans, numbers, strings, etc. The exact choice of base types
doesn't matter much---the construction of the language and its
theoretical properties work out the same no matter what we
choose---so for the sake of brevity let's take just $$bool$$ for
the moment. At the end of the chapter we'll see how to add more
base types, and in later chapters we'll enrich the pure STLC with
other useful constructs like pairs, records, subtyping, and
mutable state.
Starting from boolean constants and conditionals, we add three
things:
- variables
- function abstractions
- application
This gives us the following collection of abstract syntax
constructors (written out first in informal BNF notation---we'll
formalize it below).
$$
\begin{array}{rll}
\text{Terms}\;s,t,u
::= & x & \text{variable} \\
\mid & \lambda x : A . t & \text{abstraction} \\
\mid & s\;t & \text{application} \\
\mid & true & \text{constant true} \\
\mid & false & \text{constant false} \\
\mid & \text{if }s\text{ then }t\text{ else }u & \text{conditional}
\end{array}
$$
In a lambda abstraction $$\lambda x : A . t$$, the variable $$x$$ is called the
_parameter_ to the function; the term $$t$$ is its _body_. The annotation $$:A$$
specifies the type of arguments that the function can be applied to.
Some examples:
- The identity function for booleans:
$$\lambda x:bool. x$$.
- The identity function for booleans, applied to the boolean $$true$$:
$$(\lambda x:bool. x)\;true$$.
- The boolean "not" function:
$$\lambda x:bool. \text{if }x\text{ then }false\text{ else }true$$.
- The constant function that takes every (boolean) argument to $$true$$:
$$\lambda x:bool. true$$.
- A two-argument function that takes two booleans and returns the
first one:
$$\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x$$.
As in Agda, a two-argument function is really a
one-argument function whose body is also a one-argument function.
- A two-argument function that takes two booleans and returns the
first one, applied to the booleans $$false$$ and $$true$$:
$$(\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x)\;false\;true$$.
As in Agda, application associates to the left---i.e., this
expression is parsed as
$$((\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x)\;false)\;true$$.
- A higher-order function that takes a _function_ $$f$$ (from booleans
to booleans) as an argument, applies $$f$$ to $$true$$, and applies
$$f$$ again to the result:
$$\lambda f:bool\rightarrow bool. f\;(f\;true)$$.
- The same higher-order function, applied to the constantly $$false$$
function:
$$(\lambda f:bool\rightarrow bool. f\;(f\;true))\;(\lambda x:bool. false)$$.
As the last several examples show, the STLC is a language of
_higher-order_ functions: we can write down functions that take
other functions as arguments and/or return other functions as
results.
The STLC doesn't provide any primitive syntax for defining _named_
functions---all functions are "anonymous." We'll see in chapter
`MoreStlc` that it is easy to add named functions to what we've
got---indeed, the fundamental naming and binding mechanisms are
exactly the same.
The _types_ of the STLC include $$bool$$, which classifies the
boolean constants $$true$$ and $$false$$ as well as more complex
computations that yield booleans, plus _arrow types_ that classify
functions.
$$
\text{Types}\;A,B ::= bool \mid A \rightarrow B
$$
For example:
- $$\lambda x:bool. false$$ has type $$bool\rightarrow bool$$;
- $$\lambda x:bool. x$$ has type $$bool\rightarrow bool$$;
- $$(\lambda x:bool. x)\;true$$ has type $$bool$$;
- $$\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x$$ has type
$$bool\rightarrow bool\rightarrow bool$$
(i.e., $$bool\rightarrow (bool\rightarrow bool)$$)
- $$(\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x)\;false$$ has type $$bool\rightarrow bool$$
- $$(\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x)\;false\;true$$ has type $$bool$$
## Syntax
We begin by formalizing the syntax of the STLC.
Unfortunately, $$\rightarrow$$ is already used for Agda's function type,
so we will STLC's function type as `_⇒_`.
### Types
\begin{code}
data Type : Set where
bool : Type
_⇒_ : Type → Type → Type
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infixr 5 _⇒_
\end{code}
</div>
### Terms
\begin{code}
data Term : Set where
var : Id → Term
app : Term → Term → Term
abs : Id → Type → Term → Term
true : Term
false : Term
if_then_else_ : Term → Term → Term → Term
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infixr 8 if_then_else_
\end{code}
</div>
Note that an abstraction $$\lambda x:A.t$$ (formally, `abs x A t`) is
always annotated with the type $$A$$ of its parameter, in contrast
to Agda (and other functional languages like ML, Haskell, etc.),
which use _type inference_ to fill in missing annotations. We're
not considering type inference here.
Some examples...
\begin{code}
x = id 0
y = id 1
z = id 2
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
{-# DISPLAY zero = x #-}
{-# DISPLAY suc zero = y #-}
{-# DISPLAY suc (suc zero) = z #-}
\end{code}
</div>
$$\text{idB} = \lambda x:bool. x$$.
\begin{code}
idB = (abs x bool (var x))
\end{code}
$$\text{idBB} = \lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x$$.
\begin{code}
idBB = (abs x (bool ⇒ bool) (var x))
\end{code}
$$\text{idBBBB} = \lambda x:(bool\rightarrow bool)\rightarrow (bool\rightarrow bool). x$$.
\begin{code}
idBBBB = (abs x ((bool ⇒ bool) ⇒ (bool ⇒ bool)) (var x))
\end{code}
$$\text{k} = \lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x$$.
\begin{code}
k = (abs x bool (abs y bool (var x)))
\end{code}
$$\text{notB} = \lambda x:bool. \text{if }x\text{ then }false\text{ else }true$$.
\begin{code}
notB = (abs x bool (if (var x) then false else true))
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
{-# DISPLAY abs 0 bool (var 0) = idB #-}
{-# DISPLAY abs 0 (bool ⇒ bool) (var 0) = idBB #-}
{-# DISPLAY abs 0 ((bool ⇒ bool) ⇒ (bool ⇒ bool)) (var 0) = idBBBB #-}
{-# DISPLAY abs 0 bool (abs y bool (var 0)) = k #-}
{-# DISPLAY abs 0 bool (if (var 0) then false else true) = notB #-}
\end{code}
</div>
## Operational Semantics
To define the small-step semantics of STLC terms, we begin,
as always, by defining the set of values. Next, we define the
critical notions of _free variables_ and _substitution_, which are
used in the reduction rule for application expressions. And
finally we give the small-step relation itself.
### Values
To define the values of the STLC, we have a few cases to consider.
First, for the boolean part of the language, the situation is
clear: $$true$$ and $$false$$ are the only values. An $$\text{if}$$
expression is never a value.
Second, an application is clearly not a value: It represents a
function being invoked on some argument, which clearly still has
work left to do.
Third, for abstractions, we have a choice:
- We can say that $$\lambda x:A. t$$ is a value only when $$t$$ is a
value---i.e., only if the function's body has been
reduced (as much as it can be without knowing what argument it
is going to be applied to).
- Or we can say that $$\lambda x:A. t$$ is always a value, no matter
whether $$t$$ is one or not---in other words, we can say that
reduction stops at abstractions.
Agda makes the first choice---for example,
\begin{code}
test_normalizeUnderLambda : (λ (x : ) → 3 + 4) ≡ (λ (x : ) → 7)
test_normalizeUnderLambda = refl
\end{code}
Most real-world functional programming languages make the second
choice---reduction of a function's body only begins when the
function is actually applied to an argument. We also make the
second choice here.
\begin{code}
data Value : Term → Set where
abs : ∀ {x A t}
→ Value (abs x A t)
true : Value true
false : Value false
\end{code}
Finally, we must consider what constitutes a _complete_ program.
Intuitively, a "complete program" must not refer to any undefined
variables. We'll see shortly how to define the _free_ variables
in a STLC term. A complete program is _closed_---that is, it
contains no free variables.
Having made the choice not to reduce under abstractions, we don't
need to worry about whether variables are values, since we'll
always be reducing programs "from the outside in," and that means
the small-step relation will always be working with closed terms.
### Substitution
Now we come to the heart of the STLC: the operation of
substituting one term for a variable in another term. This
operation is used below to define the operational semantics of
function application, where we will need to substitute the
argument term for the function parameter in the function's body.
For example, we reduce
$$(\lambda x:bool. \text{if }x\text{ then }true\text{ else }x)\;false$$
to
$$\text{if }false\text{ then }true\text{ else }false$$
by substituting $$false$$ for the parameter $$x$$ in the body of the
function.
In general, we need to be able to substitute some given term $$s$$
for occurrences of some variable $$x$$ in another term $$t$$. In
informal discussions, this is usually written $$[x:=s]t$$ and
pronounced "substitute $$x$$ with $$s$$ in $$t$$."
Here are some examples:
- $$[x:=true](\text{if }x\text{ then }x\text{ else }false)$$
yields $$\text{if }true\text{ then }true\text{ else }false$$
- $$[x:=true]x$$
yields $$true$$
- $$[x:=true](\text{if }x\text{ then }x\text{ else }y)$$
yields $$\text{if }true\text{ then }true\text{ else }y$$
- $$[x:=true]y$$
yields $$y$$
- $$[x:=true]false$$
yields $$false$$ (vacuous substitution)
- $$[x:=true](\lambda y:bool. \text{if }y\text{ then }x\text{ else }false)$$
yields $$\lambda y:bool. \text{if }y\text{ then }true\text{ else }false$$
- $$[x:=true](\lambda y:bool. x)$$
yields $$\lambda y:bool. true$$
- $$[x:=true](\lambda y:bool. y)$$
yields $$\lambda y:bool. y$$
- $$[x:=true](\lambda x:bool. x)$$
yields $$\lambda x:bool. x$$
The last example is very important: substituting $$x$$ with $$true$$ in
$$\lambda x:bool. x$$ does _not_ yield $$\lambda x:bool. true$$! The reason for
this is that the $$x$$ in the body of $$\lambda x:bool. x$$ is _bound_ by the
abstraction: it is a new, local name that just happens to be
spelled the same as some global name $$x$$.
Here is the definition, informally...
$$
\begin{aligned}
&[x:=s]x &&= s \\
&[x:=s]y &&= y \;\{\text{if }x\neq y\} \\
&[x:=s](\lambda x:A. t) &&= \lambda x:A. t \\
&[x:=s](\lambda y:A. t) &&= \lambda y:A. [x:=s]t \;\{\text{if }x\neq y\} \\
&[x:=s](t1\;t2) &&= ([x:=s]t1) ([x:=s]t2) \\
&[x:=s]true &&= true \\
&[x:=s]false &&= false \\
&[x:=s](\text{if }t1\text{ then }t2\text{ else }t3) &&=
\text{if }[x:=s]t1\text{ then }[x:=s]t2\text{ else }[x:=s]t3
\end{aligned}
$$
... and formally:
\begin{code}
[_:=_]_ : Id -> Term -> Term -> Term
[ x := v ] (var y) with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = v
... | no x≠y = var y
[ x := v ] (app s t) = app ([ x := v ] s) ([ x := v ] t)
[ x := v ] (abs y A t) with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = abs y A t
... | no x≠y = abs y A ([ x := v ] t)
[ x := v ] true = true
[ x := v ] false = false
[ x := v ] (if s then t else u) =
if [ x := v ] s then [ x := v ] t else [ x := v ] u
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infix 9 [_:=_]_
\end{code}
</div>
_Technical note_: Substitution becomes trickier to define if we
consider the case where $$s$$, the term being substituted for a
variable in some other term, may itself contain free variables.
Since we are only interested here in defining the small-step relation
on closed terms (i.e., terms like $$\lambda x:bool. x$$ that include
binders for all of the variables they mention), we can avoid this
extra complexity here, but it must be dealt with when formalizing
richer languages.
#### Exercise: 3 stars (subst-correct)
The definition that we gave above defines substitution as a _function_.
Suppose, instead, we wanted to define substitution as an inductive _relation_.
We've begun the definition by providing the `data` header and
one of the constructors; your job is to fill in the rest of the constructors
and prove that the relation you've defined coincides with the function given
above.
\begin{code}
data [_:=_]_==>_ (x : Id) (s : Term) : Term -> Term -> Set where
var1 : [ x := s ] (var x) ==> s
{- FILL IN HERE -}
\end{code}
\begin{code}
postulate
subst-correct : ∀ s x t t'
→ [ x := s ] t ≡ t'
→ [ x := s ] t ==> t'
\end{code}
### Reduction
The small-step reduction relation for STLC now follows the
same pattern as the ones we have seen before. Intuitively, to
reduce a function application, we first reduce its left-hand
side (the function) until it becomes an abstraction; then we
reduce its right-hand side (the argument) until it is also a
value; and finally we substitute the argument for the bound
variable in the body of the abstraction. This last rule, written
informally as
$$
(\lambda x : A . t) v \Longrightarrow [x:=v]t
$$
is traditionally called "beta-reduction".
$$
\begin{array}{cl}
\frac{value(v)}{(\lambda x : A . t) v \Longrightarrow [x:=v]t}&(red)\\\\
\frac{s \Longrightarrow s'}{s\;t \Longrightarrow s'\;t}&(app1)\\\\
\frac{value(v)\quad t \Longrightarrow t'}{v\;t \Longrightarrow v\;t'}&(app2)
\end{array}
$$
... plus the usual rules for booleans:
$$
\begin{array}{cl}
\frac{}{(\text{if }true\text{ then }t_1\text{ else }t_2) \Longrightarrow t_1}&(iftrue)\\\\
\frac{}{(\text{if }false\text{ then }t_1\text{ else }t_2) \Longrightarrow t_2}&(iffalse)\\\\
\frac{s \Longrightarrow s'}{\text{if }s\text{ then }t_1\text{ else }t_2
\Longrightarrow \text{if }s\text{ then }t_1\text{ else }t_2}&(if)
\end{array}
$$
Formally:
\begin{code}
data _==>_ : Term → Term → Set where
red : ∀ {x A s t}
→ Value t
→ app (abs x A s) t ==> [ x := t ] s
app1 : ∀ {s s' t}
→ s ==> s'
→ app s t ==> app s' t
app2 : ∀ {s t t'}
→ Value s
→ t ==> t'
→ app s t ==> app s t'
if : ∀ {s s' t u}
→ s ==> s'
→ if s then t else u ==> if s' then t else u
iftrue : ∀ {s t}
→ if true then s else t ==> s
iffalse : ∀ {s t}
→ if false then s else t ==> t
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infix 1 _==>_
\end{code}
</div>
\begin{code}
data Multi (R : Term → Term → Set) : Term → Term → Set where
refl : ∀ {x} -> Multi R x x
step : ∀ {x y z} -> R x y -> Multi R y z -> Multi R x z
\end{code}
\begin{code}
_==>*_ : Term → Term → Set
_==>*_ = Multi _==>_
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
{-# DISPLAY Multi _==>_ = _==>*_ #-}
\end{code}
</div>
### Examples
Example:
$$((\lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x) (\lambda x:bool. x)) \Longrightarrow^* (\lambda x:bool. x)$$.
\begin{code}
step-example1 : (app idBB idB) ==>* idB
step-example1 = step (red abs)
$ refl
\end{code}
Example:
$$(\lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x) \;((\lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x)\;(\lambda x:bool. x))) \Longrightarrow^* (\lambda x:bool. x)$$.
\begin{code}
step-example2 : (app idBB (app idBB idB)) ==>* idB
step-example2 = step (app2 abs (red abs))
$ step (red abs)
$ refl
\end{code}
Example:
$$((\lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x)\;(\lambda x:bool. \text{if }x\text{ then }false\text{ else }true))\;true\Longrightarrow^* false$$.
\begin{code}
step-example3 : (app (app idBB notB) true) ==>* false
step-example3 = step (app1 (red abs))
$ step (red true)
$ step iftrue
$ refl
\end{code}
Example:
$$((\lambda x:bool\rightarrow bool. x)\;((\lambda x:bool. \text{if }x\text{ then }false\text{ else }true)\;true))\Longrightarrow^* false$$.
\begin{code}
step-example4 : (app idBB (app notB true)) ==>* false
step-example4 = step (app2 abs (red true))
$ step (app2 abs iftrue)
$ step (red false)
$ refl
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 2 stars (step-example5)
\begin{code}
postulate
step-example5 : (app (app idBBBB idBB) idB) ==>* idB
\end{code}
## Typing
Next we consider the typing relation of the STLC.
### Contexts
_Question_: What is the type of the term "$$x\;y$$"?
_Answer_: It depends on the types of $$x$$ and $$y$$!
I.e., in order to assign a type to a term, we need to know
what assumptions we should make about the types of its free
variables.
This leads us to a three-place _typing judgment_, informally
written $$\Gamma\vdash t : A$$, where $$\Gamma$$ is a
"typing context"---a mapping from variables to their types.
Informally, we'll write $$\Gamma , x:A$$ for "extend the partial function
$$\Gamma$$ to also map $$x$$ to $$A$$." Formally, we use the function `_,__`
(or "update") to add a binding to a context.
\begin{code}
Ctxt : Set
Ctxt = PartialMap Type
∅ : Ctxt
∅ = PartialMap.empty
_,__ : Ctxt -> Id -> Type -> Ctxt
_,__ = PartialMap.update
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infixl 3 _,__
\end{code}
</div>
### Typing Relation
$$
\begin{array}{cl}
\frac{\Gamma\;x = A}{\Gamma\vdash{x:A}}&(var)\\\\
\frac{\Gamma,x:A\vdash t:B}{\Gamma\vdash (\lambda x:A.t) : A\rightarrow B}&(abs)\\\\
\frac{\Gamma\vdash s:A\rightarrow B\quad\Gamma\vdash t:A}{\Gamma\vdash (s\;t) : B}&(app)\\\\
\frac{}{\Gamma\vdash true : bool}&(true)\\\\
\frac{}{\Gamma\vdash false : bool}&(true)\\\\
\frac{\Gamma\vdash s:bool \quad \Gamma\vdash t1:A \quad \Gamma\vdash t2:A}{\Gamma\vdash\text{if }s\text{ then }t1\text{ else }t2 : A}&(if)
\end{array}
$$
We can read the three-place relation $$\Gamma\vdash (t : A)$$ as:
"to the term $$t$$ we can assign the type $$A$$ using as types for
the free variables of $$t$$ the ones specified in the context
$$\Gamma$$."
\begin{code}
data _⊢__ : Ctxt -> Term -> Type -> Set where
var : ∀ {Γ} x {A}
→ Γ x ≡ just A
→ Γ ⊢ var x A
abs : ∀ {Γ} {x} {A} {B} {s}
→ Γ , x A ⊢ s B
→ Γ ⊢ abs x A s A ⇒ B
app : ∀ {Γ} {A} {B} {s} {t}
→ Γ ⊢ s A ⇒ B
→ Γ ⊢ t A
→ Γ ⊢ app s t B
true : ∀ {Γ}
→ Γ ⊢ true bool
false : ∀ {Γ}
→ Γ ⊢ false bool
if_then_else_ : ∀ {Γ} {s} {t} {u} {A}
→ Γ ⊢ s bool
→ Γ ⊢ t A
→ Γ ⊢ u A
→ Γ ⊢ if s then t else u A
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
infix 1 _⊢__
\end{code}
</div>
### Examples
\begin{code}
typing-example1 : ∅ ⊢ idB bool ⇒ bool
typing-example1 = abs (var x refl)
\end{code}
Another example:
$$\varnothing\vdash \lambda x:A. \lambda y:A\rightarrow A. y\;(y\;x) : A\rightarrow (A\rightarrow A)\rightarrow A$$.
\begin{code}
typing-example2 : ∅ ⊢
(abs x bool
(abs y (bool ⇒ bool)
(app (var y)
(app (var y) (var x)))))
(bool ⇒ (bool ⇒ bool) ⇒ bool)
typing-example2 =
(abs
(abs
(app (var y refl)
(app (var y refl) (var x refl) ))))
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 2 stars (typing-example3)
Formally prove the following typing derivation holds:
$$\exists A, \varnothing\vdash \lambda x:bool\rightarrow B. \lambda y:bool\rightarrow bool. \lambda z:bool. y\;(x\;z) : A$$.
\begin{code}
postulate
typing-example3 : ∃ λ A → ∅ ⊢
(abs x (bool ⇒ bool)
(abs y (bool ⇒ bool)
(abs z bool
(app (var y) (app (var x) (var z)))))) A
\end{code}
We can also show that terms are _not_ typable. For example, let's
formally check that there is no typing derivation assigning a type
to the term $$\lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x\;y$$---i.e.,
$$\nexists A, \varnothing\vdash \lambda x:bool. \lambda y:bool. x\;y : A$$.
\begin{code}
postulate
typing-nonexample1 : ∄ λ A → ∅ ⊢
(abs x bool
(abs y bool
(app (var x) (var y)))) A
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 3 stars, optional (typing-nonexample2)
Another nonexample:
$$\nexists A, \exists B, \varnothing\vdash \lambda x:A. x\;x : B$$.
\begin{code}
postulate
typing-nonexample2 : ∄ λ A → ∃ λ B → ∅ ⊢
(abs x B (app (var x) (var x))) A
\end{code}

5497
Stlc.md Normal file

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff

777
StlcProp.lagda Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,777 @@
---
title : "StlcProp: Properties of STLC"
layout : default
hide-implicit : false
extra-script : [agda-extra-script.html]
extra-style : [agda-extra-style.html]
permalink : "sf/StlcProp.html"
---
\begin{code}
module StlcProp where
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
open import Function using (_∘_)
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
open import Data.Maybe using (Maybe; just; nothing)
open import Data.Product using (∃; ∃₂; _,_; ,_)
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_; Dec; yes; no)
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; _≢_; refl)
open import Maps
open import Stlc
\end{code}
</div>
# Properties of STLC
In this chapter, we develop the fundamental theory of the Simply
Typed Lambda Calculus -- in particular, the type safety
theorem.
## Canonical Forms
As we saw for the simple calculus in the [Stlc](Stlc.html) chapter, the
first step in establishing basic properties of reduction and types
is to identify the possible _canonical forms_ (i.e., well-typed
closed values) belonging to each type. For $$bool$$, these are the boolean
values $$true$$ and $$false$$. For arrow types, the canonical forms
are lambda-abstractions.
\begin{code}
CanonicalForms : Term → Type → Set
CanonicalForms t bool = t ≡ true ⊎ t ≡ false
CanonicalForms t (A ⇒ B) = ∃₂ λ x t → t ≡ abs x A t
canonicalForms : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t A → Value t → CanonicalForms t A
canonicalForms (abs t) abs = _ , _ , refl
canonicalForms true true = inj₁ refl
canonicalForms false false = inj₂ refl
\end{code}
## Progress
As before, the _progress_ theorem tells us that closed, well-typed
terms are not stuck: either a well-typed term is a value, or it
can take a reduction step. The proof is a relatively
straightforward extension of the progress proof we saw in the
[Stlc](Stlc.html) chapter. We'll give the proof in English first,
then the formal version.
\begin{code}
progress : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t A → Value t ⊎ ∃ λ t → t ==> t
\end{code}
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : A$$.
- The last rule of the derivation cannot be `var`,
since a variable is never well typed in an empty context.
- The `true`, `false`, and `abs` cases are trivial, since in
each of these cases we can see by inspecting the rule that $$t$$
is a value.
- If the last rule of the derivation is `app`, then $$t$$ has the
form $$t_1\;t_2$$ for som e$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$, where we know that
$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ are also well typed in the empty context; in particular,
there exists a type $$B$$ such that $$\vdash t_1 : A\to T$$ and
$$\vdash t_2 : B$$. By the induction hypothesis, either $$t_1$$ is a
value or it can take a reduction step.
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then consider $$t_2$$, which by the other
induction hypothesis must also either be a value or take a step.
- Suppose $$t_2$$ is a value. Since $$t_1$$ is a value with an
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence $$t_1\;t_2$$
can take a step by `red`.
- Otherwise, $$t_2$$ can take a step, and hence so can $$t_1\;t_2$$
by `app2`.
- If $$t_1$$ can take a step, then so can $$t_1 t_2$$ by `app1`.
- If the last rule of the derivation is `if`, then $$t = \text{if }t_1
\text{ then }t_2\text{ else }t_3$$, where $$t_1$$ has type $$bool$$. By
the IH, $$t_1$$ either is a value or takes a step.
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then since it has type $$bool$$ it must be
either $$true$$ or $$false$$. If it is $$true$$, then $$t$$ steps
to $$t_2$$; otherwise it steps to $$t_3$$.
- Otherwise, $$t_1$$ takes a step, and therefore so does $$t$$ (by `if`).
\begin{code}
progress (var x ())
progress true = inj₁ true
progress false = inj₁ false
progress (abs tA) = inj₁ abs
progress (app t₁A⇒B t₂B)
with progress t₁A⇒B
... | inj₂ (_ , t₁⇒t₁) = inj₂ (_ , app1 t₁⇒t₁)
... | inj₁ v₁
with progress t₂B
... | inj₂ (_ , t₂⇒t₂) = inj₂ (_ , app2 v₁ t₂⇒t₂)
... | inj₁ v₂
with canonicalForms t₁A⇒B v₁
... | (_ , _ , refl) = inj₂ (_ , red v₂)
progress (if t₁bool then t₂A else t₃A)
with progress t₁bool
... | inj₂ (_ , t₁⇒t₁) = inj₂ (_ , if t₁⇒t₁)
... | inj₁ v₁
with canonicalForms t₁bool v₁
... | inj₁ refl = inj₂ (_ , iftrue)
... | inj₂ refl = inj₂ (_ , iffalse)
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 3 stars, optional (progress_from_term_ind)
Show that progress can also be proved by induction on terms
instead of induction on typing derivations.
\begin{code}
postulate
progress : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t A → Value t ⊎ ∃ λ t → t ==> t
\end{code}
## Preservation
The other half of the type soundness property is the preservation
of types during reduction. For this, we need to develop some
technical machinery for reasoning about variables and
substitution. Working from top to bottom (from the high-level
property we are actually interested in to the lowest-level
technical lemmas that are needed by various cases of the more
interesting proofs), the story goes like this:
- The _preservation theorem_ is proved by induction on a typing
derivation, pretty much as we did in the [Stlc](Stlc.html)
chapter. The one case that is significantly different is the
one for the $$red$$ rule, whose definition uses the substitution
operation. To see that this step preserves typing, we need to
know that the substitution itself does. So we prove a...
- _substitution lemma_, stating that substituting a (closed)
term $$s$$ for a variable $$x$$ in a term $$t$$ preserves the type
of $$t$$. The proof goes by induction on the form of $$t$$ and
requires looking at all the different cases in the definition
of substitition. This time, the tricky cases are the ones for
variables and for function abstractions. In both cases, we
discover that we need to take a term $$s$$ that has been shown
to be well-typed in some context $$\Gamma$$ and consider the same
term $$s$$ in a slightly different context $$\Gamma'$$. For this
we prove a...
- _context invariance_ lemma, showing that typing is preserved
under "inessential changes" to the context $$\Gamma$$ -- in
particular, changes that do not affect any of the free
variables of the term. And finally, for this, we need a
careful definition of...
- the _free variables_ of a term -- i.e., those variables
mentioned in a term and not in the scope of an enclosing
function abstraction binding a variable of the same name.
To make Agda happy, we need to formalize the story in the opposite
order...
### Free Occurrences
A variable $$x$$ _appears free in_ a term _t_ if $$t$$ contains some
occurrence of $$x$$ that is not under an abstraction labeled $$x$$.
For example:
- $$y$$ appears free, but $$x$$ does not, in $$\lambda x : A\to B. x\;y$$
- both $$x$$ and $$y$$ appear free in $$(\lambda x:A\to B. x\;y) x$$
- no variables appear free in $$\lambda x:A\to B. \lambda y:A. x\;y$$
Formally:
\begin{code}
data _FreeIn_ (x : Id) : Term → Set where
var : x FreeIn var x
abs : ∀ {y A t} → y ≢ x → x FreeIn t → x FreeIn abs y A t
app1 : ∀ {t₁ t₂} → x FreeIn t₁ → x FreeIn app t₁ t₂
app2 : ∀ {t₁ t₂} → x FreeIn t₂ → x FreeIn app t₁ t₂
if1 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₁ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
if2 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₂ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
if3 : ∀ {t₁ t₂ t₃} → x FreeIn t₃ → x FreeIn (if t₁ then t₂ else t₃)
\end{code}
A term in which no variables appear free is said to be _closed_.
\begin{code}
Closed : Term → Set
Closed t = ∀ {x} → ¬ (x FreeIn t)
\end{code}
#### Exercise: 1 star (free-in)
If the definition of `_FreeIn_` is not crystal clear to
you, it is a good idea to take a piece of paper and write out the
rules in informal inference-rule notation. (Although it is a
rather low-level, technical definition, understanding it is
crucial to understanding substitution and its properties, which
are really the crux of the lambda-calculus.)
### Substitution
To prove that substitution preserves typing, we first need a
technical lemma connecting free variables and typing contexts: If
a variable $$x$$ appears free in a term $$t$$, and if we know $$t$$ is
well typed in context $$\Gamma$$, then it must be the case that
$$\Gamma$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
\begin{code}
freeInCtxt : ∀ {x t A Γ} → x FreeIn t → Γ ⊢ t A → ∃ λ B → Γ x ≡ just B
\end{code}
_Proof_: We show, by induction on the proof that $$x$$ appears
free in $$t$$, that, for all contexts $$\Gamma$$, if $$t$$ is well
typed under $$\Gamma$$, then $$\Gamma$$ assigns some type to $$x$$.
- If the last rule used was `var`, then $$t = x$$, and from
the assumption that $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$ we have
immediately that $$\Gamma$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
- If the last rule used was `app1`, then $$t = t_1\;t_2$$ and $$x$$
appears free in $$t_1$$. Since $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$,
we can see from the typing rules that $$t_1$$ must also be, and
the IH then tells us that $$\Gamma$$ assigns $$x$$ a type.
- Almost all the other cases are similar: $$x$$ appears free in a
subterm of $$t$$, and since $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$, we
know the subterm of $$t$$ in which $$x$$ appears is well typed
under $$\Gamma$$ as well, and the IH gives us exactly the
conclusion we want.
- The only remaining case is `abs`. In this case $$t =
\lambda y:A.t'$$, and $$x$$ appears free in $$t'$$; we also know that
$$x$$ is different from $$y$$. The difference from the previous
cases is that whereas $$t$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$, its
body $$t'$$ is well typed under $$(\Gamma, y:A)$$, so the IH
allows us to conclude that $$x$$ is assigned some type by the
extended context $$(\Gamma, y:A)$$. To conclude that $$\Gamma$$
assigns a type to $$x$$, we appeal the decidable equality for names
`_≟_`, noting that $$x$$ and $$y$$ are different variables.
\begin{code}
freeInCtxt var (var _ xA) = (_ , xA)
freeInCtxt (app1 x∈t₁) (app t₁A _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₁ t₁A
freeInCtxt (app2 x∈t₂) (app _ t₂A) = freeInCtxt x∈t₂ t₂A
freeInCtxt (if1 x∈t₁) (if t₁A then _ else _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₁ t₁A
freeInCtxt (if2 x∈t₂) (if _ then t₂A else _ ) = freeInCtxt x∈t₂ t₂A
freeInCtxt (if3 x∈t₃) (if _ then _ else t₃A) = freeInCtxt x∈t₃ t₃A
freeInCtxt {x} (abs {y} y≠x x∈t) (abs tB)
with freeInCtxt x∈t tB
... | xA
with y ≟ x
... | yes y=x = ⊥-elim (y≠x y=x)
... | no _ = xA
\end{code}
Next, we'll need the fact that any term $$t$$ which is well typed in
the empty context is closed (it has no free variables).
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (∅⊢-closed)
\begin{code}
postulate
∅⊢-closed : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t A → Closed t
\end{code}
<div class="hidden">
\begin{code}
∅⊢-closed : ∀ {t A} → ∅ ⊢ t A → Closed t
∅⊢-closed (var x ())
∅⊢-closed (app t₁A⇒B t₂A) (app1 x∈t₁) = ∅⊢-closed t₁A⇒B x∈t₁
∅⊢-closed (app t₁A⇒B t₂A) (app2 x∈t₂) = ∅⊢-closed t₂A x∈t₂
∅⊢-closed true ()
∅⊢-closed false ()
∅⊢-closed (if t₁bool then t₂A else t₃A) (if1 x∈t₁) = ∅⊢-closed t₁bool x∈t₁
∅⊢-closed (if t₁bool then t₂A else t₃A) (if2 x∈t₂) = ∅⊢-closed t₂A x∈t₂
∅⊢-closed (if t₁bool then t₂A else t₃A) (if3 x∈t₃) = ∅⊢-closed t₃A x∈t₃
∅⊢-closed (abs {x = x} tA) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t) with freeInCtxt y∈t tA
∅⊢-closed (abs {x = x} tA) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t) | A , yA with x ≟ y
∅⊢-closed (abs {x = x} tA) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t) | A , yA | yes x=y = x≠y x=y
∅⊢-closed (abs {x = x} tA) {y} (abs x≠y y∈t) | A , () | no _
\end{code}
</div>
Sometimes, when we have a proof $$\Gamma\vdash t : A$$, we will need to
replace $$\Gamma$$ by a different context $$\Gamma'$$. When is it safe
to do this? Intuitively, it must at least be the case that
$$\Gamma'$$ assigns the same types as $$\Gamma$$ to all the variables
that appear free in $$t$$. In fact, this is the only condition that
is needed.
\begin{code}
replaceCtxt : ∀ {Γ Γ′ t A}
→ (∀ {x} → x FreeIn t → Γ x ≡ Γ′ x)
→ Γ ⊢ t A
→ Γ′ ⊢ t A
\end{code}
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of
$$\Gamma \vdash t \in T$$.
- If the last rule in the derivation was `var`, then $$t = x$$
and $$\Gamma x = T$$. By assumption, $$\Gamma' x = T$$ as well, and
hence $$\Gamma' \vdash t : T$$ by `var`.
- If the last rule was `abs`, then $$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, with
$$T = A\to B$$ and $$\Gamma, y : A \vdash t' : B$$. The
induction hypothesis is that, for any context $$\Gamma''$$, if
$$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma''$$ assign the same types to all the
free variables in $$t'$$, then $$t'$$ has type $$B$$ under
$$\Gamma''$$. Let $$\Gamma'$$ be a context which agrees with
$$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t$$; we must show
$$\Gamma' \vdash \lambda y:A. t' : A\to B$$.
By $$abs$$, it suffices to show that $$\Gamma', y:A \vdash t' : t'$$.
By the IH (setting $$\Gamma'' = \Gamma', y:A$$), it suffices to show
that $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$ agree on all the variables
that appear free in $$t'$$.
Any variable occurring free in $$t'$$ must be either $$y$$ or
some other variable. $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$
clearly agree on $$y$$. Otherwise, note that any variable other
than $$y$$ that occurs free in $$t'$$ also occurs free in
$$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, and by assumption $$\Gamma$$ and
$$\Gamma'$$ agree on all such variables; hence so do $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and
$$\Gamma', y:A$$.
- If the last rule was `app`, then $$t = t_1\;t_2$$, with
$$\Gamma \vdash t_1 : A\to T$$ and $$\Gamma \vdash t_2 : A$$.
One induction hypothesis states that for all contexts $$\Gamma'$$,
if $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with $$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t_1$$,
then $$t_1$$ has type $$A\to T$$ under $$\Gamma'$$; there is a similar IH
for $$t_2$$. We must show that $$t_1\;t_2$$ also has type $$T$$ under
$$\Gamma'$$, given the assumption that $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with
$$\Gamma$$ on all the free variables in $$t_1\;t_2$$. By `app`, it
suffices to show that $$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ each have the same type
under $$\Gamma'$$ as under $$\Gamma$$. But all free variables in
$$t_1$$ are also free in $$t_1\;t_2$$, and similarly for $$t_2$$;
hence the desired result follows from the induction hypotheses.
\begin{code}
replaceCtxt f (var x xA) rewrite f var = var x xA
replaceCtxt f (app t₁A⇒B t₂A)
= app (replaceCtxt (f ∘ app1) t₁A⇒B) (replaceCtxt (f ∘ app2) t₂A)
replaceCtxt {Γ} {Γ′} f (abs {.Γ} {x} {A} {B} {t} tB)
= abs (replaceCtxt f tB)
where
f : ∀ {y} → y FreeIn t → (Γ , x A) y ≡ (Γ′ , x A) y
f {y} y∈t with x ≟ y
... | yes _ = refl
... | no x≠y = f (abs x≠y y∈t)
replaceCtxt _ true = true
replaceCtxt _ false = false
replaceCtxt f (if t₁bool then t₂A else t₃A)
= if replaceCtxt (f ∘ if1) t₁bool
then replaceCtxt (f ∘ if2) t₂A
else replaceCtxt (f ∘ if3) t₃A
\end{code}
Now we come to the conceptual heart of the proof that reduction
preserves types -- namely, the observation that _substitution_
preserves types.
Formally, the so-called _Substitution Lemma_ says this: Suppose we
have a term $$t$$ with a free variable $$x$$, and suppose we've been
able to assign a type $$T$$ to $$t$$ under the assumption that $$x$$ has
some type $$U$$. Also, suppose that we have some other term $$v$$ and
that we've shown that $$v$$ has type $$U$$. Then, since $$v$$ satisfies
the assumption we made about $$x$$ when typing $$t$$, we should be
able to substitute $$v$$ for each of the occurrences of $$x$$ in $$t$$
and obtain a new term that still has type $$T$$.
_Lemma_: If $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$ and $$\vdash v : U$$, then
$$\Gamma \vdash [x:=v]t : T$$.
\begin{code}
[:=]-preserves-⊢ : ∀ {Γ x A t v B}
→ ∅ ⊢ v A
→ Γ , x A ⊢ t B
→ Γ , x A ⊢ [ x := v ] t B
\end{code}
One technical subtlety in the statement of the lemma is that
we assign $$v$$ the type $$U$$ in the _empty_ context -- in other
words, we assume $$v$$ is closed. This assumption considerably
simplifies the $$abs$$ case of the proof (compared to assuming
$$\Gamma \vdash v : U$$, which would be the other reasonable assumption
at this point) because the context invariance lemma then tells us
that $$v$$ has type $$U$$ in any context at all -- we don't have to
worry about free variables in $$v$$ clashing with the variable being
introduced into the context by $$abs$$.
The substitution lemma can be viewed as a kind of "commutation"
property. Intuitively, it says that substitution and typing can
be done in either order: we can either assign types to the terms
$$t$$ and $$v$$ separately (under suitable contexts) and then combine
them using substitution, or we can substitute first and then
assign a type to $$ $$x:=v$$ t $$ -- the result is the same either
way.
_Proof_: We show, by induction on $$t$$, that for all $$T$$ and
$$\Gamma$$, if $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$ and $$\vdash v : U$$, then $$\Gamma
\vdash $$x:=v$$t : T$$.
- If $$t$$ is a variable there are two cases to consider,
depending on whether $$t$$ is $$x$$ or some other variable.
- If $$t = x$$, then from the fact that $$\Gamma, x:U \vdash x :
T$$ we conclude that $$U = T$$. We must show that $$$$x:=v$$x =
v$$ has type $$T$$ under $$\Gamma$$, given the assumption that
$$v$$ has type $$U = T$$ under the empty context. This
follows from context invariance: if a closed term has type
$$T$$ in the empty context, it has that type in any context.
- If $$t$$ is some variable $$y$$ that is not equal to $$x$$, then
we need only note that $$y$$ has the same type under $$\Gamma,
x:U$$ as under $$\Gamma$$.
- If $$t$$ is an abstraction $$\lambda y:T_11. t_12$$, then the IH tells us,
for all $$\Gamma'$$ and $$T'$$, that if $$\Gamma',x:U \vdash t_12 : T'$$
and $$\vdash v : U$$, then $$\Gamma' \vdash $$x:=v$$t_12 : T'$$.
The substitution in the conclusion behaves differently
depending on whether $$x$$ and $$y$$ are the same variable.
First, suppose $$x = y$$. Then, by the definition of
substitution, $$[x:=v]t = t$$, so we just need to show $$\Gamma \vdash
t : T$$. But we know $$\Gamma,x:U \vdash t : T$$, and, since $$y$$
does not appear free in $$\lambda y:T_11. t_12$$, the context invariance
lemma yields $$\Gamma \vdash t : T$$.
Second, suppose $$x <> y$$. We know $$\Gamma,x:U,y:T_11 \vdash t_12 :
T_12$$ by inversion of the typing relation, from which
$$\Gamma,y:T_11,x:U \vdash t_12 : T_12$$ follows by the context
invariance lemma, so the IH applies, giving us $$\Gamma,y:T_11 \vdash
$$x:=v$$t_12 : T_12$$. By $$abs$$, $$\Gamma \vdash \lambda y:T_11. $$x:=v$$t_12
: T_11→T_12$$, and by the definition of substitution (noting
that $$x <> y$$), $$\Gamma \vdash \lambda y:T_11. $$x:=v$$t_12 : T_11→T_12$$ as
required.
- If $$t$$ is an application $$t_1 t_2$$, the result follows
straightforwardly from the definition of substitution and the
induction hypotheses.
- The remaining cases are similar to the application case.
One more technical note: This proof is a rare case where an
induction on terms, rather than typing derivations, yields a
simpler argument. The reason for this is that the assumption
$$update Gamma x U \vdash t : T$$ is not completely generic, in the
sense that one of the "slots" in the typing relation -- namely the
context -- is not just a variable, and this means that Agda's
native induction tactic does not give us the induction hypothesis
that we want. It is possible to work around this, but the needed
generalization is a little tricky. The term $$t$$, on the other
hand, _is_ completely generic.
\begin{code}
[:=]-preserves-⊢ {Γ} {x} vA (var y y∈Γ) with x ≟ y
... | yes x=y = {!!}
... | no x≠y = {!!}
[:=]-preserves-⊢ vA (abs tB) = {!!}
[:=]-preserves-⊢ vA (app t₁A⇒B t₂A) =
app ([:=]-preserves-⊢ vA t₁A⇒B) ([:=]-preserves-⊢ vA t₂A)
[:=]-preserves-⊢ vA true = true
[:=]-preserves-⊢ vA false = false
[:=]-preserves-⊢ vA (if t₁bool then t₂B else t₃B) =
if [:=]-preserves-⊢ vA t₁bool
then [:=]-preserves-⊢ vA t₂B
else [:=]-preserves-⊢ vA t₃B
\end{code}
### Main Theorem
We now have the tools we need to prove preservation: if a closed
term $$t$$ has type $$T$$ and takes a step to $$t'$$, then $$t'$$
is also a closed term with type $$T$$. In other words, the small-step
reduction relation preserves types.
Theorem preservation : forall t t' T,
empty \vdash t : T →
t ==> t' →
empty \vdash t' : T.
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : T$$.
- We can immediately rule out $$var$$, $$abs$$, $$T_True$$, and
$$T_False$$ as the final rules in the derivation, since in each of
these cases $$t$$ cannot take a step.
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$app$$, then $$t = t_1
t_2$$. There are three cases to consider, one for each rule that
could have been used to show that $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step to $$t'$$.
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sapp1$$, with $$t_1$$ stepping to
$$t_1'$$, then by the IH $$t_1'$$ has the same type as $$t_1$$, and
hence $$t_1' t_2$$ has the same type as $$t_1 t_2$$.
- The $$Sapp2$$ case is similar.
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sred$$, then $$t_1 =
\lambda x:T_11.t_12$$ and $$t_1 t_2$$ steps to $$$$x:=t_2$$t_12$$; the
desired result now follows from the fact that substitution
preserves types.
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$if$$, then $$t = if t_1
then t_2 else t_3$$, and there are again three cases depending on
how $$t$$ steps.
- If $$t$$ steps to $$t_2$$ or $$t_3$$, the result is immediate, since
$$t_2$$ and $$t_3$$ have the same type as $$t$$.
- Otherwise, $$t$$ steps by $$Sif$$, and the desired conclusion
follows directly from the induction hypothesis.
Proof with eauto.
remember (@empty ty) as Gamma.
intros t t' T HT. generalize dependent t'.
induction HT;
intros t' HE; subst Gamma; subst;
try solve $$inversion HE; subst; auto$$.
- (* app
inversion HE; subst...
(* Most of the cases are immediate by induction,
and $$eauto$$ takes care of them
+ (* Sred
apply substitution_preserves_typing with T_11...
inversion HT_1...
Qed.
#### Exercise: 2 stars, recommended (subject_expansion_stlc)
An exercise in the $$Stlc$$$$sf/Stlc.html$$ chapter asked about the subject
expansion property for the simple language of arithmetic and
boolean expressions. Does this property hold for STLC? That is,
is it always the case that, if $$t ==> t'$$ and $$has_type t' T$$,
then $$empty \vdash t : T$$? If so, prove it. If not, give a
counter-example not involving conditionals.
(* FILL IN HERE
## Type Soundness
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (type_soundness)
Put progress and preservation together and show that a well-typed
term can _never_ reach a stuck state.
Definition stuck (t:tm) : Prop :=
(normal_form step) t /\ ~ value t.
Corollary soundness : forall t t' T,
empty \vdash t : T →
t ==>* t' →
~(stuck t').
Proof.
intros t t' T Hhas_type Hmulti. unfold stuck.
intros $$Hnf Hnot_val$$. unfold normal_form in Hnf.
induction Hmulti.
(* FILL IN HERE Admitted.
(** $$$$
## Uniqueness of Types
#### Exercise: 3 stars (types_unique)
Another nice property of the STLC is that types are unique: a
given term (in a given context) has at most one type.
Formalize this statement and prove it.
(* FILL IN HERE
(** $$$$
## Additional Exercises
#### Exercise: 1 star (progress_preservation_statement)
Without peeking at their statements above, write down the progress
and preservation theorems for the simply typed lambda-calculus.
$$$$
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation1)
Suppose we add a new term $$zap$$ with the following reduction rule
--------- (ST_Zap)
t ==> zap
and the following typing rule:
---------------- (T_Zap)
Gamma \vdash zap : T
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of these rules? For each property, write either
"remains true" or "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation2)
Suppose instead that we add a new term $$foo$$ with the following
reduction rules:
----------------- (ST_Foo1)
(\lambda x:A. x) ==> foo
------------ (ST_Foo2)
foo ==> true
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation3)
Suppose instead that we remove the rule $$Sapp1$$ from the $$step$$
relation. Which of the following properties of the STLC remain
true in the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation4)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the
reduction relation:
---------------------------------- (ST_FunnyIfTrue)
(if true then t_1 else t_2) ==> true
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation5)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing
relation:
Gamma \vdash t_1 : bool→bool→bool
Gamma \vdash t_2 : bool
------------------------------ (T_FunnyApp)
Gamma \vdash t_1 t_2 : bool
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation6)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing
relation:
Gamma \vdash t_1 : bool
Gamma \vdash t_2 : bool
--------------------- (T_FunnyApp')
Gamma \vdash t_1 t_2 : bool
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (stlc_variation7)
Suppose we add the following new rule to the typing relation
of the STLC:
------------------- (T_FunnyAbs)
\vdash \lambda x:bool.t : bool
Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in
the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
false, give a counterexample.
- Determinism of $$step$$
- Progress
- Preservation
### Exercise: STLC with Arithmetic
To see how the STLC might function as the core of a real
programming language, let's extend it with a concrete base
type of numbers and some constants and primitive
operators.
To types, we add a base type of natural numbers (and remove
booleans, for brevity).
Inductive ty : Type :=
| TArrow : ty → ty → ty
| TNat : ty.
To terms, we add natural number constants, along with
successor, predecessor, multiplication, and zero-testing.
Inductive tm : Type :=
| tvar : id → tm
| tapp : tm → tm → tm
| tabs : id → ty → tm → tm
| tnat : nat → tm
| tsucc : tm → tm
| tpred : tm → tm
| tmult : tm → tm → tm
| tif0 : tm → tm → tm → tm.
#### Exercise: 4 stars (stlc_arith)
Finish formalizing the definition and properties of the STLC extended
with arithmetic. Specifically:
- Copy the whole development of STLC that we went through above (from
the definition of values through the Type Soundness theorem), and
paste it into the file at this point.
- Extend the definitions of the $$subst$$ operation and the $$step$$
relation to include appropriate clauses for the arithmetic operators.
- Extend the proofs of all the properties (up to $$soundness$$) of
the original STLC to deal with the new syntactic forms. Make
sure Agda accepts the whole file.

5279
StlcProp.md Normal file

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff