added Properties

This commit is contained in:
wadler 2018-01-01 15:45:01 -02:00
parent d83f9539a1
commit 7c7ecbe950
5 changed files with 172 additions and 19808 deletions

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff

File diff suppressed because it is too large Load diff

View file

@ -127,7 +127,7 @@ Let's look again at the definition of natural numbers:
Wait a minute! The second line defines natural numbers
in terms of natural numbers. How can that posssibly be allowed?
Isn't this as useless as claiming `Brexit means Brexit`?
Isn't this as useless as claiming "Brexit means Brexit"?
In fact, it is possible to assign our definition a meaning without
resorting to any unpermitted circularities. Furthermore, we can do so
@ -296,25 +296,25 @@ numbers. Such a definition is called *well founded*.
For example, let's add two and three.
2 + 3
= { expand shorthand }
= (is shorthand for)
(suc (suc zero)) + (suc (suc (suc zero)))
= { by (ii) }
= (ii)
suc ((suc zero) + (suc (suc (suc zero))))
= { by (ii) }
= (ii)
suc (suc (zero + (suc (suc (suc zero)))))
= { by (i) }
= (i)
suc (suc (suc (suc (suc zero))))
= { compress longhand }
= (is longhand for)
5
We can write this more compactly by only expanding shorthand as needed.
2 + 3
= { by (ii) }
= (ii)
suc (1 + 3)
= { by (ii) }
= (ii)
suc (suc (0 + 3))
= { by (i) }
= (i)
suc (suc 3)
=
5
@ -358,11 +358,11 @@ larger numbers is defined in terms of multiplication of smaller numbers.
For example, let's multiply two and three.
2 * 3
= {by (iv)}
= (iv)
3 + (1 * 3)
= {by (iv)}
= (iv)
3 + (3 + (0 * 3))
= {by (iii)}
= (iii)
3 + (3 + 0)
=
6
@ -418,22 +418,22 @@ small numbers.
For example, let's subtract two from three.
3 ∸ 2
= {by (ix)}
= (ix)
2 ∸ 1
= {by (ix)}
= (ix)
1 ∸ 0
= {by (vii)}
= (vii)
1
We did not use equation (viii) at all, but it will be required
if we try to subtract a smaller number from a larger one.
2 ∸ 3
= {by (ix)}
= (ix)
1 ∸ 2
= {by (ix)}
= (ix)
0 ∸ 1
= {by (viii)}
= (viii)
0
**Exercise** Compute `5 ∸ 3` and `3 ∸ 5` by the same technique.

154
src/Properties.lagda Normal file
View file

@ -0,0 +1,154 @@
---
title : "Properties: Proof by Induction"
layout : page
permalink : /Properties
---
Now that we've defined the naturals and operations upon them,
our next step is to learn how to prove properties that they
satisfy. Unsurprisingly, properties of *inductive datatypes*
are proved by *induction*.
## Imports
Each chapter will begin with a list of the imports we require from the
Agda standard library. We will, of course, require the naturals;
everything in the previous chapter is also found in the library module
`Data.Nat`, so we import the required definitions from there. We also
require propositional equality.
\begin{code}
open import Data.Nat using (; zero; suc)
open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; refl)
\end{code}
Each import consists of the keywords `open` and `import`, followed by
the module name, followed by the keyword `using`, followed by the
names of each identifier imported from the module, surrounded by
parentheses and separated by semicolons.
## Associativity
One property of addition is that it is *associative*, that is that the
order of the parentheses does not matter:
(m + n) + p ≡ m + (n + p)
We write `=` in an Agda definition, whereas we write `≡` for an
equality we are trying to prove. Here `m`, `n`, and `p` are variables
that range over all natural numbers.
We can test the proposition by choosing specific numbers for the three
variables.
(3 + 4) + 5
7 + 5
12
3 + 9
3 + (4 + 5)
Here we have displayed the computation in tabular form, one term to a
line. We will often use such a form. It is often easiest to read
such computations from the top down until one reaches the simplest
possible term (in this case, 12), and then from the bottom up until
one reaches the same term.
We could go on testing the proposition by choosing other numbers, but---since there are an infinite number of naturals---we will never finish.
To prove a property of natural numbers by induction, we need to prove two things.
First, we prove the property holds for `zero`, and secondly we prove that if
the property holds for an arbitrary natural `m` then it also holds for `suc m`.
If we write `P m` for a property of `m`, then we can write out the principle
of induction as an inference rule:
P zero
∀ (m : ) → P m → P (suc m)
-----------------------------
∀ (m : ) → P m
Let's unpack this rule. The first hypothesis states
that property `P` holds for `zero`. The second hypothesis states that for all natural
numbers `m`, if `P` holds for `m` then `P` also holds for `suc m`. The conclusion
states that for all natural numbers `m` we have that `P` holds for `m`.
We call the first hypothesis the *base case*; it requires we show `P zero`.
We call the second hypothesis the *inductive case*; it requires we assume `P m`, which
we call the *induction hypothesis*, and use it to show `P (suc m)`.
In order to prove associativity, we take `P m` to be the property
(m + n) + p ≡ m + (n + p)
Then the appropriate instance of the inference rule becomes:
(zero + n) + p ≡ zero + (n + p)
∀ (m : ) → (m + n) + p ≡ m + (n + p) → (suc m + n) + p ≡ (suc m + n) + p
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------
∀ (m : ) → (m + n) + p ≡ m + (n + p)
In the inference rule, `n` and `p` are any arbitary natural numbers, so when we
are done with the proof we know it holds for any `n` and `p` as well as any `m`.
Recall the definition of addition.
\begin{code}
_+_ :
zero + n = n -- (i)
(suc m) + n = suc (m + n) -- (ii)
\end{code}
For the base case, we must show:
(zero + n) + p ≡ zero + (n + p)
By (i), both sides of the equation simplify to `n + p`, so it holds.
In tabular form, we write this as follows:
(zero + n) + p
≡ (i)
n + p
≡ (i)
zero + (n + p)
It is often easiest to read such proofs down from the top and up from
the bottom, meeting in the middle where the two terms are the same.
For the inductive case, we assume
(m + n) + p ≡ m + (n + p)
and must show
(suc m + n) + p ≡ (suc m + n) + p
By (ii), the left-hand side simplifies to `suc ((m + n) + p)` and the
right-hand side simplifies to `suc (m + (n + p))`, and the equality of
these follow from what we assumed. In tabular form:
(suc m + n) + p
≡ (ii)
suc (m + n) + p
≡ (ii)
suc ((m + n) + p)
≡ (induction hypothesis)
suc (m + (n + p))
≡ (ii)
suc m + (n + p)
## Unicode
In this chapter we use the following unicode.
≡ U+2261 IDENTICAL TO (\==)
∀ U+2200 FOR ALL (\forall)
λ U+03BB GREEK SMALL LETTER LAMBDA (\Gl, \lambda)