publish
This commit is contained in:
parent
77390abcc9
commit
9071f42d41
6 changed files with 7424 additions and 8658 deletions
6337
out/Maps.md
6337
out/Maps.md
File diff suppressed because it is too large
Load diff
874
out/Stlc.md
874
out/Stlc.md
File diff suppressed because it is too large
Load diff
8418
out/StlcProp.md
8418
out/StlcProp.md
File diff suppressed because it is too large
Load diff
|
@ -86,8 +86,6 @@ y = id "y"
|
|||
z = id "z"
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
## Extensionality
|
||||
|
||||
## Total Maps
|
||||
|
||||
Our main job in this chapter will be to build a definition of
|
||||
|
@ -112,8 +110,8 @@ TotalMap : Set → Set
|
|||
TotalMap A = Id → A
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
Intuitively, a total map over anfi element type $$A$$ _is_ just a
|
||||
function that can be used to look up ids, yielding $$A$$s.
|
||||
Intuitively, a total map over anfi element type `A` _is_ just a
|
||||
function that can be used to look up ids, yielding `A`s.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
module TotalMap where
|
||||
|
@ -129,10 +127,12 @@ applied to any id.
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
More interesting is the update function, which (as before) takes
|
||||
a map $$ρ$$, a key $$x$$, and a value $$v$$ and returns a new map that
|
||||
takes $$x$$ to $$v$$ and takes every other key to whatever $$ρ$$ does.
|
||||
a map `ρ`, a key `x`, and a value `v` and returns a new map that
|
||||
takes `x` to `v` and takes every other key to whatever `ρ` does.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
infixl 100 _,_↦_
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → TotalMap A → Id → A → TotalMap A
|
||||
(ρ , x ↦ v) y with x ≟ y
|
||||
... | yes x=y = v
|
||||
|
@ -140,30 +140,11 @@ takes $$x$$ to $$v$$ and takes every other key to whatever $$ρ$$ does.
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
This definition is a nice example of higher-order programming.
|
||||
The update function takes a _function_ $$ρ$$ and yields a new
|
||||
The update function takes a _function_ `ρ` and yields a new
|
||||
function that behaves like the desired map.
|
||||
|
||||
We define handy abbreviations for updating a map two, three, or four times.
|
||||
|
||||
<div class="note hidden">
|
||||
Wen: you don't actually need to define these, you can simply declare `_,_↦_` to
|
||||
be a left-associative infix operator with an `infixl` statement, and then you'll
|
||||
be able to just evaluate `M , x ↦ y , z ↦ w` as `(M , x ↦ y) , z ↦ w`.
|
||||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → TotalMap A → Id → A → Id → A → TotalMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ = (ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → TotalMap A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → TotalMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ , x₃ ↦ v₃ = ((ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂), x₃ ↦ v₃
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → TotalMap A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → TotalMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ , x₃ ↦ v₃ , x₄ ↦ v₄ = (((ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂), x₃ ↦ v₃), x₄ ↦ v₄
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
For example, we can build a map taking ids to naturals, where $$x$$
|
||||
maps to 42, $$y$$ maps to 69, and every other key maps to 0, as follows:
|
||||
For example, we can build a map taking ids to naturals, where `x`
|
||||
maps to 42, `y` maps to 69, and every other key maps to 0, as follows:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
ρ₀ : TotalMap ℕ
|
||||
|
@ -206,9 +187,9 @@ The `always` map returns its default element for all keys:
|
|||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-eq)
|
||||
Next, if we update a map $$ρ$$ at a key $$x$$ with a new value $$v$$
|
||||
and then look up $$x$$ in the map resulting from the update, we get
|
||||
back $$v$$:
|
||||
Next, if we update a map `ρ` at a key `x` with a new value `v`
|
||||
and then look up `x` in the map resulting from the update, we get
|
||||
back `v`:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
|
@ -227,9 +208,9 @@ back $$v$$:
|
|||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-neq)
|
||||
On the other hand, if we update a map $$m$$ at a key $$x$$ and
|
||||
then look up a _different_ key $$y$$ in the resulting map, we get
|
||||
the same result that $$m$$ would have given:
|
||||
On the other hand, if we update a map `m` at a key `x` and
|
||||
then look up a _different_ key `y` in the resulting map, we get
|
||||
the same result that `m` would have given:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
update-neq : ∀ {A} (ρ : TotalMap A) (x : Id) (v : A) (y : Id)
|
||||
|
@ -248,11 +229,11 @@ show two maps equal we will need to postulate extensionality.
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (update-shadow)
|
||||
If we update a map $$ρ$$ at a key $$x$$ with a value $$v$$ and then
|
||||
update again with the same key $$x$$ and another value $$w$$, the
|
||||
If we update a map `ρ` at a key `x` with a value `v` and then
|
||||
update again with the same key `x` and another value `w`, the
|
||||
resulting map behaves the same (gives the same result when applied
|
||||
to any key) as the simpler map obtained by performing just
|
||||
the second update on $$ρ$$:
|
||||
the second update on `ρ`:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
|
@ -274,9 +255,9 @@ the second update on $$ρ$$:
|
|||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (update-same)
|
||||
Prove the following theorem, which states that if we update a map $$ρ$$ to
|
||||
assign key $$x$$ the same value as it already has in $$ρ$$, then the
|
||||
result is equal to $$ρ$$:
|
||||
Prove the following theorem, which states that if we update a map `ρ` to
|
||||
assign key `x` the same value as it already has in `ρ`, then the
|
||||
result is equal to `ρ`:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
|
@ -297,7 +278,7 @@ result is equal to $$ρ$$:
|
|||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (update-permute)
|
||||
Prove one final property of the `update` function: If we update a map
|
||||
$$m$$ at two distinct keys, it doesn't matter in which order we do the
|
||||
`m` at two distinct keys, it doesn't matter in which order we do the
|
||||
updates.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
|
@ -354,21 +335,11 @@ module PartialMap where
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
infixl 100 _,_↦_
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} (ρ : PartialMap A) (x : Id) (v : A) → PartialMap A
|
||||
ρ , x ↦ v = TotalMap._,_↦_ ρ x (just v)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
As before, we define handy abbreviations for updating a map two, three, or four times.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → PartialMap A → Id → A → Id → A → PartialMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ = (ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → PartialMap A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → PartialMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ , x₃ ↦ v₃ = ((ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂), x₃ ↦ v₃
|
||||
|
||||
_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_,_↦_ : ∀ {A} → PartialMap A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → Id → A → PartialMap A
|
||||
ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁ , x₂ ↦ v₂ , x₃ ↦ v₃ , x₄ ↦ v₄ = (((ρ , x₁ ↦ v₁), x₂ ↦ v₂), x₃ ↦ v₃), x₄ ↦ v₄
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
We now lift all of the basic lemmas about total maps to partial maps.
|
||||
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -168,6 +168,8 @@ example₁ = ⟨ step₀ ⟩ >> ⟨ step₁ ⟩ >> ⟨ step₂ ⟩ >> ⟨ step
|
|||
Context : Set
|
||||
Context = PartialMap Type
|
||||
|
||||
infix 50 _⊢_∈_
|
||||
|
||||
data _⊢_∈_ : Context → Term → Type → Set where
|
||||
Ax : ∀ {Γ x A} →
|
||||
Γ x ≡ just A →
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -28,8 +28,8 @@ theorem.
|
|||
As we saw for the simple calculus in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }})
|
||||
chapter, the first step in establishing basic properties of reduction and types
|
||||
is to identify the possible _canonical forms_ (i.e., well-typed closed values)
|
||||
belonging to each type. For $$bool$$, these are the boolean values $$true$$ and
|
||||
$$false$$. For arrow types, the canonical forms are lambda-abstractions.
|
||||
belonging to each type. For `bool`, these are the boolean values `true` and
|
||||
`false`. For arrow types, the canonical forms are lambda-abstractions.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
data canonical_for_ : Term → Type → Set where
|
||||
|
@ -63,43 +63,43 @@ first, then the formal version.
|
|||
progress : ∀ {M A} → ∅ ⊢ M ∈ A → value M ⊎ ∃ λ N → M ⟹ N
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : A$$.
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of `\vdash t : A`.
|
||||
|
||||
- The last rule of the derivation cannot be `var`,
|
||||
since a variable is never well typed in an empty context.
|
||||
|
||||
- The `true`, `false`, and `abs` cases are trivial, since in
|
||||
each of these cases we can see by inspecting the rule that $$t$$
|
||||
each of these cases we can see by inspecting the rule that `t`
|
||||
is a value.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `app`, then $$t$$ has the
|
||||
form $$t_1\;t_2$$ for som e$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$, where we know that
|
||||
$$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ are also well typed in the empty context; in particular,
|
||||
there exists a type $$B$$ such that $$\vdash t_1 : A\to T$$ and
|
||||
$$\vdash t_2 : B$$. By the induction hypothesis, either $$t_1$$ is a
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `app`, then `t` has the
|
||||
form `t_1\;t_2` for som e`t_1` and `t_2`, where we know that
|
||||
`t_1` and `t_2` are also well typed in the empty context; in particular,
|
||||
there exists a type `B` such that `\vdash t_1 : A\to T` and
|
||||
`\vdash t_2 : B`. By the induction hypothesis, either `t_1` is a
|
||||
value or it can take a reduction step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then consider $$t_2$$, which by the other
|
||||
- If `t_1` is a value, then consider `t_2`, which by the other
|
||||
induction hypothesis must also either be a value or take a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- Suppose $$t_2$$ is a value. Since $$t_1$$ is a value with an
|
||||
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence $$t_1\;t_2$$
|
||||
- Suppose `t_2` is a value. Since `t_1` is a value with an
|
||||
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence `t_1\;t_2`
|
||||
can take a step by `red`.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t_2$$ can take a step, and hence so can $$t_1\;t_2$$
|
||||
- Otherwise, `t_2` can take a step, and hence so can `t_1\;t_2`
|
||||
by `app2`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ can take a step, then so can $$t_1 t_2$$ by `app1`.
|
||||
- If `t_1` can take a step, then so can `t_1 t_2` by `app1`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `if`, then $$t = \text{if }t_1
|
||||
\text{ then }t_2\text{ else }t_3$$, where $$t_1$$ has type $$bool$$. By
|
||||
the IH, $$t_1$$ either is a value or takes a step.
|
||||
- If the last rule of the derivation is `if`, then `t = \text{if }t_1
|
||||
\text{ then }t_2\text{ else }t_3`, where `t_1` has type `bool`. By
|
||||
the IH, `t_1` either is a value or takes a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1$$ is a value, then since it has type $$bool$$ it must be
|
||||
either $$true$$ or $$false$$. If it is $$true$$, then $$t$$ steps
|
||||
to $$t_2$$; otherwise it steps to $$t_3$$.
|
||||
- If `t_1` is a value, then since it has type `bool` it must be
|
||||
either `true` or `false`. If it is `true`, then `t` steps
|
||||
to `t_2`; otherwise it steps to `t_3`.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t_1$$ takes a step, and therefore so does $$t$$ (by `if`).
|
||||
- Otherwise, `t_1` takes a step, and therefore so does `t` (by `if`).
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
progress (Ax ())
|
||||
|
@ -141,23 +141,23 @@ interesting proofs), the story goes like this:
|
|||
- The _preservation theorem_ is proved by induction on a typing
|
||||
derivation, pretty much as we did in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }})
|
||||
chapter. The one case that is significantly different is the one for the
|
||||
$$red$$ rule, whose definition uses the substitution operation. To see that
|
||||
`red` rule, whose definition uses the substitution operation. To see that
|
||||
this step preserves typing, we need to know that the substitution itself
|
||||
does. So we prove a...
|
||||
|
||||
- _substitution lemma_, stating that substituting a (closed)
|
||||
term $$s$$ for a variable $$x$$ in a term $$t$$ preserves the type
|
||||
of $$t$$. The proof goes by induction on the form of $$t$$ and
|
||||
term `s` for a variable `x` in a term `t` preserves the type
|
||||
of `t`. The proof goes by induction on the form of `t` and
|
||||
requires looking at all the different cases in the definition
|
||||
of substitition. This time, the tricky cases are the ones for
|
||||
variables and for function abstractions. In both cases, we
|
||||
discover that we need to take a term $$s$$ that has been shown
|
||||
to be well-typed in some context $$\Gamma$$ and consider the same
|
||||
term $$s$$ in a slightly different context $$\Gamma'$$. For this
|
||||
discover that we need to take a term `s` that has been shown
|
||||
to be well-typed in some context `\Gamma` and consider the same
|
||||
term `s` in a slightly different context `\Gamma'`. For this
|
||||
we prove a...
|
||||
|
||||
- _context invariance_ lemma, showing that typing is preserved
|
||||
under "inessential changes" to the context $$\Gamma$$---in
|
||||
under "inessential changes" to the context `\Gamma`---in
|
||||
particular, changes that do not affect any of the free
|
||||
variables of the term. And finally, for this, we need a
|
||||
careful definition of...
|
||||
|
@ -172,13 +172,13 @@ order...
|
|||
|
||||
### Free Occurrences
|
||||
|
||||
A variable $$x$$ _appears free in_ a term $$M$$ if $$M$$ contains some
|
||||
occurrence of $$x$$ that is not under an abstraction over $$x$$.
|
||||
A variable `x` _appears free in_ a term `M` if `M` contains some
|
||||
occurrence of `x` that is not under an abstraction over `x`.
|
||||
For example:
|
||||
|
||||
- $$y$$ appears free, but $$x$$ does not, in $$λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ x ·ᵀ y$$
|
||||
- both $$x$$ and $$y$$ appear free in $$(λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ x ·ᵀ y) ·ᵀ x$$
|
||||
- no variables appear free in $$λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ (λᵀ y ∈ A ⇒ x ·ᵀ y)$$
|
||||
- `y` appears free, but `x` does not, in `λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ x ·ᵀ y`
|
||||
- both `x` and `y` appear free in `(λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ x ·ᵀ y) ·ᵀ x`
|
||||
- no variables appear free in `λᵀ x ∈ (A ⇒ B) ⇒ (λᵀ y ∈ A ⇒ x ·ᵀ y)`
|
||||
|
||||
Formally:
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -211,42 +211,42 @@ are really the crux of the lambda-calculus.)
|
|||
### Substitution
|
||||
To prove that substitution preserves typing, we first need a
|
||||
technical lemma connecting free variables and typing contexts: If
|
||||
a variable $$x$$ appears free in a term $$M$$, and if we know $$M$$ is
|
||||
well typed in context $$Γ$$, then it must be the case that
|
||||
$$Γ$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
|
||||
a variable `x` appears free in a term `M`, and if we know `M` is
|
||||
well typed in context `Γ`, then it must be the case that
|
||||
`Γ` assigns a type to `x`.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
freeLemma : ∀ {x M A Γ} → x FreeIn M → Γ ⊢ M ∈ A → ∃ λ B → Γ x ≡ just B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on the proof that $$x$$ appears
|
||||
free in $$P$$, that, for all contexts $$Γ$$, if $$P$$ is well
|
||||
typed under $$Γ$$, then $$Γ$$ assigns some type to $$x$$.
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on the proof that `x` appears
|
||||
free in `P`, that, for all contexts `Γ`, if `P` is well
|
||||
typed under `Γ`, then `Γ` assigns some type to `x`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `free-varᵀ`, then $$P = x$$, and from
|
||||
the assumption that $$M$$ is well typed under $$Γ$$ we have
|
||||
immediately that $$Γ$$ assigns a type to $$x$$.
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `free-varᵀ`, then `P = x`, and from
|
||||
the assumption that `M` is well typed under `Γ` we have
|
||||
immediately that `Γ` assigns a type to `x`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `free-·₁`, then $$P = L ·ᵀ M$$ and $$x$$
|
||||
appears free in $$L$$. Since $$L$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$,
|
||||
we can see from the typing rules that $$L$$ must also be, and
|
||||
the IH then tells us that $$Γ$$ assigns $$x$$ a type.
|
||||
- If the last rule used was `free-·₁`, then `P = L ·ᵀ M` and `x`
|
||||
appears free in `L`. Since `L` is well typed under `\Gamma`,
|
||||
we can see from the typing rules that `L` must also be, and
|
||||
the IH then tells us that `Γ` assigns `x` a type.
|
||||
|
||||
- Almost all the other cases are similar: $$x$$ appears free in a
|
||||
subterm of $$P$$, and since $$P$$ is well typed under $$Γ$$, we
|
||||
know the subterm of $$M$$ in which $$x$$ appears is well typed
|
||||
under $$Γ$$ as well, and the IH gives us exactly the
|
||||
- Almost all the other cases are similar: `x` appears free in a
|
||||
subterm of `P`, and since `P` is well typed under `Γ`, we
|
||||
know the subterm of `M` in which `x` appears is well typed
|
||||
under `Γ` as well, and the IH gives us exactly the
|
||||
conclusion we want.
|
||||
|
||||
- The only remaining case is `free-λᵀ`. In this case $$P =
|
||||
λᵀ y ∈ A ⇒ N$$, and $$x$$ appears free in $$N$$; we also know that
|
||||
$$x$$ is different from $$y$$. The difference from the previous
|
||||
cases is that whereas $$P$$ is well typed under $$\Gamma$$, its
|
||||
body $$N$$ is well typed under $$(Γ , y ↦ A)$$, so the IH
|
||||
allows us to conclude that $$x$$ is assigned some type by the
|
||||
extended context $$(Γ , y ↦ A)$$. To conclude that $$Γ$$
|
||||
assigns a type to $$x$$, we appeal the decidable equality for names
|
||||
`_≟_`, noting that $$x$$ and $$y$$ are different variables.
|
||||
- The only remaining case is `free-λᵀ`. In this case `P =
|
||||
λᵀ y ∈ A ⇒ N`, and `x` appears free in `N`; we also know that
|
||||
`x` is different from `y`. The difference from the previous
|
||||
cases is that whereas `P` is well typed under `\Gamma`, its
|
||||
body `N` is well typed under `(Γ , y ↦ A)`, so the IH
|
||||
allows us to conclude that `x` is assigned some type by the
|
||||
extended context `(Γ , y ↦ A)`. To conclude that `Γ`
|
||||
assigns a type to `x`, we appeal the decidable equality for names
|
||||
`_≟_`, noting that `x` and `y` are different variables.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
freeLemma free-varᵀ (Ax Γx≡justA) = (_ , Γx≡justA)
|
||||
|
@ -261,11 +261,11 @@ freeLemma (free-λᵀ {x} {y} y≢x x∈N) (⇒-I ⊢N) with freeLemma x∈N ⊢
|
|||
... | no _ = Γx=justC
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
[A subtle point: if the first argument of $$free-λᵀ$$ was of type
|
||||
$$x ≢ y$$ rather than of type $$y ≢ x$$, then the type of the
|
||||
term $$Γx=justC$$ would not simplify properly.]
|
||||
[A subtle point: if the first argument of `free-λᵀ` was of type
|
||||
`x ≢ y` rather than of type `y ≢ x`, then the type of the
|
||||
term `Γx=justC` would not simplify properly.]
|
||||
|
||||
Next, we'll need the fact that any term $$M$$ which is well typed in
|
||||
Next, we'll need the fact that any term `M` which is well typed in
|
||||
the empty context is closed (it has no free variables).
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars, optional (∅⊢-closed)
|
||||
|
@ -286,11 +286,11 @@ contradiction ()
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
</div>
|
||||
|
||||
Sometimes, when we have a proof $$Γ ⊢ M ∈ A$$, we will need to
|
||||
replace $$Γ$$ by a different context $$Γ′$$. When is it safe
|
||||
Sometimes, when we have a proof `Γ ⊢ M ∈ A`, we will need to
|
||||
replace `Γ` by a different context `Γ′`. When is it safe
|
||||
to do this? Intuitively, it must at least be the case that
|
||||
$$Γ′$$ assigns the same types as $$Γ$$ to all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in $$M$$. In fact, this is the only condition that
|
||||
`Γ′` assigns the same types as `Γ` to all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in `M`. In fact, this is the only condition that
|
||||
is needed.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
|
@ -301,45 +301,45 @@ weaken : ∀ {Γ Γ′ M A}
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of
|
||||
$$Γ ⊢ M ∈ A$$.
|
||||
`Γ ⊢ M ∈ A`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was `var`, then $$t = x$$
|
||||
and $$\Gamma x = T$$. By assumption, $$\Gamma' x = T$$ as well, and
|
||||
hence $$\Gamma' \vdash t : T$$ by `var`.
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was `var`, then `t = x`
|
||||
and `\Gamma x = T`. By assumption, `\Gamma' x = T` as well, and
|
||||
hence `\Gamma' \vdash t : T` by `var`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule was `abs`, then $$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, with
|
||||
$$T = A\to B$$ and $$\Gamma, y : A \vdash t' : B$$. The
|
||||
induction hypothesis is that, for any context $$\Gamma''$$, if
|
||||
$$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma''$$ assign the same types to all the
|
||||
free variables in $$t'$$, then $$t'$$ has type $$B$$ under
|
||||
$$\Gamma''$$. Let $$\Gamma'$$ be a context which agrees with
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t$$; we must show
|
||||
$$\Gamma' \vdash \lambda y:A. t' : A\to B$$.
|
||||
- If the last rule was `abs`, then `t = \lambda y:A. t'`, with
|
||||
`T = A\to B` and `\Gamma, y : A \vdash t' : B`. The
|
||||
induction hypothesis is that, for any context `\Gamma''`, if
|
||||
`\Gamma, y:A` and `\Gamma''` assign the same types to all the
|
||||
free variables in `t'`, then `t'` has type `B` under
|
||||
`\Gamma''`. Let `\Gamma'` be a context which agrees with
|
||||
`\Gamma` on the free variables in `t`; we must show
|
||||
`\Gamma' \vdash \lambda y:A. t' : A\to B`.
|
||||
|
||||
By $$abs$$, it suffices to show that $$\Gamma', y:A \vdash t' : t'$$.
|
||||
By the IH (setting $$\Gamma'' = \Gamma', y:A$$), it suffices to show
|
||||
that $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$ agree on all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in $$t'$$.
|
||||
By `abs`, it suffices to show that `\Gamma', y:A \vdash t' : t'`.
|
||||
By the IH (setting `\Gamma'' = \Gamma', y:A`), it suffices to show
|
||||
that `\Gamma, y:A` and `\Gamma', y:A` agree on all the variables
|
||||
that appear free in `t'`.
|
||||
|
||||
Any variable occurring free in $$t'$$ must be either $$y$$ or
|
||||
some other variable. $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and $$\Gamma', y:A$$
|
||||
clearly agree on $$y$$. Otherwise, note that any variable other
|
||||
than $$y$$ that occurs free in $$t'$$ also occurs free in
|
||||
$$t = \lambda y:A. t'$$, and by assumption $$\Gamma$$ and
|
||||
$$\Gamma'$$ agree on all such variables; hence so do $$\Gamma, y:A$$ and
|
||||
$$\Gamma', y:A$$.
|
||||
Any variable occurring free in `t'` must be either `y` or
|
||||
some other variable. `\Gamma, y:A` and `\Gamma', y:A`
|
||||
clearly agree on `y`. Otherwise, note that any variable other
|
||||
than `y` that occurs free in `t'` also occurs free in
|
||||
`t = \lambda y:A. t'`, and by assumption `\Gamma` and
|
||||
`\Gamma'` agree on all such variables; hence so do `\Gamma, y:A` and
|
||||
`\Gamma', y:A`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule was `app`, then $$t = t_1\;t_2$$, with
|
||||
$$\Gamma \vdash t_1:A\to T$$ and $$\Gamma \vdash t_2:A$$.
|
||||
One induction hypothesis states that for all contexts $$\Gamma'$$,
|
||||
if $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with $$\Gamma$$ on the free variables in $$t_1$$,
|
||||
then $$t_1$$ has type $$A\to T$$ under $$\Gamma'$$; there is a similar IH
|
||||
for $$t_2$$. We must show that $$t_1\;t_2$$ also has type $$T$$ under
|
||||
$$\Gamma'$$, given the assumption that $$\Gamma'$$ agrees with
|
||||
$$\Gamma$$ on all the free variables in $$t_1\;t_2$$. By `app`, it
|
||||
suffices to show that $$t_1$$ and $$t_2$$ each have the same type
|
||||
under $$\Gamma'$$ as under $$\Gamma$$. But all free variables in
|
||||
$$t_1$$ are also free in $$t_1\;t_2$$, and similarly for $$t_2$$;
|
||||
- If the last rule was `app`, then `t = t_1\;t_2`, with
|
||||
`\Gamma \vdash t_1:A\to T` and `\Gamma \vdash t_2:A`.
|
||||
One induction hypothesis states that for all contexts `\Gamma'`,
|
||||
if `\Gamma'` agrees with `\Gamma` on the free variables in `t_1`,
|
||||
then `t_1` has type `A\to T` under `\Gamma'`; there is a similar IH
|
||||
for `t_2`. We must show that `t_1\;t_2` also has type `T` under
|
||||
`\Gamma'`, given the assumption that `\Gamma'` agrees with
|
||||
`\Gamma` on all the free variables in `t_1\;t_2`. By `app`, it
|
||||
suffices to show that `t_1` and `t_2` each have the same type
|
||||
under `\Gamma'` as under `\Gamma`. But all free variables in
|
||||
`t_1` are also free in `t_1\;t_2`, and similarly for `t_2`;
|
||||
hence the desired result follows from the induction hypotheses.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
|
@ -383,16 +383,16 @@ preserves types---namely, the observation that _substitution_
|
|||
preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
Formally, the so-called _Substitution Lemma_ says this: Suppose we
|
||||
have a term $$N$$ with a free variable $$x$$, and suppose we've been
|
||||
able to assign a type $$B$$ to $$N$$ under the assumption that $$x$$ has
|
||||
some type $$A$$. Also, suppose that we have some other term $$V$$ and
|
||||
that we've shown that $$V$$ has type $$A$$. Then, since $$V$$ satisfies
|
||||
the assumption we made about $$x$$ when typing $$N$$, we should be
|
||||
able to substitute $$V$$ for each of the occurrences of $$x$$ in $$N$$
|
||||
and obtain a new term that still has type $$B$$.
|
||||
have a term `N` with a free variable `x`, and suppose we've been
|
||||
able to assign a type `B` to `N` under the assumption that `x` has
|
||||
some type `A`. Also, suppose that we have some other term `V` and
|
||||
that we've shown that `V` has type `A`. Then, since `V` satisfies
|
||||
the assumption we made about `x` when typing `N`, we should be
|
||||
able to substitute `V` for each of the occurrences of `x` in `N`
|
||||
and obtain a new term that still has type `B`.
|
||||
|
||||
_Lemma_: If $$Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B$$ and $$∅ ⊢ V ∈ A$$, then
|
||||
$$Γ ⊢ (N [ x := V ]) ∈ B$$.
|
||||
_Lemma_: If `Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B` and `∅ ⊢ V ∈ A`, then
|
||||
`Γ ⊢ (N [ x := V ]) ∈ B`.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
preservation-[:=] : ∀ {Γ x A N B V}
|
||||
|
@ -402,63 +402,63 @@ preservation-[:=] : ∀ {Γ x A N B V}
|
|||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
One technical subtlety in the statement of the lemma is that
|
||||
we assign $$V$$ the type $$A$$ in the _empty_ context---in other
|
||||
words, we assume $$V$$ is closed. This assumption considerably
|
||||
simplifies the $$λᵀ$$ case of the proof (compared to assuming
|
||||
$$Γ ⊢ V ∈ A$$, which would be the other reasonable assumption
|
||||
we assign `V` the type `A` in the _empty_ context---in other
|
||||
words, we assume `V` is closed. This assumption considerably
|
||||
simplifies the `λᵀ` case of the proof (compared to assuming
|
||||
`Γ ⊢ V ∈ A`, which would be the other reasonable assumption
|
||||
at this point) because the context invariance lemma then tells us
|
||||
that $$V$$ has type $$A$$ in any context at all---we don't have to
|
||||
worry about free variables in $$V$$ clashing with the variable being
|
||||
introduced into the context by $$λᵀ$$.
|
||||
that `V` has type `A` in any context at all---we don't have to
|
||||
worry about free variables in `V` clashing with the variable being
|
||||
introduced into the context by `λᵀ`.
|
||||
|
||||
The substitution lemma can be viewed as a kind of "commutation"
|
||||
property. Intuitively, it says that substitution and typing can
|
||||
be done in either order: we can either assign types to the terms
|
||||
$$N$$ and $$V$$ separately (under suitable contexts) and then combine
|
||||
`N` and `V` separately (under suitable contexts) and then combine
|
||||
them using substitution, or we can substitute first and then
|
||||
assign a type to $$N [ x := V ]$$---the result is the same either
|
||||
assign a type to `N [ x := V ]`---the result is the same either
|
||||
way.
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on $$N$$, that for all $$A$$ and
|
||||
$$Γ$$, if $$Γ , x ↦ A \vdash N ∈ B$$ and $$∅ ⊢ V ∈ A$$, then
|
||||
$$Γ \vdash N [ x := V ] ∈ B$$.
|
||||
_Proof_: We show, by induction on `N`, that for all `A` and
|
||||
`Γ`, if `Γ , x ↦ A \vdash N ∈ B` and `∅ ⊢ V ∈ A`, then
|
||||
`Γ \vdash N [ x := V ] ∈ B`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$N$$ is a variable there are two cases to consider,
|
||||
depending on whether $$N$$ is $$x$$ or some other variable.
|
||||
- If `N` is a variable there are two cases to consider,
|
||||
depending on whether `N` is `x` or some other variable.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$N = varᵀ x$$, then from the fact that $$Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B$$
|
||||
we conclude that $$A = B$$. We must show that $$x [ x := V] =
|
||||
V$$ has type $$A$$ under $$Γ$$, given the assumption that
|
||||
$$V$$ has type $$A$$ under the empty context. This
|
||||
- If `N = varᵀ x`, then from the fact that `Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B`
|
||||
we conclude that `A = B`. We must show that `x [ x := V] =
|
||||
V` has type `A` under `Γ`, given the assumption that
|
||||
`V` has type `A` under the empty context. This
|
||||
follows from context invariance: if a closed term has type
|
||||
$$A$$ in the empty context, it has that type in any context.
|
||||
`A` in the empty context, it has that type in any context.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$N$$ is some variable $$x′$$ different from $$x$$, then
|
||||
we need only note that $$x′$$ has the same type under $$Γ , x ↦ A$$
|
||||
as under $$Γ$$.
|
||||
- If `N` is some variable `x′` different from `x`, then
|
||||
we need only note that `x′` has the same type under `Γ , x ↦ A`
|
||||
as under `Γ`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$N$$ is an abstraction $$λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′$$, then the IH tells us,
|
||||
for all $$Γ′$$́ and $$B′$$, that if $$Γ′ , x ↦ A ⊢ N′ ∈ B′$$
|
||||
and $$∅ ⊢ V ∈ A$$, then $$Γ′ ⊢ N′ [ x := V ] ∈ B′$$.
|
||||
- If `N` is an abstraction `λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′`, then the IH tells us,
|
||||
for all `Γ′`́ and `B′`, that if `Γ′ , x ↦ A ⊢ N′ ∈ B′`
|
||||
and `∅ ⊢ V ∈ A`, then `Γ′ ⊢ N′ [ x := V ] ∈ B′`.
|
||||
|
||||
The substitution in the conclusion behaves differently
|
||||
depending on whether $$x$$ and $$x′$$ are the same variable.
|
||||
depending on whether `x` and `x′` are the same variable.
|
||||
|
||||
First, suppose $$x ≡ x′$$. Then, by the definition of
|
||||
substitution, $$N [ x := V] = N$$, so we just need to show $$Γ ⊢ N ∈ B$$.
|
||||
But we know $$Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B$$ and, since $$x ≡ x′$$
|
||||
does not appear free in $$λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′$$, the context invariance
|
||||
lemma yields $$Γ ⊢ N ∈ B$$.
|
||||
First, suppose `x ≡ x′`. Then, by the definition of
|
||||
substitution, `N [ x := V] = N`, so we just need to show `Γ ⊢ N ∈ B`.
|
||||
But we know `Γ , x ↦ A ⊢ N ∈ B` and, since `x ≡ x′`
|
||||
does not appear free in `λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′`, the context invariance
|
||||
lemma yields `Γ ⊢ N ∈ B`.
|
||||
|
||||
Second, suppose $$x ≢ x′$$. We know $$Γ , x ↦ A , x′ ↦ A′ ⊢ N′ ∈ B′$$
|
||||
Second, suppose `x ≢ x′`. We know `Γ , x ↦ A , x′ ↦ A′ ⊢ N′ ∈ B′`
|
||||
by inversion of the typing relation, from which
|
||||
$$Γ , x′ ↦ A′ , x ↦ A ⊢ N′ ∈ B′$$ follows by update permute,
|
||||
so the IH applies, giving us $$Γ , x′ ↦ A′ ⊢ N′ [ x := V ] ∈ B′$$
|
||||
By $$⇒-I$$, we have $$Γ ⊢ λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ (N′ [ x := V ]) ∈ A′ ⇒ B′$$
|
||||
and the definition of substitution (noting $$x ≢ x′$$) gives
|
||||
$$Γ ⊢ (λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′) [ x := V ] ∈ A′ ⇒ B′$$ as required.
|
||||
`Γ , x′ ↦ A′ , x ↦ A ⊢ N′ ∈ B′` follows by update permute,
|
||||
so the IH applies, giving us `Γ , x′ ↦ A′ ⊢ N′ [ x := V ] ∈ B′`
|
||||
By `⇒-I`, we have `Γ ⊢ λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ (N′ [ x := V ]) ∈ A′ ⇒ B′`
|
||||
and the definition of substitution (noting `x ≢ x′`) gives
|
||||
`Γ ⊢ (λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′) [ x := V ] ∈ A′ ⇒ B′` as required.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$N$$ is an application $$L′ ·ᵀ M′$$, the result follows
|
||||
- If `N` is an application `L′ ·ᵀ M′`, the result follows
|
||||
straightforwardly from the definition of substitution and the
|
||||
induction hypotheses.
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -492,7 +492,7 @@ preservation-[:=] {Γ} {x} {A} {λᵀ x′ ∈ A′ ⇒ N′} {.A′ ⇒ B′} {
|
|||
...| no _ = refl
|
||||
...| no x≢x′ = ⇒-I ⊢N′V
|
||||
where
|
||||
x′x⊢N′ : (Γ , x′ ↦ A′ , x ↦ A) ⊢ N′ ∈ B′
|
||||
x′x⊢N′ : Γ , x′ ↦ A′ , x ↦ A ⊢ N′ ∈ B′
|
||||
x′x⊢N′ rewrite update-permute Γ x A x′ A′ x≢x′ = ⊢N′
|
||||
⊢N′V : (Γ , x′ ↦ A′) ⊢ N′ [ x := V ] ∈ B′
|
||||
⊢N′V = preservation-[:=] x′x⊢N′ ⊢V
|
||||
|
@ -507,43 +507,43 @@ preservation-[:=] (𝔹-E ⊢L ⊢M ⊢N) ⊢V =
|
|||
### Main Theorem
|
||||
|
||||
We now have the tools we need to prove preservation: if a closed
|
||||
term $$M$$ has type $$A$$ and takes a step to $$N$$, then $$N$$
|
||||
is also a closed term with type $$A$$. In other words, small-step
|
||||
term `M` has type `A` and takes a step to `N`, then `N`
|
||||
is also a closed term with type `A`. In other words, small-step
|
||||
reduction preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
preservation : ∀ {M N A} → ∅ ⊢ M ∈ A → M ⟹ N → ∅ ⊢ N ∈ A
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of $$\vdash t : T$$.
|
||||
_Proof_: By induction on the derivation of `\vdash t : T`.
|
||||
|
||||
- We can immediately rule out $$var$$, $$abs$$, $$T_True$$, and
|
||||
$$T_False$$ as the final rules in the derivation, since in each of
|
||||
these cases $$t$$ cannot take a step.
|
||||
- We can immediately rule out `var`, `abs`, `T_True`, and
|
||||
`T_False` as the final rules in the derivation, since in each of
|
||||
these cases `t` cannot take a step.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$app$$, then $$t = t_1
|
||||
t_2$$. There are three cases to consider, one for each rule that
|
||||
could have been used to show that $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step to $$t'$$.
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was `app`, then `t = t_1
|
||||
t_2`. There are three cases to consider, one for each rule that
|
||||
could have been used to show that `t_1 t_2` takes a step to `t'`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sapp1$$, with $$t_1$$ stepping to
|
||||
$$t_1'$$, then by the IH $$t_1'$$ has the same type as $$t_1$$, and
|
||||
hence $$t_1' t_2$$ has the same type as $$t_1 t_2$$.
|
||||
- If `t_1 t_2` takes a step by `Sapp1`, with `t_1` stepping to
|
||||
`t_1'`, then by the IH `t_1'` has the same type as `t_1`, and
|
||||
hence `t_1' t_2` has the same type as `t_1 t_2`.
|
||||
|
||||
- The $$Sapp2$$ case is similar.
|
||||
- The `Sapp2` case is similar.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t_1 t_2$$ takes a step by $$Sred$$, then $$t_1 =
|
||||
\lambda x:t_{11}.t_{12}$$ and $$t_1 t_2$$ steps to $$$$x:=t_2$$t_{12}$$; the
|
||||
- If `t_1 t_2` takes a step by `Sred`, then `t_1 =
|
||||
\lambda x:t_{11}.t_{12}` and `t_1 t_2` steps to ``x:=t_2`t_{12}`; the
|
||||
desired result now follows from the fact that substitution
|
||||
preserves types.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was $$if$$, then $$t = if t_1
|
||||
then t_2 else t_3$$, and there are again three cases depending on
|
||||
how $$t$$ steps.
|
||||
- If the last rule in the derivation was `if`, then `t = if t_1
|
||||
then t_2 else t_3`, and there are again three cases depending on
|
||||
how `t` steps.
|
||||
|
||||
- If $$t$$ steps to $$t_2$$ or $$t_3$$, the result is immediate, since
|
||||
$$t_2$$ and $$t_3$$ have the same type as $$t$$.
|
||||
- If `t` steps to `t_2` or `t_3`, the result is immediate, since
|
||||
`t_2` and `t_3` have the same type as `t`.
|
||||
|
||||
- Otherwise, $$t$$ steps by $$Sif$$, and the desired conclusion
|
||||
- Otherwise, `t` steps by `Sif`, and the desired conclusion
|
||||
follows directly from the induction hypothesis.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
|
@ -571,11 +571,11 @@ Proof with eauto.
|
|||
intros t t' T HT. generalize dependent t'.
|
||||
induction HT;
|
||||
intros t' HE; subst Gamma; subst;
|
||||
try solve $$inversion HE; subst; auto$$.
|
||||
try solve `inversion HE; subst; auto`.
|
||||
- (* app
|
||||
inversion HE; subst...
|
||||
(* Most of the cases are immediate by induction,
|
||||
and $$eauto$$ takes care of them
|
||||
and `eauto` takes care of them
|
||||
+ (* Sred
|
||||
apply substitution_preserves_typing with t_{11}...
|
||||
inversion HT_1...
|
||||
|
@ -585,7 +585,7 @@ Qed.
|
|||
An exercise in the [Stlc]({{ "Stlc" | relative_url }}) chapter asked about the
|
||||
subject expansion property for the simple language of arithmetic and boolean
|
||||
expressions. Does this property hold for STLC? That is, is it always the case
|
||||
that, if $$t ==> t'$$ and $$has_type t' T$$, then $$empty \vdash t : T$$? If
|
||||
that, if `t ==> t'` and `has_type t' T`, then `empty \vdash t : T`? If
|
||||
so, prove it. If not, give a counter-example not involving conditionals.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -604,7 +604,7 @@ Corollary soundness : forall t t' T,
|
|||
~(stuck t').
|
||||
Proof.
|
||||
intros t t' T Hhas_type Hmulti. unfold stuck.
|
||||
intros $$Hnf Hnot_val$$. unfold normal_form in Hnf.
|
||||
intros `Hnf Hnot_val`. unfold normal_form in Hnf.
|
||||
induction Hmulti.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -621,10 +621,10 @@ Formalize this statement and prove it.
|
|||
#### Exercise: 1 star (progress_preservation_statement)
|
||||
Without peeking at their statements above, write down the progress
|
||||
and preservation theorems for the simply typed lambda-calculus.
|
||||
$$$$
|
||||
``
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation1)
|
||||
Suppose we add a new term $$zap$$ with the following reduction rule
|
||||
Suppose we add a new term `zap` with the following reduction rule
|
||||
|
||||
--------- (ST_Zap)
|
||||
t ==> zap
|
||||
|
@ -639,7 +639,7 @@ the presence of these rules? For each property, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -647,7 +647,7 @@ false, give a counterexample.
|
|||
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation2)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add a new term $$foo$$ with the following
|
||||
Suppose instead that we add a new term `foo` with the following
|
||||
reduction rules:
|
||||
|
||||
----------------- (ST_Foo1)
|
||||
|
@ -661,20 +661,20 @@ the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
- Preservation
|
||||
|
||||
#### Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation3)
|
||||
Suppose instead that we remove the rule $$Sapp1$$ from the $$step$$
|
||||
Suppose instead that we remove the rule `Sapp1` from the `step`
|
||||
relation. Which of the following properties of the STLC remain
|
||||
true in the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
||||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -692,7 +692,7 @@ the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -714,7 +714,7 @@ the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -736,7 +736,7 @@ the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -756,7 +756,7 @@ the presence of this rule? For each one, write either
|
|||
"remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes
|
||||
false, give a counterexample.
|
||||
|
||||
- Determinism of $$step$$
|
||||
- Determinism of `step`
|
||||
|
||||
- Progress
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -798,10 +798,10 @@ with arithmetic. Specifically:
|
|||
the definition of values through the Type Soundness theorem), and
|
||||
paste it into the file at this point.
|
||||
|
||||
- Extend the definitions of the $$subst$$ operation and the $$step$$
|
||||
- Extend the definitions of the `subst` operation and the `step`
|
||||
relation to include appropriate clauses for the arithmetic operators.
|
||||
|
||||
- Extend the proofs of all the properties (up to $$soundness$$) of
|
||||
- Extend the proofs of all the properties (up to `soundness`) of
|
||||
the original STLC to deal with the new syntactic forms. Make
|
||||
sure Agda accepts the whole file.
|
||||
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue