updated pairs in Negation and Quantifiers
This commit is contained in:
parent
242e174280
commit
e188bedcc2
3 changed files with 413 additions and 22 deletions
|
@ -15,7 +15,7 @@ open import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality using (_≡_; refl)
|
|||
open import Data.Nat using (ℕ; zero; suc)
|
||||
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
|
||||
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (_×_; proj₁; proj₂) renaming (_,_ to ⟨_,_⟩)
|
||||
open import Function using (_∘_)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
|
|
394
src/Quantifiers-old.lagda
Normal file
394
src/Quantifiers-old.lagda
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,394 @@
|
|||
---
|
||||
title : "Quantifiers: Universals and Existentials"
|
||||
layout : page
|
||||
permalink : /Quantifiers
|
||||
---
|
||||
|
||||
This chapter introduces universal and existential quantification.
|
||||
|
||||
## Imports
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality as Eq
|
||||
open Eq using (_≡_; refl; sym; trans; cong)
|
||||
open Eq.≡-Reasoning
|
||||
open import Isomorphism using (_≃_; ≃-sym; ≃-trans; _≲_)
|
||||
open Isomorphism.≃-Reasoning
|
||||
open import Data.Nat using (ℕ; zero; suc; _+_; _*_)
|
||||
open import Data.Nat.Properties.Simple using (+-suc)
|
||||
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_)
|
||||
open import Function using (_∘_)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂)
|
||||
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
We assume [extensionality][extensionality].
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
postulate
|
||||
extensionality : ∀ {A B : Set} {f g : A → B} → (∀ (x : A) → f x ≡ g x) → f ≡ g
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
[extensionality]: Equality/index.html#extensionality
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Universals
|
||||
|
||||
Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B x` which
|
||||
contains `x` as a free variable, the universally quantified
|
||||
proposition `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds if for every term `M` of type
|
||||
`A` the proposition `B M` holds. Here `B M` stands for
|
||||
the proposition `B x` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by
|
||||
`M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B x` but bound in
|
||||
`∀ (x : A) → B x`. We formalise universal quantification using the
|
||||
dependent function type, which has appeared throughout this book.
|
||||
|
||||
Evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds is of the form
|
||||
|
||||
λ (x : A) → N
|
||||
|
||||
where `N` is a term of type `B x`, and `N x` and `B x` both contain
|
||||
a free variable `x` of type `A`. Given a term `L` providing evidence
|
||||
that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds, and a term `M` of type `A`, the term `L
|
||||
M` provides evidence that `B M` holds. In other words, evidence that
|
||||
`∀ (x : A) → B x` holds is a function that converts a term `M` of type
|
||||
`A` into evidence that `B M` holds.
|
||||
|
||||
Put another way, if we know that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds and that `M`
|
||||
is a term of type `A` then we may conclude that `B M` holds.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∀-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (∀ (x : A) → B x) → (M : A) → B M
|
||||
∀-elim L M = L M
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
As with `→-elim`, the rule corresponds to function application.
|
||||
|
||||
Functions arise as a special case of dependent functions,
|
||||
where the range does not depend on a variable drawn from the domain.
|
||||
When a function is viewed as evidence of implication, both its
|
||||
argument and result are viewed as evidence, whereas when a dependent
|
||||
function is viewed as evidence of a universal, its argument is viewed
|
||||
as an element of a data type and its result is viewed as evidence of
|
||||
a proposition that depends on the argument. This difference is largely
|
||||
a matter of interpretation, since in Agda values of a type and
|
||||
evidence of a proposition are indistinguishable.
|
||||
|
||||
Dependent function types are sometimes referred to as dependent products,
|
||||
because if `A` is a finite type with values `x₁ , ⋯ , xᵢ`, and if
|
||||
each of the types `B x₁ , ⋯ , B xᵢ` has `m₁ , ⋯ , mᵢ` distinct members,
|
||||
then `∀ (x : A) → B x` has `m₁ * ⋯ * mᵢ` members.
|
||||
Indeed, sometimes the notation `∀ (x : A) → B x`
|
||||
is replaced by a notation such as `Π[ x ∈ A ] (B x)`,
|
||||
where `Π` stands for product. However, we will stick with the name
|
||||
dependent function, because (as we will see) dependent product is ambiguous.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`∀-distrib-×`)
|
||||
|
||||
Show that universals distribute over conjunction.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∀-Distrib-× = ∀ {A : Set} {B C : A → Set} →
|
||||
(∀ (x : A) → B x × C x) ≃ (∀ (x : A) → B x) × (∀ (x : A) → C x)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Compare this with the result (`→-distrib-×`) in Chapter [Connectives](Connectives).
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`⊎∀-implies-∀⊎`)
|
||||
|
||||
Show that a disjunction of universals implies a universal of disjunctions.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
⊎∀-Implies-∀⊎ = ∀ {A : Set} { B C : A → Set } →
|
||||
(∀ (x : A) → B x) ⊎ (∀ (x : A) → C x) → ∀ (x : A) → B x ⊎ C x
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Does the converse hold? If so, prove; if not, explain why.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Existentials
|
||||
|
||||
Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B x` which
|
||||
contains `x` as a free variable, the existentially quantified
|
||||
proposition `Σ[ x ∈ A ] B x` holds if for some term `M` of type
|
||||
`A` the proposition `B M` holds. Here `B M` stands for
|
||||
the proposition `B x` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by
|
||||
`M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B x` but bound in
|
||||
`Σ[ x ∈ A ] B x`.
|
||||
|
||||
We formalise existential quantification by declaring a suitable
|
||||
inductive type.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
data Σ (A : Set) (B : A → Set) : Set where
|
||||
_,_ : (x : A) → B x → Σ A B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
We define a convenient syntax for existentials as follows.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
infix 2 Σ-syntax
|
||||
|
||||
Σ-syntax = Σ
|
||||
|
||||
syntax Σ-syntax A (λ x → B) = Σ[ x ∈ A ] B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
This is our first use of a syntax declaration, which specifies that
|
||||
the term on the left may be written with the syntax on the right.
|
||||
The special syntax is available only when the identifier
|
||||
`Σ-syntax` is imported.
|
||||
|
||||
Evidence that `Σ[ x ∈ A ] B x` holds is of the form
|
||||
`(M , N)` where `M` is a term of type `A`, and `N` is evidence
|
||||
that `B M` holds.
|
||||
|
||||
Equivalently, we could also declare existentials as a record type.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
record Σ′ (A : Set) (B : A → Set) : Set where
|
||||
field
|
||||
proj₁′ : A
|
||||
proj₂′ : B proj₁′
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Here record construction
|
||||
|
||||
record
|
||||
{ proj₁′ = M
|
||||
; proj₂′ = N
|
||||
}
|
||||
|
||||
corresponds to the term
|
||||
|
||||
( M , N )
|
||||
|
||||
where `M` is a term of type `A` and `N` is a term of type `B M`.
|
||||
|
||||
Products arise a special case of existentials, where the second
|
||||
component does not depend on a variable drawn from the first
|
||||
component. When a product is viewed as evidence of a conjunction,
|
||||
both of its components are viewed as evidence, whereas when it is
|
||||
viewed as evidence of an existential, the first component is viewed as
|
||||
an element of a datatype and the second component is viewed as
|
||||
evidence of a proposition that depends on the first component. This
|
||||
difference is largely a matter of interpretation, since in Agda values
|
||||
of a type and evidence of a proposition are indistinguishable.
|
||||
|
||||
Existentials are sometimes referred to as dependent sums,
|
||||
because if `A` is a finite type with values `x₁ , ⋯ , xᵢ`, and if
|
||||
each of the types `B x₁ , ⋯ B xᵢ` has `m₁ , ⋯ , mᵢ` distinct members,
|
||||
then `Σ[ x ∈ A] B x` has `m₁ + ⋯ + mᵢ` members, which explains the
|
||||
choice of notation for existentials, since `Σ` stands for sum.
|
||||
|
||||
Existentials are sometimes referred to as dependent products, since
|
||||
products arise as a special case. However, that choice of names is
|
||||
doubly confusing, since universal also have a claim to the name dependent
|
||||
product and since existential also have a claim to the name dependent sum.
|
||||
|
||||
A common notation for existentials is `∃` (analogous to `∀` for universals).
|
||||
We follow the convention of the Agda standard library, and reserve this
|
||||
notation for the case where the domain of the bound variable is left implicit.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃ : ∀ {A : Set} (B : A → Set) → Set
|
||||
∃ {A} B = Σ A B
|
||||
|
||||
∃-syntax = ∃
|
||||
|
||||
syntax ∃-syntax (λ x → B) = ∃[ x ] B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
The special syntax is available only when the identifier `∃-syntax` is imported.
|
||||
We will tend to use this syntax, since it is shorter and more familiar.
|
||||
|
||||
Given evidence that `∀ x → B x → C` holds, where `C` does not contain
|
||||
`x` as a free variable, and given evidence that `∃[ x ] B x` holds, we
|
||||
may conclude that `C` holds.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} → (∀ x → B x → C) → ∃[ x ] B x → C
|
||||
∃-elim f (x , y) = f x y
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
In other words, if we know for every `x` of type `A` that `B x`
|
||||
implies `C`, and we know for some `x` of type `A` that `B x` holds,
|
||||
then we may conclude that `C` holds. This is because we may
|
||||
instantiate that proof that `∀ x → B x → C` to any value `x` of type
|
||||
`A` and any `y` of type `B x`, and exactly such values are provided by
|
||||
the evidence for `∃[ x ] B x`.
|
||||
|
||||
Indeed, the converse also holds, and the two together form an isomorphism.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∀∃-currying : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} → (∀ x → B x → C) ≃ (∃[ x ] B x → C)
|
||||
∀∃-currying =
|
||||
record
|
||||
{ to = λ{ f → λ{ (x , y) → f x y }}
|
||||
; from = λ{ g → λ{ x → λ{ y → g (x , y) }}}
|
||||
; from∘to = λ{ f → refl }
|
||||
; to∘from = λ{ g → extensionality λ{ (x , y) → refl }}
|
||||
}
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
The result can be viewed as a generalisation of currying. Indeed, the code to
|
||||
establish the isomorphism is identical to what we wrote when discussing
|
||||
[implication][implication].
|
||||
|
||||
[implication]: Connectives/index.html#implication
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`∃-distrib-⊎`)
|
||||
|
||||
Show that universals distribute over conjunction.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃-Distrib-⊎ = ∀ {A : Set} {B C : A → Set} →
|
||||
∃[ x ] (B x ⊎ C x) ≃ (∃[ x ] B x) ⊎ (∃[ x ] C x)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`∃×-implies-×∃`)
|
||||
|
||||
Show that an existential of conjunctions implies a conjunction of existentials.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃×-Implies-×∃ = ∀ {A : Set} { B C : A → Set } →
|
||||
∃[ x ] (B x × C x) → (∃[ x ] B x) × (∃[ x ] C x)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Does the converse hold? If so, prove; if not, explain why.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## An existential example
|
||||
|
||||
Recall the definitions of `even` and `odd` from Chapter [Relations](Relations).
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
data even : ℕ → Set
|
||||
data odd : ℕ → Set
|
||||
|
||||
data even where
|
||||
even-zero : even zero
|
||||
even-suc : ∀ {n : ℕ} → odd n → even (suc n)
|
||||
|
||||
data odd where
|
||||
odd-suc : ∀ {n : ℕ} → even n → odd (suc n)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
A number is even if it is zero or the successor of an odd number, and
|
||||
odd if it the successor of an even number.
|
||||
|
||||
We will show that a number is even if and only if it is twice some
|
||||
other number, and odd if and only if it is one more than twice
|
||||
some other number. In other words, we will show
|
||||
|
||||
even n iff ∃[ m ] ( m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
odd n iff ∃[ m ] (1 + m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
|
||||
By convention, one tends to write constant factors first and to put
|
||||
the constant term in a sum last. Here we've reversed each of those
|
||||
conventions, because doing so eases the proof.
|
||||
|
||||
Here is the proof in the forward direction.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
even-∃ : ∀ {n : ℕ} → even n → ∃[ m ] ( m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
odd-∃ : ∀ {n : ℕ} → odd n → ∃[ m ] (1 + m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
|
||||
even-∃ even-zero = zero , refl
|
||||
even-∃ (even-suc o) with odd-∃ o
|
||||
... | m , refl = suc m , refl
|
||||
|
||||
odd-∃ (odd-suc e) with even-∃ e
|
||||
... | m , refl = m , refl
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
We define two mutually recursive functions. Given
|
||||
evidence that `n` is even or odd, we return a
|
||||
number `m` and evidence that `m * 2 ≡ n` or `1 + m * 2 ≡ n`.
|
||||
We induct over the evidence that `n` is even or odd.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the number is even because it is zero, then we return a pair
|
||||
consisting of zero and the (trivial) proof that twice zero is zero.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the number is even because it is one more than an odd number,
|
||||
then we apply the induction hypothesis to give a number `m` and
|
||||
evidence that `1 + m * 2 ≡ n`. We return a pair consisting of `suc m`
|
||||
and evidence that `suc m * 2` ≡ suc n`, which is immediate after
|
||||
substituting for `n`.
|
||||
|
||||
- If the number is odd because it is the successor of an even number,
|
||||
then we apply the induction hypothesis to give a number `m` and
|
||||
evidence that `m * 2 ≡ n`. We return a pair consisting of `suc m` and
|
||||
evidence that `1 + 2 * m = suc n`, which is immediate after
|
||||
substituting for `n`.
|
||||
|
||||
This completes the proof in the forward direction.
|
||||
|
||||
Here is the proof in the reverse direction.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃-even : ∀ {n : ℕ} → ∃[ m ] ( m * 2 ≡ n) → even n
|
||||
∃-odd : ∀ {n : ℕ} → ∃[ m ] (1 + m * 2 ≡ n) → odd n
|
||||
|
||||
∃-even ( zero , refl) = even-zero
|
||||
∃-even (suc m , refl) = even-suc (∃-odd (m , refl))
|
||||
|
||||
∃-odd ( m , refl) = odd-suc (∃-even (m , refl))
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Given a number that is twice some other number we must show it is
|
||||
even, and a number that is one more than twice some other number we
|
||||
must show it is odd. We induct over the evidence of the existential,
|
||||
and in the even case consider the two possibilities for the number
|
||||
that is doubled.
|
||||
|
||||
- In the even case for `zero`, we must show `2 * zero` is even, which
|
||||
follows by `even-zero`.
|
||||
|
||||
- In the even case for `suc n`, we must show `2 * suc m` is even. The
|
||||
inductive hypothesis tells us that `1 + 2 * m` is odd, from which the
|
||||
desired result follows by `even-suc`.
|
||||
|
||||
- In the odd case, we must show `1 + m * 2` is odd. The inductive
|
||||
hypothesis tell us that `m * 2` is even, from which the desired result
|
||||
follows by `odd-suc`.
|
||||
|
||||
This completes the proof in the backward direction.
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`∃-even′, ∃-odd′`)
|
||||
|
||||
How do the proofs become more difficult if we replace `m * 2` and `1 + m * 2`
|
||||
by `2 * m` and `2 * m + 1`? Rewrite the proofs of `∃-even` and `∃-odd` when
|
||||
restated in this way.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Existentials, Universals, and Negation
|
||||
|
||||
Negation of an existential is isomorphic to universal
|
||||
of a negation. Considering that existentials are generalised
|
||||
disjunction and universals are generalised conjunction, this
|
||||
result is analogous to the one which tells us that negation
|
||||
of a disjunction is isomorphic to a conjunction of negations.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
¬∃∀ : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (¬ ∃[ x ] B x) ≃ ∀ x → ¬ B x
|
||||
¬∃∀ =
|
||||
record
|
||||
{ to = λ{ ¬∃xy x y → ¬∃xy (x , y) }
|
||||
; from = λ{ ∀¬xy (x , y) → ∀¬xy x y }
|
||||
; from∘to = λ{ ¬∃xy → extensionality λ{ (x , y) → refl } }
|
||||
; to∘from = λ{ ∀¬xy → refl }
|
||||
}
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
In the `to` direction, we are given a value `¬∃xy` of type
|
||||
`¬ ∃[ x ] B x`, and need to show that given a value
|
||||
`x` that `¬ B x` follows, in other words, from
|
||||
a value `y` of type `B x` we can derive false. Combining
|
||||
`x` and `y` gives us a value `(x , y)` of type `∃[ x ] B x`,
|
||||
and applying `¬∃xy` to that yields a contradiction.
|
||||
|
||||
In the `from` direction, we are given a value `∀¬xy` of type
|
||||
`∀ x → ¬ B x`, and need to show that from a value `(x , y)`
|
||||
of type `∃[ x ] B x` we can derive false. Applying `∀¬xy`
|
||||
to `x` gives a value of type `¬ B x`, and applying that to `y` yields
|
||||
a contradiction.
|
||||
|
||||
The two inverse proofs are straightforward, where one direction
|
||||
requires extensionality.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
### Exercise (`∃¬-Implies-¬∀`)
|
||||
|
||||
Show `∃[ x ] ¬ B x → ¬ (∀ x → B x)`.
|
||||
|
||||
Does the converse hold? If so, prove; if not, explain why.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Standard Prelude
|
||||
|
||||
Definitions similar to those in this chapter can be found in the standard library.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
import Data.Product using (Σ; _,_; ∃; Σ-syntax; ∃-syntax)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
## Unicode
|
||||
|
||||
This chapter uses the following unicode.
|
||||
|
||||
∃ U+2203 THERE EXISTS (\ex, \exists)
|
||||
|
||||
|
|
@ -18,7 +18,7 @@ open import Data.Nat using (ℕ; zero; suc; _+_; _*_)
|
|||
open import Data.Nat.Properties.Simple using (+-suc)
|
||||
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_)
|
||||
open import Function using (_∘_)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂)
|
||||
open import Data.Product using (_×_; proj₁; proj₂) renaming (_,_ to ⟨_,_⟩)
|
||||
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -114,14 +114,12 @@ We formalise existential quantification by declaring a suitable
|
|||
inductive type.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
data Σ (A : Set) (B : A → Set) : Set where
|
||||
_,_ : (x : A) → B x → Σ A B
|
||||
⟨_,_⟩ : (x : A) → B x → Σ A B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
We define a convenient syntax for existentials as follows.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
infix 2 Σ-syntax
|
||||
|
||||
Σ-syntax = Σ
|
||||
|
||||
infix 2 Σ-syntax
|
||||
syntax Σ-syntax A (λ x → B) = Σ[ x ∈ A ] B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
This is our first use of a syntax declaration, which specifies that
|
||||
|
@ -149,7 +147,7 @@ Here record construction
|
|||
|
||||
corresponds to the term
|
||||
|
||||
( M , N )
|
||||
⟨ M , N ⟩
|
||||
|
||||
where `M` is a term of type `A` and `N` is a term of type `B M`.
|
||||
|
||||
|
@ -182,7 +180,6 @@ notation for the case where the domain of the bound variable is left implicit.
|
|||
∃ {A} B = Σ A B
|
||||
|
||||
∃-syntax = ∃
|
||||
|
||||
syntax ∃-syntax (λ x → B) = ∃[ x ] B
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
The special syntax is available only when the identifier `∃-syntax` is imported.
|
||||
|
@ -193,7 +190,7 @@ Given evidence that `∀ x → B x → C` holds, where `C` does not contain
|
|||
may conclude that `C` holds.
|
||||
\begin{code}
|
||||
∃-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} → (∀ x → B x → C) → ∃[ x ] B x → C
|
||||
∃-elim f (x , y) = f x y
|
||||
∃-elim f ⟨ x , y ⟩ = f x y
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
In other words, if we know for every `x` of type `A` that `B x`
|
||||
implies `C`, and we know for some `x` of type `A` that `B x` holds,
|
||||
|
@ -207,10 +204,10 @@ Indeed, the converse also holds, and the two together form an isomorphism.
|
|||
∀∃-currying : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} → (∀ x → B x → C) ≃ (∃[ x ] B x → C)
|
||||
∀∃-currying =
|
||||
record
|
||||
{ to = λ{ f → λ{ (x , y) → f x y }}
|
||||
; from = λ{ g → λ{ x → λ{ y → g (x , y) }}}
|
||||
{ to = λ{ f → λ{ ⟨ x , y ⟩ → f x y }}
|
||||
; from = λ{ g → λ{ x → λ{ y → g ⟨ x , y ⟩ }}}
|
||||
; from∘to = λ{ f → refl }
|
||||
; to∘from = λ{ g → extensionality λ{ (x , y) → refl }}
|
||||
; to∘from = λ{ g → extensionality λ{ ⟨ x , y ⟩ → refl }}
|
||||
}
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
The result can be viewed as a generalisation of currying. Indeed, the code to
|
||||
|
@ -270,12 +267,12 @@ Here is the proof in the forward direction.
|
|||
even-∃ : ∀ {n : ℕ} → even n → ∃[ m ] ( m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
odd-∃ : ∀ {n : ℕ} → odd n → ∃[ m ] (1 + m * 2 ≡ n)
|
||||
|
||||
even-∃ even-zero = zero , refl
|
||||
even-∃ even-zero = ⟨ zero , refl ⟩
|
||||
even-∃ (even-suc o) with odd-∃ o
|
||||
... | m , refl = suc m , refl
|
||||
... | ⟨ m , refl ⟩ = ⟨ suc m , refl ⟩
|
||||
|
||||
odd-∃ (odd-suc e) with even-∃ e
|
||||
... | m , refl = m , refl
|
||||
... | ⟨ m , refl ⟩ = ⟨ m , refl ⟩
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
We define two mutually recursive functions. Given
|
||||
evidence that `n` is even or odd, we return a
|
||||
|
@ -304,10 +301,10 @@ Here is the proof in the reverse direction.
|
|||
∃-even : ∀ {n : ℕ} → ∃[ m ] ( m * 2 ≡ n) → even n
|
||||
∃-odd : ∀ {n : ℕ} → ∃[ m ] (1 + m * 2 ≡ n) → odd n
|
||||
|
||||
∃-even ( zero , refl) = even-zero
|
||||
∃-even (suc m , refl) = even-suc (∃-odd (m , refl))
|
||||
∃-even ⟨ zero , refl ⟩ = even-zero
|
||||
∃-even ⟨ suc m , refl ⟩ = even-suc (∃-odd ⟨ m , refl ⟩)
|
||||
|
||||
∃-odd ( m , refl) = odd-suc (∃-even (m , refl))
|
||||
∃-odd ⟨ m , refl ⟩ = odd-suc (∃-even ⟨ m , refl ⟩)
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
Given a number that is twice some other number we must show it is
|
||||
even, and a number that is one more than twice some other number we
|
||||
|
@ -346,9 +343,9 @@ of a disjunction is isomorphic to a conjunction of negations.
|
|||
¬∃∀ : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (¬ ∃[ x ] B x) ≃ ∀ x → ¬ B x
|
||||
¬∃∀ =
|
||||
record
|
||||
{ to = λ{ ¬∃xy x y → ¬∃xy (x , y) }
|
||||
; from = λ{ ∀¬xy (x , y) → ∀¬xy x y }
|
||||
; from∘to = λ{ ¬∃xy → extensionality λ{ (x , y) → refl } }
|
||||
{ to = λ{ ¬∃xy x y → ¬∃xy ⟨ x , y ⟩ }
|
||||
; from = λ{ ∀¬xy ⟨ x , y ⟩ → ∀¬xy x y }
|
||||
; from∘to = λ{ ¬∃xy → extensionality λ{ ⟨ x , y ⟩ → refl } }
|
||||
; to∘from = λ{ ∀¬xy → refl }
|
||||
}
|
||||
\end{code}
|
||||
|
@ -360,7 +357,7 @@ a value `y` of type `B x` we can derive false. Combining
|
|||
and applying `¬∃xy` to that yields a contradiction.
|
||||
|
||||
In the `from` direction, we are given a value `∀¬xy` of type
|
||||
`∀ x → ¬ B x`, and need to show that from a value `(x , y)`
|
||||
`∀ x → ¬ B x`, and need to show that from a value `⟨ x , y ⟩`
|
||||
of type `∃[ x ] B x` we can derive false. Applying `∀¬xy`
|
||||
to `x` gives a value of type `¬ B x`, and applying that to `y` yields
|
||||
a contradiction.
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue