doc(doc/lean): update Lean tutorial to Lean 0.2, and use org-mode
Signed-off-by: Leonardo de Moura <leonardo@microsoft.com>
This commit is contained in:
parent
5f360cd8ec
commit
8ad6d7a98b
6 changed files with 879 additions and 785 deletions
|
@ -21,7 +21,7 @@ About
|
|||
- [Design](doc/design.md)
|
||||
- [To Do list](doc/todo.md)
|
||||
- [Authors](doc/authors.md)
|
||||
- [Tutorial](doc/lean/tutorial.md)
|
||||
- [Tutorial](doc/lean/tutorial.org)
|
||||
|
||||
Requirements
|
||||
------------
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -1,97 +0,0 @@
|
|||
Calculational Proofs
|
||||
====================
|
||||
|
||||
A calculational proof is just a chain of intermediate results that are
|
||||
meant to be composed by basic principles such as the transitivity of
|
||||
`=`. In Lean, a calculation proof starts with the keyword `calc`, and has
|
||||
the following syntax
|
||||
|
||||
calc <expr>_0 'op_1' <expr>_1 ':' <proof>_1
|
||||
'...' 'op_2' <expr>_2 ':' <proof>_2
|
||||
...
|
||||
'...' 'op_n' <expr>_n ':' <proof>_n
|
||||
|
||||
Each `<proof>_i` is a proof for `<expr>_{i-1} op_i <expr>_i`.
|
||||
Recall that proofs are also expressions in Lean. The `<proof>_i`
|
||||
may also be of the form `{ <pr> }`, where `<pr>` is a proof
|
||||
for some equality `a = b`. The form `{ <pr> }` is just syntax sugar
|
||||
for
|
||||
|
||||
subst (refl <expr>_{i-1}) <pr>
|
||||
|
||||
That is, we are claiming we can obtain `<expr>_i` by replacing `a` with `b`
|
||||
in `<expr>_{i-1}`.
|
||||
|
||||
Here is an example
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variables a b c d e : Nat.
|
||||
axiom Ax1 : a = b.
|
||||
axiom Ax2 : b = c + 1.
|
||||
axiom Ax3 : c = d.
|
||||
axiom Ax4 : e = 1 + d.
|
||||
|
||||
theorem T : a = e
|
||||
:= calc a = b : Ax1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : Ax2
|
||||
... = d + 1 : { Ax3 }
|
||||
... = 1 + d : Nat::add_comm d 1
|
||||
... = e : symm Ax4.
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The proof expressions `<proof>_i` do not need to be explicitly provided.
|
||||
We can use `by <tactic>` or `by <solver>` to (try to) automatically construct the
|
||||
proof expression using the given tactic or solver.
|
||||
|
||||
Even when tactics and solvers are not used, we can still use the elaboration engine to fill
|
||||
gaps in our calculational proofs. In the previous examples, we can use `_` as arguments for the
|
||||
`Nat::add_comm` theorem. The Lean elaboration engine will infer `d` and `1` for us.
|
||||
Here is the same example using placeholders.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem T' : a = e
|
||||
:= calc a = b : Ax1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : Ax2
|
||||
... = d + 1 : { Ax3 }
|
||||
... = 1 + d : Nat::add_comm _ _
|
||||
... = e : symm Ax4.
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We can also use the operators `=>`, `⇒`, `<=>`, `⇔` and `≠` in calculational proofs.
|
||||
Here is an example.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem T2 (a b c : Nat) (H1 : a = b) (H2 : b = c + 1) : a ≠ 0
|
||||
:= calc a = b : H1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : H2
|
||||
... ≠ 0 : Nat::succ_nz _.
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean `let` construct can also be used to build calculational-like proofs.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable P : Nat → Nat → Bool.
|
||||
variable f : Nat → Nat.
|
||||
axiom Axf (a : Nat) : f (f a) = a.
|
||||
|
||||
theorem T3 (a b : Nat) (H : P (f (f (f (f a)))) (f (f b))) : P a b
|
||||
:= let s1 : P (f (f a)) (f (f b)) := subst H (Axf a),
|
||||
s2 : P a (f (f b)) := subst s1 (Axf a),
|
||||
s3 : P a b := subst s2 (Axf b)
|
||||
in s3.
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Finally, the [Nat (natural number) builtin library](../../src/builtin/Nat.lean) makes extensive use of calculational proofs.
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean simplifier can be used to reduce the size of calculational proofs.
|
||||
In the following example, we create a rewrite rule set with basic theorems from the Natural number library, and some of the axioms
|
||||
declared above.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
import tactic
|
||||
rewrite_set simple
|
||||
add_rewrite Nat::add_comm Nat::add_assoc Nat::add_left_comm Ax1 Ax2 Ax3 eq_id : simple
|
||||
theorem T'' : a = e
|
||||
:= calc a = 1 + d : (by simp simple)
|
||||
... = e : symm Ax4
|
||||
```
|
88
doc/lean/calc.org
Normal file
88
doc/lean/calc.org
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,88 @@
|
|||
* Calculational Proofs
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
A calculational proof is just a chain of intermediate results that are
|
||||
meant to be composed by basic principles such as the transitivity of
|
||||
===. In Lean, a calculation proof starts with the keyword =calc=, and has
|
||||
the following syntax
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC
|
||||
calc <expr>_0 'op_1' <expr>_1 ':' <proof>_1
|
||||
'...' 'op_2' <expr>_2 ':' <proof>_2
|
||||
...
|
||||
'...' 'op_n' <expr>_n ':' <proof>_n
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Each =<proof>_i= is a proof for =<expr>_{i-1} op_i <expr>_i=.
|
||||
Recall that proofs are also expressions in Lean. The =<proof>_i=
|
||||
may also be of the form ={ <pr> }=, where =<pr>= is a proof
|
||||
for some equality =a = b=. The form ={ <pr> }= is just syntax sugar
|
||||
for =subst <pr> (refl <expr>_{i-1})=
|
||||
|
||||
That is, we are claiming we can obtain =<expr>_i= by replacing =a= with =b=
|
||||
in =<expr>_{i-1}=.
|
||||
|
||||
Here is an example
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
variables a b c d e : nat.
|
||||
axiom Ax1 : a = b.
|
||||
axiom Ax2 : b = c + 1.
|
||||
axiom Ax3 : c = d.
|
||||
axiom Ax4 : e = 1 + d.
|
||||
|
||||
theorem T : a = e
|
||||
:= calc a = b : Ax1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : Ax2
|
||||
... = d + 1 : { Ax3 }
|
||||
... = 1 + d : add_comm d 1
|
||||
... = e : symm Ax4.
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The proof expressions =<proof>_i= do not need to be explicitly provided.
|
||||
We can use =by <tactic>= or =by <solver>= to (try to) automatically construct the
|
||||
proof expression using the given tactic or solver.
|
||||
|
||||
Even when tactics and solvers are not used, we can still use the elaboration engine to fill
|
||||
gaps in our calculational proofs. In the previous examples, we can use =_= as arguments for the
|
||||
=add_comm= theorem. The Lean elaboration engine will infer =d= and =1= for us.
|
||||
Here is the same example using placeholders.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
variables a b c d e : nat.
|
||||
axiom Ax1 : a = b.
|
||||
axiom Ax2 : b = c + 1.
|
||||
axiom Ax3 : c = d.
|
||||
axiom Ax4 : e = 1 + d.
|
||||
|
||||
theorem T : a = e
|
||||
:= calc a = b : Ax1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : Ax2
|
||||
... = d + 1 : { Ax3 }
|
||||
... = 1 + d : add_comm _ _
|
||||
... = e : symm Ax4.
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The =calc= command can be configured for any relation that supports
|
||||
some form of transitivity. It can even combine different relations.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
theorem T2 (a b c : nat) (H1 : a = b) (H2 : b = c + 1) : a ≠ 0
|
||||
:= calc a = b : H1
|
||||
... = c + 1 : H2
|
||||
... = succ c : add_one _
|
||||
... ≠ 0 : succ_ne_zero _
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean simplifier can be used to reduce the size of calculational proofs.
|
||||
In the following example, we create a rewrite rule set with basic theorems from the Natural number library, and some of the axioms
|
||||
declared above.
|
|
@ -1,687 +0,0 @@
|
|||
Lean Tutorial
|
||||
=============
|
||||
|
||||
**WARNING: This tutoral is for Lean 0.1, before major modifications performed in version 0.2.
|
||||
Version 0.2 is still under development. [Here you can find a snapshot of Lean 0.1](https://github.com/leanprover/lean0.1).**
|
||||
|
||||
Introduction
|
||||
------------
|
||||
|
||||
Lean is an automatic and interactive theorem prover. It can be used to
|
||||
create specifications, build mathematical libraries, and solve
|
||||
constraints. In this tutorial, we introduce basic concepts, the logic
|
||||
used in Lean, and the main commands.
|
||||
|
||||
Getting started
|
||||
---------------
|
||||
|
||||
We can use Lean in interactive or batch mode.
|
||||
The following example just displays the message `hello world`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
print "hello world"
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
All we have to do to run your first example is to call the `lean` executable
|
||||
with the name of the text file that contains the command above.
|
||||
If you saved the above command in the file `hello.lean`, then you just have
|
||||
to execute
|
||||
|
||||
lean hello.lean
|
||||
|
||||
As a more complex example, the next example defines a function that doubles
|
||||
the input value.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
-- defines the double function
|
||||
definition double (x : Nat) := x + x
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Basics
|
||||
------
|
||||
|
||||
We can also view Lean as a suite of tools for evaluating and processing
|
||||
expressions representing terms, definitions, and theorems.
|
||||
|
||||
Every expression has a unique type in Lean. The command `check` returns the
|
||||
type of a given expression.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check double 3
|
||||
check double
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The last command returns `Nat → Nat`. That is, the type of double is a function
|
||||
from `Nat` to `Nat`, where `Nat` is the type of the natural numbers.
|
||||
|
||||
The command `import` loads existing libraries and extensions. The
|
||||
following command imports the command `find` that searches the Lean
|
||||
environment using regular expressions
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
import find
|
||||
|
||||
find "Nat" -- find all object that start with the prefix Nat
|
||||
check Nat::ge -- display the signature of the Nat::ge definition
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We say `Nat::ge` is a hierarchical name comprised of two parts: `Nat` and `ge`
|
||||
|
||||
The command `using` creates aliases based on a given prefix. For example, the following
|
||||
command creates aliases for all objects starting with `Nat`
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
using Nat
|
||||
check ge -- display the signature of the Nat::ge definition
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The command `variable` assigns a type to an identifier. The following command postulates/assumes
|
||||
that `n`, `m` and `o` have type `Nat`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable n : Nat
|
||||
variable m : Nat
|
||||
variable o : Nat
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The command `variables n m o : Nat` can be used a shorthand for the three commands above.
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, proofs are also expressions, and all functionality provided for manipulating
|
||||
expressions is also available for manipulating proofs. For example, `refl n` is a proof
|
||||
for `n = n`. In Lean, `refl` is the reflexivity theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check refl n
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The command `axiom` postulates that a given proposition (aka Boolean formula) is true.
|
||||
The following commands postulate two axioms `Ax1` and `Ax2` that state that `n = m` and
|
||||
`m = o`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
axiom Ax1 : n = m
|
||||
axiom Ax2 : m = o
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
`Ax1` and `Ax2` are not just names. For example, `trans Ax1 Ax2` is a proof that
|
||||
`n = o`, where `trans` is the transitivity theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check trans Ax1 Ax2
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `trans Ax1 Ax2` is just a function application like any other.
|
||||
Moreover, in Lean, _propositions are types_. Any Boolean expression `P` can be used
|
||||
as a type. The elements of type `P` can be viewed as the proofs of `P`.
|
||||
Moreover, in Lean, _proof checking is type checking_. For example, the Lean type checker
|
||||
will reject the type incorrect term `trans Ax2 Ax1`.
|
||||
|
||||
Because we use _proposition as types_, we must support _empty types_. For example,
|
||||
the type `false` must be empty, since we don't have a proof for `false`.
|
||||
|
||||
Most systems based on the _propositions as types_ paradigm are based on constructive logic.
|
||||
Lean on the other hand is based on classical logic. The _excluded middle_ is a theorem
|
||||
in Lean, and `em p` is a proof for `p ∨ ¬ p`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable p : Bool
|
||||
check em p
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The commands `axiom` and `variable` are essentially the same command. We provide both
|
||||
just to make Lean files more readable. We encourage users to use `axiom` only for
|
||||
propostions, and `variable` for everything else.
|
||||
|
||||
Similarly, a theorem is just a definition. The following command defines a new theorem
|
||||
called `nat_trans3`
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem nat_trans3 (a b c d : Nat) (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d
|
||||
:= trans (trans H1 (symm H2)) H3
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The theorem `nat_trans3` has 7 parameters, it takes for natural numbers `a`, `b`, `c` and `d`,
|
||||
and three proofs showing that `a = b`, `c = b` and `c = d`, and returns a proof that `a = d`.
|
||||
In the example above, `symm` is the symmetry theorem. Now, we use `nat_trans3` in a simple
|
||||
example.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variables x y z w : Nat
|
||||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||||
check nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The theorem `nat_trans3` is somewhat inconvenient to use because it has 7 parameters.
|
||||
However, the first four parameters can be inferred from the last 3. We can use `_` as a placeholder
|
||||
that instructs Lean to synthesize this expression. The synthesis process is based on type inference, and it is
|
||||
the most basic form of automation provided by Lean.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check nat_trans3 _ _ _ _ Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Lean also supports _implicit arguments_.
|
||||
We mark implicit arguments using curly braces instead of parenthesis.
|
||||
In the following example, we define the theorem `nat_trans3i` using implicit arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem nat_trans3i {a b c d : Nat} (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d
|
||||
:= trans (trans H1 (symm H2)) H3
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
It is identical to `nat_trans3`, the only difference is the use of curly braces.
|
||||
Lean will (try to) infer the implicit arguments. The idea behind implicit arguments
|
||||
is quite simple, we are just instructing Lean to automatically insert the placeholders
|
||||
`_` for us.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Sometimes, Lean will not be able to infer the parameters automatically.
|
||||
So, whenever we define a theorem/definition/axiom/variable containing implicit arguments, Lean will
|
||||
automatically create an _explicit_ version where all parameters are explicit.
|
||||
The explicit version uses the same name with a `@` prefix.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @nat_trans3i
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The theorems `refl`, `trans` and `symm` all have implicit arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @refl
|
||||
check @trans
|
||||
check @symm
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We can also instruct Lean to display all implicit arguments when it prints expressions.
|
||||
This is useful when debugging non-trivial problems.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
set_option pp::implicit true -- show implicit arguments
|
||||
check nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
set_option pp::implicit false -- hide implicit arguments
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
In the previous example, the `check` command stated that `nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw`
|
||||
has type `@eq ℕ x w`. The expression `x = w` is just notational convenience.
|
||||
|
||||
We have seen many occurrences of `(Type U)`, where `U` is a _universe variable_.
|
||||
In Lean, the type of `Nat` and `Bool` is `Type`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check Nat
|
||||
check Bool
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We say `Type` is the type of all _small_ types, but what is the type of `Type`?
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check Type
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Lean returns `(Type 1)`. Similarly, the type of `(Type 1)` is `(Type 2)`. In Lean, we also have _universe cumulativity_.
|
||||
That is, we can provide an element of type `(Type i)` where an element of type `(Type j)` is expected when `i ≤ j`.
|
||||
This makes the system more convenient to use. Otherwise, we would need a reflexivity theorem for `Type` (i.e., `(Type 0)`),
|
||||
`Type 1`, `Type 2`, etc. Universe cumulativity improves usability, but it is not enough because
|
||||
we would still have the question: how big should `i` be? Moreover, if we choose an `i` that is not big enough
|
||||
we have to go back and correct all libraries. This is not satisfactory and not modular.
|
||||
So, in Lean, we allow users to declare _universe variables_ and simple constraints between them. The Lean kernel defines
|
||||
one universe variable `U`, and states that `U ≥ 1` using the command `universe U ≥ 1`.
|
||||
The Lean type casting library defines another universe variable called `M` and states that `universe M ≥ 1`.
|
||||
In Lean, whenever we declare a new universe `V`, the system automatically adds the constraint `U ≥ V + 1`.
|
||||
That is, `U` the _maximal_ universe in Lean.
|
||||
Lean reports an universe inconsistency if the universe constraints are inconsistent. For example, it will return an error
|
||||
if execute the command `universe M ≥ U`. We can view universe variables as placeholders, and we can always solve
|
||||
the universe constraints and find and assignment for the universe variables used in our developments.
|
||||
This assignment allows us to automatically generate a Lean specification that is not based on this particular feature.
|
||||
|
||||
Propositional logic
|
||||
-------------------
|
||||
|
||||
To manipulate formulas with a richer logical structure, it is important to master the notation Lean uses for building
|
||||
composite logical expressions out of basic formulas using _logical connectives_. The logical connectives (`and`, `or`, `not`, etc)
|
||||
are defined in the Lean [kernel](../../src/builtin/kernel.lean). The kernel also defines notational convention for rewriting formulas
|
||||
in a natural way. Here is a table showing the notation for the so called propositional (or Boolean) connectives.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
| Ascii | Ascii alt. | Unicode | Definition |
|
||||
|-------|--------------|---------|--------------|
|
||||
| true | | ⊤ | true |
|
||||
| false | | ⊥ | false |
|
||||
| not | | ¬ | not |
|
||||
| /\ | && | ∧ | and |
|
||||
| \/ | || | ∨ | or |
|
||||
| -> | | → | implies |
|
||||
| <-> | | ↔ | iff |
|
||||
|
||||
`true` and `false` are logical constants to denote the true and false propositions. Logical negation is a unary operator just like
|
||||
arithmetical negation on numbers. The other connectives are all binary operators. The meaning of the operators is the usual one.
|
||||
The table above makes clear that Lean supports unicode characters. We can use Ascii or/and unicode versions.
|
||||
Here is a simple example using the connectives above.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable q : Bool
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
check ¬ p → p ↔ false
|
||||
check p ∨ q → q ∨ p
|
||||
-- Ascii version
|
||||
check p -> q -> p && q
|
||||
check not p -> p <-> false
|
||||
check p || q -> q \/ p
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Depending on the platform, Lean uses unicode characters by default when printing expressions. The following commands can be used to
|
||||
change this behavior.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
set_option pp::unicode false
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
set_option pp::unicode true
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Note that, it may seem that the symbols `->` and `→` are overloaded, and Lean uses them to represent Boolean implication and the type
|
||||
of functions. Actually, they are not overloaded, they are the same symbols. In Lean, the Boolean `p → q` expression is also the type
|
||||
of the functions that given a proof for `p`, returns a proof for `q`. This is very convenient for writing proofs.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
-- Hpq is a function that takes a proof for p and returns a proof for q
|
||||
axiom Hpq : p → q
|
||||
-- Hq is a proof/certificate for p
|
||||
axiom Hp : p
|
||||
-- The expression Hpq Hp is a proof/certificate for q
|
||||
check Hpq Hp
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
In composite expressions, the precedences of the various binary
|
||||
connectives are in order of the above table, with `and` being the
|
||||
strongest and `iff` the weakest. For example, `a ∧ b → c ∨ d ∧ e`
|
||||
means `(a ∧ b) → (c ∨ (d ∧ e))`. All of them are right-associative.
|
||||
So, `p ∧ q ∧ r` means `p ∧ (q ∧ r)`. The actual precedence and fixity of all
|
||||
logical connectives is defined in the Lean [kernel definition file](../../src/builtin/kernel.lean).
|
||||
|
||||
Finally, `not`, `and`, `or` and `iff` are the actual names used when
|
||||
defining the Boolean connectives. They can be used as any other function.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check and
|
||||
check or
|
||||
check not
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Lean supports _currying_ `and true` is a function from `Bool` to `Bool`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check and true
|
||||
definition id := and true
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Functions
|
||||
---------
|
||||
|
||||
There are many variable-binding constructs in mathematics. Lean expresses
|
||||
all of them using just one _abstraction_, which is a converse operation to
|
||||
function application. Given a variable `x`, a type `A`, and a term `t` that
|
||||
may or may not contain `x`, one can construct the so-called _lambda abstraction_
|
||||
`fun x : A, t`, or using unicode notation `λ x : A, t`. Here is some simple
|
||||
examples.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun x : Nat, x + 1
|
||||
check fun x y : Nat, x + 2 * y
|
||||
check fun x y : Bool, not (x ∧ y)
|
||||
check λ x : Nat, x + 1
|
||||
check λ (x : Nat) (p : Bool), x = 0 ∨ p
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
In many cases, Lean can automatically infer the type of the variable. Actually,
|
||||
In all examples above, the type can be inferred automatically.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun x, x + 1
|
||||
check fun x y, x + 2 * y
|
||||
check fun x y, not (x ∧ y)
|
||||
check λ x, x + 1
|
||||
check λ x p, x = 0 ∨ p
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
However, Lean will complain that it cannot infer the type of the
|
||||
variable `x` in `fun x, x` because any type would work in this example.
|
||||
|
||||
The following example shows how to use lambda abstractions in
|
||||
function applications
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1
|
||||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1 2
|
||||
check (fun x y, not (x ∧ y)) true false
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Lambda abstractions are also used to create proofs for propositions of the form `A → B`.
|
||||
This should be natural since we can "view" `A → B` as the type of functions that given
|
||||
a proof for `A` returns a proof for `B`.
|
||||
For example, a proof for `p → p` is just `fun H : p, H` (the identity function).
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun H : p, H
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Definitional equality
|
||||
---------------------
|
||||
|
||||
The command `eval t` computes a normal form for the term `t`.
|
||||
In Lean, we say two terms are _definitionally equal_ if the have the same
|
||||
normal form. For example, the terms `(λ x : Nat, x + 1) a` and `a + 1`
|
||||
are definitionally equal. The Lean type/proof checker uses the normalizer when
|
||||
checking types/proofs. So, we can prove that two definitionally equal terms
|
||||
are equal using just `refl`. Here is a simple example.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem def_eq_th (a : Nat) : ((λ x : Nat, x + 1) a) = a + 1
|
||||
:= refl (a+1)
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Provable equality
|
||||
-----------------
|
||||
|
||||
In the previous examples, we have used `nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw`
|
||||
to show that `x = w`. In this case, `x` and `w` are not definitionally equal,
|
||||
but they are provably equal in the environment that contains `nat_trans3` and
|
||||
axioms `Hxy`, `Hzy` and `Hzw`.
|
||||
|
||||
Proving
|
||||
-------
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean kernel contains basic theorems for creating proof terms. The
|
||||
basic theorems are useful for creating manual proofs. The are also the
|
||||
basic building blocks used by all automated proof engines available in
|
||||
Lean. The theorems can be broken into three different categories:
|
||||
introduction, elimination, and rewriting. First, we cover the introduction
|
||||
and elimination theorems for the basic Boolean connectives.
|
||||
|
||||
### And (conjuction)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `and_intro H1 H2` creates a proof for `a ∧ b` using proofs
|
||||
`H1 : a` and `H2 : b`. We say `and_intro` is the _and-introduction_ operation.
|
||||
In the following example we use `and_intro` for creating a proof for
|
||||
`p → q → p ∧ q`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun (Hp : p) (Hq : q), and_intro Hp Hq
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `and_eliml H` creates a proof `a` from a proof `H : a ∧ b`.
|
||||
Similarly `and_elimr H` is a proof for `b`. We say they are the _left/right and-elimination_.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → p
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_eliml H
|
||||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → q
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_elimr H
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Now, we prove `p ∧ q → q ∧ p` with the following simple proof term.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_intro (and_elimr H) (and_eliml H)
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Note that the proof term is very similar to a function that just swaps the
|
||||
elements of a pair.
|
||||
|
||||
### Or (disjuction)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `or_introl H1 b` creates a proof for `a ∨ b` using a proof `H1 : a`.
|
||||
Similarly, `or_intror a H2` creates a proof for `a ∨ b` using a proof `H2 : b`.
|
||||
We say they are the _left/right or-introduction_.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
-- Proof for p → p ∨ q
|
||||
check fun H : p, or_introl H q
|
||||
-- Proof for q → p ∨ q
|
||||
check fun H : q, or_intror p H
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The or-elimination rule is slightly more complicated. The basic idea is the
|
||||
following, we can prove `c` from `a ∨ b`, by showing we can prove `c`
|
||||
by assuming `a` or by assuming `b`. It is essentially a proof by cases.
|
||||
`or_elim Hab Hac Hbc` takes three arguments `Hab : a ∨ b`, `Hac : a → c` and `Hbc : b → c` and produces a proof for `c`.
|
||||
In the following example, we use `or_elim` to prove that `p v q → q ∨ p`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check fun H : p ∨ q,
|
||||
or_elim H
|
||||
(fun Hp : p, or_intror q Hp)
|
||||
(fun Hq : q, or_introl Hq p)
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
### Not (negation)
|
||||
|
||||
`not_intro H` produces a proof for `¬ a` from `H : a → false`. That is,
|
||||
we obtain `¬ a` if we can derive `false` from `a`. The expression
|
||||
`absurd_elim b Ha Hna` produces a proof for `b` from `Ha : a` and `Hna : ¬ a`.
|
||||
That is, we can deduce anything if we have `a` and `¬ a`.
|
||||
We now use `not_intro` and `absurd_elim` to produce a proof term for
|
||||
`(a → b) → ¬ b → ¬ a`
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variables a b : Bool
|
||||
check fun (Hab : a → b) (Hnb : ¬ b),
|
||||
not_intro (fun Ha : a, absurd_elim false (Hab Ha) Hnb)
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Here is the proof term for `¬ a → b → (b → a) → c`
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable c : Bool
|
||||
check fun (Hna : ¬ a) (Hb : b) (Hba : b → a),
|
||||
absurd_elim c (Hba Hb) Hna
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
### Iff (if-and-only-if)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `iff_intro H1 H2` produces a proof for `a ↔ b` from `H1 : a → b` and `H2 : b → a`.
|
||||
`iff_eliml H` produces a proof for `a → b` from `H : a ↔ b`. Similarly,
|
||||
`iff_elimr H` produces a proof for `b → a` from `H : a ↔ b`.
|
||||
Note that, in Lean, `a ↔ b` is definitionally equal to `a = b` when `a` and `b` have type `Bool`.
|
||||
Here is the proof term for `a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a`
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check iff_intro (fun H : a ∧ b, and_intro (and_elimr H) (and_eliml H))
|
||||
(fun H : b ∧ a, and_intro (and_elimr H) (and_eliml H))
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
### True and False
|
||||
|
||||
The expression `trivial` is a proof term for `true`, and `false_elim a H`
|
||||
produces a proof for `a` from `H : false`.
|
||||
|
||||
Other basic operators used in proof construction are `eqt_intro`, `eqt_elim`, `eqf_intro` and `eqf_elim`.
|
||||
`eqt_intro H` produces a proof for `a ↔ true` from `H : a`.
|
||||
`eqt_elim H` produces a proof for `a` from `H : a ↔ true`.
|
||||
`eqf_intro H` produces a proof for `a ↔ false` from `H : ¬ a`.
|
||||
`eqf_elim H` produces a proof for `¬ a` from `H : a ↔ false`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @eqt_intro
|
||||
check @eqt_elim
|
||||
check @eqf_intro
|
||||
check @eqf_elim
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
### Rewrite rules
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean kernel also contains many theorems that are meant to be used as rewriting/simplification rules.
|
||||
The conclusion of these theorems is of the form `t = s` or `t ↔ s`. For example, `and_id a` is proof term for
|
||||
`a ∧ a ↔ a`. The Lean simplifier can use these theorems to automatically create proof terms for us.
|
||||
The expression `(by simp [rule-set])` is similar to `_`, but it tells Lean to synthesize the proof term using the simplifier
|
||||
using the rewrite rule set named `[rule-set]`. In the following example, we create a simple rewrite rule set
|
||||
and use it to prove a theorem that would be quite tedious to prove by hand.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
-- import module that defines several tactics/strategies including "simp"
|
||||
import tactic
|
||||
-- create a rewrite rule set with name 'simple'
|
||||
rewrite_set simple
|
||||
-- add some theorems to the rewrite rule set 'simple'
|
||||
add_rewrite and_id and_truer and_truel and_comm and_assoc and_left_comm iff_id : simple
|
||||
theorem th1 (a b : Bool) : a ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ↔ a ∧ b
|
||||
:= (by simp simple)
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, we can combine manual and automated proofs in a natural way. We can manually write the proof
|
||||
skeleton and use the `by` construct to invoke automated proof engines like the simplifier for filling the
|
||||
tedious steps. Here is a very simple example.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem th2 (a b : Bool) : a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a
|
||||
:= iff_intro
|
||||
(fun H : a ∧ b, (by simp simple))
|
||||
(fun H : b ∧ a, (by simp simple))
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
### Dependent functions and quantifiers
|
||||
|
||||
Lean supports _dependent functions_. In type theory, they are also called dependent product types or Pi-types.
|
||||
The idea is quite simple, suppose we have a type `A` in some universe `(Type i)`, and a family of types `B : A → (Type j)` which assigns to each `a : A` a type `B a`. So a dependent function is a function whose range varies depending on its arguments.
|
||||
In lean, the dependent functions is written as `forall a : A, B a`, or `∀ x : A, B a` using unicode.
|
||||
The proposition as types paradigm is based on dependent functions. In the previous examples, we have seen many examples of dependent functions. The theorems `refl`, `trans` and `symm`, and the equality are all dependent functions,
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @refl
|
||||
check @trans
|
||||
check @symm
|
||||
check @eq
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The universal quantifier is also a dependent function. In Lean, if we have a family of types `B : A → Bool`, then `∀ x : A, B a` has type `Bool`. This features complicates the Lean set-theoretic model, but it improves usability. Several theorem provers have a `forall elimination` (aka instantiation) proof rule. In Lean (and other systems based on proposition as types), this rule is just function application. In the following example we add an axiom stating that `f x` is `0` forall `x`. Then we instantiate the axiom using function application.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
variable f : Nat → Nat
|
||||
axiom fzero : ∀ x, f x = 0
|
||||
check fzero 1
|
||||
check fzero x
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Since we instantiate quantifiers using function application, it is
|
||||
natural to create proof terms for universal quantifiers using lambda
|
||||
abstraction. In the following example, we create a proof term showing that for all
|
||||
`x` and `y`, `f x = f y`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check λ x y, trans (fzero x) (symm (fzero y))
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We can view the proof term above as a simple function or "recipe" for showing that
|
||||
`f x = f y` for any `x` and `y`. The function "invokes" `fzero` for creating
|
||||
proof terms for `f x = 0` and `f y = 0`. Then, it uses symmetry `symm` to create
|
||||
a proof term for `0 = f y`. Finally, transitivity is used to combine the proofs
|
||||
for `f x = 0` and `0 = f y`.
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, the existential quantifier `exists x : A, B x` is defined as `¬ forall x : A, ¬ B x`.
|
||||
We can also write existential quantifiers as `∃ x : A, B x`. Actually both versions are just
|
||||
notational convenience for `Exists A (fun x : A, B x)`. That is, the existential quantifier
|
||||
is actually a constant defined in the file `kernel.lean`. This file also defines the
|
||||
`exists_intro` and `exists_elim` theorems. To build a proof for `∃ x : A, B x`, we should
|
||||
provide a term `w : A` and a proof term `Hw : B w` to `exists_intro`.
|
||||
We say `w` is the witness for the existential introduction. In previous examples,
|
||||
`nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw` was a proof term for `x = w`. Then, we can create a proof term
|
||||
for `∃ a : Nat, a = w` using
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
theorem ex_a_eq_w : exists a, a = w := exists_intro x (nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw)
|
||||
check ex_a_eq_w
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Note that `exists_intro` also has implicit arguments. For example, Lean has to infer the implicit argument
|
||||
`P : A → Bool`, a predicate (aka function to Bool). This creates complications. For example, suppose
|
||||
we have `Hg : g 0 0 = 0` and we invoke `exists_intro 0 Hg`. There are different possible values for `P`.
|
||||
Each possible value corresponds to a different theorem: `∃ x, g x x = x`, `∃ x, g x x = 0`,
|
||||
`∃ x, g x 0 = x`, etc. Lean uses the context where `exists_intro` occurs to infer the users intent.
|
||||
In the example above, we were trying to prove the theorem `∃ a, a = w`. So, we are implicitly telling
|
||||
Lean how to choose `P`. In the following example, we demonstrate this issue. We ask Lean to display
|
||||
the implicit arguments using the option `pp::implicit`. We see that each instance of `exists_intro 0 Hg`
|
||||
has different values for the implicit argument `P`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @exists_intro
|
||||
variable g : Nat → Nat → Nat
|
||||
axiom Hg : g 0 0 = 0
|
||||
theorem gex1 : ∃ x, g x x = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex2 : ∃ x, g x 0 = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex3 : ∃ x, g 0 0 = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex4 : ∃ x, g x x = 0 := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
set_option pp::implicit true -- display implicit arguments
|
||||
print environment 4 -- print the last four theorems
|
||||
set_option pp::implicit false -- hide implicit arguments
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
We can view `exists_intro` (aka existential introduction) as an information hiding procedure.
|
||||
We are "hiding" what is the witness for some fact. The existential elimination performs the opposite
|
||||
operation. The `exists_elim` theorem allows us to prove some proposition `B` from `∃ x : A, B x`
|
||||
if we can derive `B` using an "abstract" witness `w` and a proof term `Hw : B w`.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
check @exists_elim
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
In the following example, we define `even a` as `∃ b, a = 2*b`, and then we show that the sum
|
||||
of two even numbers is an even number.
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
definition even (a : Nat) := ∃ b, a = 2*b
|
||||
theorem EvenPlusEven {a b : Nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b)
|
||||
:= exists_elim H1 (fun (w1 : Nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1),
|
||||
exists_elim H2 (fun (w2 : Nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2),
|
||||
exists_intro (w1 + w2)
|
||||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : { Hw1 }
|
||||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : { Hw2 }
|
||||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : symm (distributer 2 w1 w2))))
|
||||
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The example above also uses [_calculational proofs_](calc.md) to show that `a + b = 2*(w1 + w2)`.
|
||||
The `calc` construct is just syntax sugar for creating proofs using transitivity and substitution.
|
||||
|
||||
The module `macros` provides notation for making proof terms more readable.
|
||||
For example, it defines the `obtain _, from _, _` macro as syntax sugar for `exists_elim`.
|
||||
With this macro we can write the example above as:
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
import macros
|
||||
theorem EvenPlusEven2 {a b : Nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b)
|
||||
:= obtain (w1 : Nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1), from H1,
|
||||
obtain (w2 : Nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2), from H2,
|
||||
exists_intro (w1 + w2)
|
||||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : { Hw1 }
|
||||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : { Hw2 }
|
||||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : symm (distributer 2 w1 w2))
|
||||
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
The module `macros` also defines `take x : A, H` and `assume x : A, H`
|
||||
as syntax sugar for `fun x : A, H`. This may been silly, but it allows us to simulate [Mizar](http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Mizar_system)-style declarative proofs in Lean. Using these macros, we can write
|
||||
|
||||
```lean
|
||||
definition Set (A : Type) : Type := A → Bool
|
||||
|
||||
definition element {A : Type} (x : A) (s : Set A) := s x
|
||||
infix 60 ∈ : element
|
||||
|
||||
definition subset {A : Type} (s1 : Set A) (s2 : Set A) := ∀ x, x ∈ s1 → x ∈ s2
|
||||
infix 50 ⊆ : subset
|
||||
|
||||
theorem subset_trans {A : Type} {s1 s2 s3 : Set A} (H1 : s1 ⊆ s2) (H2 : s2 ⊆ s3) : s1 ⊆ s3
|
||||
:= take x : A,
|
||||
assume Hin : x ∈ s1,
|
||||
show x ∈ s3, from
|
||||
let L1 : x ∈ s2 := H1 x Hin
|
||||
in H2 x L1
|
||||
```
|
||||
|
||||
Finally, the construct `show A, from H` means "have" a proof for `A` using `H`. It is just syntax sugar for
|
||||
`let H_show : A := H in H_show`. It is useful to document intermediate steps in manually constructed proofs.
|
788
doc/lean/tutorial.org
Normal file
788
doc/lean/tutorial.org
Normal file
|
@ -0,0 +1,788 @@
|
|||
* Lean Tutorial
|
||||
|
||||
** Introduction
|
||||
|
||||
Lean is an automatic and interactive theorem prover. It can be used to
|
||||
create specifications, build mathematical libraries, and solve
|
||||
constraints. In this tutorial, we introduce basic concepts, the logic
|
||||
used in Lean, and the main commands.
|
||||
|
||||
** Getting started
|
||||
|
||||
We can use Lean in interactive or batch mode.
|
||||
The following example just displays the message `hello world`.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
print "hello world"
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
All we have to do to run your first example is to call the =lean= executable
|
||||
with the name of the text file that contains the command above.
|
||||
If you saved the above command in the file =hello.lean=, then you just have
|
||||
to execute
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC shell
|
||||
lean hello.lean
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
As a more complex example, the next example defines a function that doubles
|
||||
the input value.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
-- defines the double function
|
||||
definition double (x : nat) := x + x
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
** Basics
|
||||
|
||||
We can also view Lean as a suite of tools for evaluating and processing
|
||||
expressions representing terms, definitions, and theorems.
|
||||
|
||||
Every expression has a unique type in Lean. The command =check= returns the
|
||||
type of a given expression.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
check true
|
||||
check and
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The last command returns =Prop → Prop → Prop=. That is, the type of
|
||||
=and= is a function that takes two _propositions_ and return a
|
||||
proposition, =Prop= is the type of propositions.
|
||||
|
||||
The command =import= loads existing libraries and extensions.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
check nat.ge
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
We say =nat.ge= is a hierarchical name comprised of two parts: =nat= and =ge=.
|
||||
|
||||
The command =using= creates aliases based on a given prefix. The
|
||||
command also imports notation, hints, and other features. We will
|
||||
discuss its other applications later. Regarding aliases,
|
||||
the following command creates aliases for all objects starting with
|
||||
=nat=, and imports all notations defined in this namespace.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
check ge -- display the type of nat.ge
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The command =variable= assigns a type to an identifier. The following command postulates/assumes
|
||||
that =n=, =m= and =o= have type =nat=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
variable n : nat
|
||||
variable m : nat
|
||||
variable o : nat
|
||||
-- The command 'using nat' also imported the notation defined at the namespace 'nat'
|
||||
check n + m
|
||||
check n ≤ m
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The command =variables n m o : nat= can be used as a shorthand for the three commands above.
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, proofs are also expressions, and all functionality provided for manipulating
|
||||
expressions is also available for manipulating proofs. For example, =refl n= is a proof
|
||||
for =n = n=. In Lean, =refl= is the reflexivity theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
variable n : nat
|
||||
check refl n
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The command =axiom= postulates that a given proposition holds.
|
||||
The following commands postulate two axioms =Ax1= and =Ax2= that state that =n = m= and
|
||||
=m = o=. =Ax1= and =Ax2= are not just names. For example, =trans Ax1 Ax2= is a proof that
|
||||
=n = o=, where =trans= is the transitivity theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
variables m n o : nat
|
||||
axiom Ax1 : n = m
|
||||
axiom Ax2 : m = o
|
||||
check trans Ax1 Ax2
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =trans Ax1 Ax2= is just a function application like any other.
|
||||
Moreover, in Lean, _propositions are types_. Any proposition =P= can be used
|
||||
as a type. The elements of type =P= can be viewed as the proofs of =P=.
|
||||
Moreover, in Lean, _proof checking is type checking_. For example, the Lean type checker
|
||||
will reject the type incorrect term =trans Ax2 Ax1=.
|
||||
|
||||
Because we use _proposition as types_, we must support _empty types_. For example,
|
||||
the type =false= must be empty, since we don't have a proof for =false=.
|
||||
|
||||
Most systems based on the _propositions as types_ paradigm are based on constructive logic.
|
||||
In Lean, we support classical and constructive logic. We can load
|
||||
_classical axiom_ by using =import classical=. When the classical
|
||||
extensions are loaded, the _excluded middle_ is a theorem,
|
||||
and =em p= is a proof for =p ∨ ¬ p=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import classical
|
||||
variable p : Prop
|
||||
check em p
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The commands =axiom= and =variable= are essentially the same command. We provide both
|
||||
just to make Lean files more readable. We encourage users to use =axiom= only for
|
||||
propositions, and =variable= for everything else.
|
||||
|
||||
Similarly, a theorem is just a definition. The following command defines a new theorem
|
||||
called =nat_trans3=, and then use it to prove something else. In this
|
||||
example, =symm= is the symmetry theorem.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
theorem nat_trans3 (a b c d : nat) (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d
|
||||
:= trans (trans H1 (symm H2)) H3
|
||||
|
||||
-- Example using nat_trans3
|
||||
variables x y z w : nat
|
||||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||||
check nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The theorem =nat_trans3= has 7 parameters, it takes for natural numbers =a=, =b=, =c= and =d=,
|
||||
and three proofs showing that =a = b=, =c = b= and =c = d=, and returns a proof that =a = d=.
|
||||
|
||||
The theorem =nat_trans3= is somewhat inconvenient to use because it has 7 parameters.
|
||||
However, the first four parameters can be inferred from the last 3. We can use =_= as a placeholder
|
||||
that instructs Lean to synthesize this expression. The synthesis process is based on type inference, and it is
|
||||
the most basic form of automation provided by Lean.
|
||||
In the example above, we can use =check nat_trans3 _ _ _ _ Hxy Hzy Hzw=.
|
||||
|
||||
Lean also supports _implicit arguments_.
|
||||
We mark implicit arguments using curly braces instead of parenthesis.
|
||||
In the following example, we define the theorem =nat_trans3i= using
|
||||
implicit arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
theorem nat_trans3i {a b c d : nat} (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d
|
||||
:= trans (trans H1 (symm H2)) H3
|
||||
|
||||
-- Example using nat_trans3
|
||||
variables x y z w : nat
|
||||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||||
check nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
It is identical to =nat_trans3=, the only difference is the use of curly braces.
|
||||
Lean will (try to) infer the implicit arguments. The idea behind implicit arguments
|
||||
is quite simple, we are just instructing Lean to automatically insert the placeholders
|
||||
=_= for us.
|
||||
|
||||
Sometimes, Lean will not be able to infer the parameters automatically.
|
||||
The annotation =@f= instructs Lean that we want to provide the
|
||||
implicit arguments for =f= explicitly.
|
||||
The theorems =refl=, =trans= and =symm= all have implicit arguments.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
check @refl
|
||||
check @symm
|
||||
check @trans
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
We can also instruct Lean to display all implicit arguments when it prints expressions.
|
||||
This is useful when debugging non-trivial problems.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
variables a b c : nat
|
||||
axiom H1 : a = b
|
||||
axiom H2 : b = c
|
||||
check trans H1 H2
|
||||
|
||||
set_option pp.implicit true
|
||||
-- Now, Lean will display all implicit arguments
|
||||
check trans H1 H2
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In the previous example, the =check= command stated that =trans H1 H2=
|
||||
has type =@eq ℕ a c=. The expression =a = c= is just notational convenience.
|
||||
|
||||
We have seen many occurrences of =Type=.
|
||||
In Lean, the type of =nat= and =Prop= is =Type=.
|
||||
What is the type of =Type=?
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
check Type
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Lean reports =Type : Type=, is it Lean inconsistent? Now, it is not.
|
||||
Internally, Lean maintains a hierarchy of Types. We say each one of
|
||||
them _lives_ in a universe. Lean is universe polymorphic, and by
|
||||
default all universes are hidden from the user. Like implicit
|
||||
arguments, we can instruct Lean to display the universe levels
|
||||
explicitly.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
set_option pp.universes true
|
||||
check Type
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In the command above, Lean reports that =Type.{l_1}= that lives in
|
||||
universe =l_1= has type =Type.{succ l_1}=. That is, its type lives in
|
||||
the universe =l_1 + 1=.
|
||||
|
||||
Definitions such as =refl=, =symm= and =trans= are all universe
|
||||
polymorphic.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
set_option pp.universes true
|
||||
check @refl
|
||||
check @symm
|
||||
check @trans
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Whenever we declare a new constant, Lean automatically infers the
|
||||
universe parameters. We can also provide the universe levels
|
||||
explicitly.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
|
||||
definition id.{l} {A : Type.{l}} (a : A) : Type.{l}
|
||||
:= a
|
||||
|
||||
check id true
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The universes can be explicitly provided for each constant and =Type=
|
||||
by using the notation =.{ ... }=. Unlike other systems, Lean does not
|
||||
have _universe cumulativity_. That is, the type =Type.{i}= is *not* an
|
||||
element of =Type.{j}= for =j > i=.
|
||||
|
||||
** Propositional logic
|
||||
|
||||
To manipulate formulas with a richer logical structure, it is important to master the notation Lean uses for building
|
||||
composite logical expressions out of basic formulas using _logical connectives_. The logical connectives (=and=, =or=, =not=, etc)
|
||||
are defined in the file [[../../library/standard/logic.lean][logic.lean]]. This file also defines notational convention for writing formulas
|
||||
in a natural way. Here is a table showing the notation for the so called propositional (or Boolean) connectives.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
| Ascii | Unicode | Definition |
|
||||
|-------|-----------------------|--------------|
|
||||
| true | | true |
|
||||
| false | | false |
|
||||
| not | ¬ | not |
|
||||
| /\ | ∧ | and |
|
||||
| \/ | ∨ | or |
|
||||
| -> | → | |
|
||||
| <-> | ↔ | iff |
|
||||
|
||||
=true= and =false= are logical constants to denote the true and false propositions. Logical negation is a unary operator just like
|
||||
arithmetical negation on numbers. The other connectives are all binary operators. The meaning of the operators is the usual one.
|
||||
The table above makes clear that Lean supports unicode characters. We can use Ascii or/and unicode versions.
|
||||
Here is a simple example using the connectives above.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
check ¬p → p ↔ false
|
||||
check p ∨ q → q ∨ p
|
||||
-- Ascii version
|
||||
check p -> q -> p /\ q
|
||||
check not p -> p <-> false
|
||||
check p \/ q -> q \/ p
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Depending on the platform, Lean uses unicode characters by default when printing expressions. The following commands can be used to
|
||||
change this behavior.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
set_option pp.unicode false
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
set_option pp.unicode true
|
||||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Note that, it may seem that the symbols =->= and =→= are overloaded, and Lean uses them to represent implication and the type
|
||||
of functions. Actually, they are not overloaded, they are the same symbols. In Lean, the Proposition =p → q= expression is also the type
|
||||
of the functions that given a proof for =p=, returns a proof for =q=. This is very convenient for writing proofs.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
-- Hpq is a function that takes a proof for p and returns a proof for q
|
||||
axiom Hpq : p → q
|
||||
-- Hq is a proof/certificate for p
|
||||
axiom Hp : p
|
||||
-- The expression Hpq Hp is a proof/certificate for q
|
||||
check Hpq Hp
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In composite expressions, the precedences of the various binary
|
||||
connectives are in order of the above table, with =and= being the
|
||||
strongest and =iff= the weakest. For example, =a ∧ b → c ∨ d ∧ e=
|
||||
means =(a ∧ b) → (c ∨ (d ∧ e))=. All of them are right-associative.
|
||||
So, =p ∧ q ∧ r= means =p ∧ (q ∧ r)=. The actual precedence and fixity of all
|
||||
logical connectives is defined in the Lean
|
||||
[[../../library/standard/logic.lean][logic definition file]].
|
||||
Finally, =not=, =and=, =or= and =iff= are the actual names used when
|
||||
defining the Boolean connectives. They can be used as any other function.
|
||||
Lean supports _currying_ =and true= is a function from =Prop= to =Prop=.
|
||||
|
||||
** Functions
|
||||
|
||||
There are many variable-binding constructs in mathematics. Lean expresses
|
||||
all of them using just one _abstraction_, which is a converse operation to
|
||||
function application. Given a variable =x=, a type =A=, and a term =t= that
|
||||
may or may not contain =x=, one can construct the so-called _lambda abstraction_
|
||||
=fun x : A, t=, or using unicode notation =λ x : A, t=. Here is some simple
|
||||
examples.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
check fun x : nat, x + 1
|
||||
check fun x y : nat, x + 2 * y
|
||||
check fun x y : Prop, not (x ∧ y)
|
||||
check λ x : nat, x + 1
|
||||
check λ (x : nat) (p : Prop), x = 0 ∨ p
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In many cases, Lean can automatically infer the type of the variable. Actually,
|
||||
In all examples above, the type can be inferred automatically.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
check fun x, x + 1
|
||||
check fun x y, x + 2 * y
|
||||
check fun x y, not (x ∧ y)
|
||||
check λ x, x + 1
|
||||
check λ x p, x = 0 ∨ p
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
However, Lean will complain that it cannot infer the type of the
|
||||
variable =x= in =fun x, x= because any type would work in this example.
|
||||
|
||||
The following example shows how to use lambda abstractions in
|
||||
function applications
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1
|
||||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1 2
|
||||
check (fun x y, not (x ∧ y)) true false
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Lambda abstractions are also used to create proofs for propositions of the form =A → B=.
|
||||
This should be natural since we can "view" =A → B= as the type of functions that given
|
||||
a proof for =A= returns a proof for =B=.
|
||||
For example, a proof for =p → p= is just =fun H : p, H= (the identity function).
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variable p : Prop
|
||||
check fun H : p, H
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
** Definitional equality
|
||||
|
||||
The command =eval t= computes a normal form for the term =t=.
|
||||
In Lean, we say two terms are _definitionally equal_ if the have the same
|
||||
normal form. For example, the terms =(λ x : nat, x + 1) a= and =a + 1=
|
||||
are definitionally equal. The Lean type/proof checker uses the normalizer when
|
||||
checking types/proofs. So, we can prove that two definitionally equal terms
|
||||
are equal using just =refl=. Here is a simple example.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
theorem def_eq_th (a : nat) : ((λ x : nat, x + 1) a) = a + 1
|
||||
:= refl (a+1)
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
** Provable equality
|
||||
|
||||
In the previous examples, we have used =nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw=
|
||||
to show that =x = w=. In this case, =x= and =w= are not definitionally equal,
|
||||
but they are provably equal in the environment that contains =nat_trans3= and
|
||||
axioms =Hxy=, =Hzy= and =Hzw=.
|
||||
|
||||
** Proving
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean standard library contains basic theorems for creating proof terms. The
|
||||
basic theorems are useful for creating manual proofs. The are also the
|
||||
basic building blocks used by all automated proof engines available in
|
||||
Lean. The theorems can be broken into three different categories:
|
||||
introduction, elimination, and rewriting. First, we cover the introduction
|
||||
and elimination theorems for the basic Boolean connectives.
|
||||
|
||||
*** And (conjuction)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =and_intro H1 H2= creates a proof for =a ∧ b= using proofs
|
||||
=H1 : a= and =H2 : b=. We say =and_intro= is the _and-introduction_ operation.
|
||||
In the following example we use =and_intro= for creating a proof for
|
||||
=p → q → p ∧ q=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check fun (Hp : p) (Hq : q), and_intro Hp Hq
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =and_elim_left H= creates a proof =a= from a proof =H : a ∧ b=.
|
||||
Similarly =and_elim_right H= is a proof for =b=. We say they are the _left/right and-eliminators_.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → p
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_elim_left H
|
||||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → q
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_elim_right H
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Now, we prove =p ∧ q → q ∧ p= with the following simple proof term.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and_intro (and_elim_right H) (and_elim_left H)
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Note that the proof term is very similar to a function that just swaps the
|
||||
elements of a pair.
|
||||
|
||||
*** (disjuction)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =or_intro_left b H1= creates a proof for =a ∨ b= using a proof =H1 : a=.
|
||||
Similarly, =or_intro_right a H2= creates a proof for =a ∨ b= using a proof =H2 : b=.
|
||||
We say they are the _left/right or-introduction_.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
-- Proof for p → p ∨ q
|
||||
check fun H : p, or_intro_left q H
|
||||
-- Proof for q → p ∨ q
|
||||
check fun H : q, or_intro_right p H
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The or-elimination rule is slightly more complicated. The basic idea is the
|
||||
following, we can prove =c= from =a ∨ b=, by showing we can prove =c=
|
||||
by assuming =a= or by assuming =b=. It is essentially a proof by cases.
|
||||
=or_elim Hab Hac Hbc= takes three arguments =Hab : a ∨ b=, =Hac : a → c= and =Hbc : b → c= and produces a proof for =c=.
|
||||
In the following example, we use =or_elim= to prove that =p v q → q ∨ p=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check fun H : p ∨ q,
|
||||
or_elim H
|
||||
(fun Hp : p, or_intro_right q Hp)
|
||||
(fun Hq : q, or_intro_left p Hq)
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In most cases, the first argument of =or_intro_right= and
|
||||
=or_intro_left= can be inferred automatically by Lean. Moreover, Lean
|
||||
provides =or_inr= and =or_inl= as shorthands for =or_intro_right _=
|
||||
and =or_intro_left _=. These two shorthands are extensively used in
|
||||
the Lean standard library.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables p q : Prop
|
||||
check fun H : p ∨ q,
|
||||
or_elim H
|
||||
(fun Hp : p, or_inr Hp)
|
||||
(fun Hq : q, or_inl Hq)
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
*** Not (negation)
|
||||
|
||||
=not_intro H= produces a proof for =¬ a= from =H : a → false=. That is,
|
||||
we obtain =¬ a= if we can derive =false= from =a=. The expression
|
||||
=absurd_elim b Ha Hna= produces a proof for =b= from =Ha : a= and =Hna : ¬ a=.
|
||||
That is, we can deduce anything if we have =a= and =¬ a=.
|
||||
We now use =not_intro= and =absurd_elim= to produce a proof term for
|
||||
=(a → b) → ¬b → ¬a=. =absurd Ha Hna= is just =absurd_elim false Ha Hna=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables a b : Prop
|
||||
check fun (Hab : a → b) (Hnb : ¬ b),
|
||||
not_intro (fun Ha : a, absurd (Hab Ha) Hnb)
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In the standard library, =not a= is actually just an _abbreviation_
|
||||
for =a → false=. Thus, we don't really need to use =not_intro=
|
||||
explicitly. Moreover, =absurd Ha Hna= is just =Hna Ha=.
|
||||
We can suppress both of them in the previous example
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables a b : Prop
|
||||
check fun (Hab : a → b) (Hnb : ¬ b),
|
||||
(fun Ha : a, Hnb (Hab Ha))
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Now, here is the proof term for =¬a → b → (b → a) → c=
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables a b c : Prop
|
||||
check fun (Hna : ¬ a) (Hb : b) (Hba : b → a),
|
||||
absurd_elim c (Hba Hb) Hna
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
*** Iff (if-and-only-if)
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =iff_intro H1 H2= produces a proof for =a ↔ b= from =H1 : a → b= and =H2 : b → a=.
|
||||
=iff_elim_left H= produces a proof for =a → b= from =H : a ↔ b=. Similarly,
|
||||
=iff_elim_right H= produces a proof for =b → a= from =H : a ↔ b=.
|
||||
Here is the proof term for =a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a=
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables a b : Prop
|
||||
check iff_intro
|
||||
(fun H : a ∧ b, and_intro (and_elim_right H) (and_elim_left H))
|
||||
(fun H : b ∧ a, and_intro (and_elim_right H) (and_elim_left H))
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, we can use =assume= instead of =fun= to make proof terms look
|
||||
more like proofs found in text books.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
variables a b : Prop
|
||||
check iff_intro
|
||||
(assume H : a ∧ b, and_intro (and_elim_right H) (and_elim_left H))
|
||||
(assume H : b ∧ a, and_intro (and_elim_right H) (and_elim_left H))
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
*** True and False
|
||||
|
||||
The expression =trivial= is a proof term for =true=, and =false_elim a H=
|
||||
produces a proof for =a= from =H : false=.
|
||||
|
||||
*** Rewrite rules
|
||||
|
||||
*WARNING: We did not port this section to Lean 0.2 yet*
|
||||
|
||||
The Lean kernel also contains many theorems that are meant to be used as rewriting/simplification rules.
|
||||
The conclusion of these theorems is of the form =t = s= or =t ↔ s=. For example, =and_id a= is proof term for
|
||||
=a ∧ a ↔ a=. The Lean simplifier can use these theorems to automatically create proof terms for us.
|
||||
The expression =(by simp [rule-set])= is similar to =_=, but it tells Lean to synthesize the proof term using the simplifier
|
||||
using the rewrite rule set named =[rule-set]=. In the following example, we create a simple rewrite rule set
|
||||
and use it to prove a theorem that would be quite tedious to prove by hand.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
-- import module that defines several tactics/strategies including "simp"
|
||||
import tactic
|
||||
-- create a rewrite rule set with name 'simple'
|
||||
rewrite_set simple
|
||||
-- add some theorems to the rewrite rule set 'simple'
|
||||
add_rewrite and_id and_truer and_truel and_comm and_assoc and_left_comm iff_id : simple
|
||||
theorem th1 (a b : Bool) : a ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ↔ a ∧ b
|
||||
:= (by simp simple)
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, we can combine manual and automated proofs in a natural way. We can manually write the proof
|
||||
skeleton and use the =by= construct to invoke automated proof engines like the simplifier for filling the
|
||||
tedious steps. Here is a very simple example.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
theorem th2 (a b : Prop) : a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a
|
||||
:= iff_intro
|
||||
(fun H : a ∧ b, (by simp simple))
|
||||
(fun H : b ∧ a, (by simp simple))
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
** Dependent functions and quantifiers
|
||||
|
||||
Lean supports _dependent functions_. In type theory, they are also called dependent product types or Pi-types.
|
||||
The idea is quite simple, suppose we have a type =A : Type=, and a family of types =B : A → Type= which assigns to each =a : A= a type =B a=. So a dependent function is a function whose range varies depending on its arguments.
|
||||
In Lean, the dependent functions is written as =forall a : A, B a=,
|
||||
=Pi a : A, B a=, =∀ x : A, B a=, or =Π x : A, B a=. We usually use
|
||||
=forall= and =∀= for propositions, and =Pi= and =Π= for everything
|
||||
else. In the previous examples, we have seen many examples of
|
||||
dependent functions. The theorems =refl=, =trans= and =symm=, and the
|
||||
equality are all dependent functions.
|
||||
|
||||
The universal quantifier is just a dependent function.
|
||||
In Lean, if we have a family of types =B : A → Prop=,
|
||||
then =∀ x : A, B a= has type =Prop=.
|
||||
This features complicates the Lean set-theoretic model, but it
|
||||
improves usability.
|
||||
Several theorem provers have a =forall elimination= (aka
|
||||
instantiation) proof rule.
|
||||
In Lean (and other systems based on proposition as types), this rule
|
||||
is just function application.
|
||||
In the following example we add an axiom stating that =f x= is =0=
|
||||
forall =x=.
|
||||
Then we instantiate the axiom using function application.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
variable f : nat → nat
|
||||
axiom fzero : ∀ x, f x = 0
|
||||
check fzero 1
|
||||
variable a : nat
|
||||
check fzero a
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
Since we instantiate quantifiers using function application, it is
|
||||
natural to create proof terms for universal quantifiers using lambda
|
||||
abstraction. In the following example, we create a proof term showing that for all
|
||||
=x= and =y=, =f x = f y=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
variable f : nat → nat
|
||||
axiom fzero : ∀ x, f x = 0
|
||||
check λ x y, trans (fzero x) (symm (fzero y))
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
We can view the proof term above as a simple function or "recipe" for showing that
|
||||
=f x = f y= for any =x= and =y=. The function "invokes" =fzero= for creating
|
||||
proof terms for =f x = 0= and =f y = 0=. Then, it uses symmetry =symm= to create
|
||||
a proof term for =0 = f y=. Finally, transitivity is used to combine the proofs
|
||||
for =f x = 0= and =0 = f y=.
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, the existential quantifier can be written as =exists x : A, B
|
||||
x= or =∃ x : A, B x=. Actually both versions are just
|
||||
notational convenience for =Exists (fun x : A, B x)=. That is, the existential quantifier
|
||||
is actually a constant defined in the file =logic.lean=.
|
||||
This file also defines the =exists_intro= and =exists_elim=.
|
||||
To build a proof for =∃ x : A, B x=, we should provide a term =w : A= and a proof term =Hw : B w= to =exists_intro=.
|
||||
We say =w= is the witness for the existential introduction. In previous examples,
|
||||
=nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw= was a proof term for =x = w=. Then, we can create a proof term
|
||||
for =∃ a : nat, a = w= using
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
theorem nat_trans3i {a b c d : nat} (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d
|
||||
:= trans (trans H1 (symm H2)) H3
|
||||
|
||||
variables x y z w : nat
|
||||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||||
|
||||
theorem ex_a_eq_w : exists a, a = w := exists_intro x (nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw)
|
||||
check ex_a_eq_w
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
Note that =exists_intro= also has implicit arguments. For example, Lean has to infer the implicit argument
|
||||
=P : A → Bool=, a predicate (aka function to Prop). This creates complications. For example, suppose
|
||||
we have =Hg : g 0 0 = 0= and we invoke =exists_intro 0 Hg=. There are different possible values for =P=.
|
||||
Each possible value corresponds to a different theorem: =∃ x, g x x = x=, =∃ x, g x x = 0=,
|
||||
=∃ x, g x 0 = x=, etc. Lean uses the context where =exists_intro= occurs to infer the users intent.
|
||||
In the example above, we were trying to prove the theorem =∃ a, a = w=. So, we are implicitly telling
|
||||
Lean how to choose =P=. In the following example, we demonstrate this issue. We ask Lean to display
|
||||
the implicit arguments using the option =pp.implicit=. We see that each instance of =exists_intro 0 Hg=
|
||||
has different values for the implicit argument =P=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
check @exists_intro
|
||||
variable g : nat → nat → nat
|
||||
axiom Hg : g 0 0 = 0
|
||||
theorem gex1 : ∃ x, g x x = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex2 : ∃ x, g x 0 = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex3 : ∃ x, g 0 0 = x := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
theorem gex4 : ∃ x, g x x = 0 := exists_intro 0 Hg
|
||||
set_option pp.implicit true -- display implicit arguments
|
||||
check gex1
|
||||
check gex2
|
||||
check gex3
|
||||
check gex4
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
We can view =exists_intro= (aka existential introduction) as an information hiding procedure.
|
||||
We are "hiding" what is the witness for some fact. The existential elimination performs the opposite
|
||||
operation. The =exists_elim= theorem allows us to prove some proposition =B= from =∃ x : A, B x=
|
||||
if we can derive =B= using an "abstract" witness =w= and a proof term =Hw : B w=.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import logic
|
||||
check @exists_elim
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
In the following example, we define =even a= as =∃ b, a = 2*b=, and then we show that the sum
|
||||
of two even numbers is an even number.
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
|
||||
definition even (a : nat) := ∃ b, a = 2*b
|
||||
theorem EvenPlusEven {a b : nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b)
|
||||
:= exists_elim H1 (fun (w1 : nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1),
|
||||
exists_elim H2 (fun (w2 : nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2),
|
||||
exists_intro (w1 + w2)
|
||||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : {Hw1}
|
||||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : {Hw2}
|
||||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : symm (mul_add_distr_right 2 w1 w2))))
|
||||
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
||||
The example above also uses [[./calc.org][calculational proofs]] to show that =a + b = 2*(w1 + w2)=.
|
||||
The =calc= construct is just syntax sugar for creating proofs using transitivity and substitution.
|
||||
|
||||
In Lean, we can use =obtain _, from _, _= as syntax sugar for =exists_elim=.
|
||||
With this macro we can write the example above in a more natural way
|
||||
|
||||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||||
import nat
|
||||
using nat
|
||||
definition even (a : nat) := ∃ b, a = 2*b
|
||||
theorem EvenPlusEven {a b : nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b)
|
||||
:= obtain (w1 : nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1), from H1,
|
||||
obtain (w2 : nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2), from H2,
|
||||
exists_intro (w1 + w2)
|
||||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : {Hw1}
|
||||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : {Hw2}
|
||||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : symm (mul_add_distr_right 2 w1 w2))
|
||||
#+END_SRC
|
||||
|
|
@ -212,6 +212,7 @@ calc_trans eq_ne_trans
|
|||
calc_trans ne_eq_trans
|
||||
|
||||
definition iff (a b : Prop) := (a → b) ∧ (b → a)
|
||||
infix `<->`:25 := iff
|
||||
infix `↔`:25 := iff
|
||||
|
||||
theorem iff_intro {a b : Prop} (H1 : a → b) (H2 : b → a) : a ↔ b
|
||||
|
@ -286,6 +287,7 @@ theorem or_assoc (a b c : Prop) : (a ∨ b) ∨ c ↔ a ∨ (b ∨ c)
|
|||
inductive Exists {A : Type} (P : A → Prop) : Prop :=
|
||||
| exists_intro : ∀ (a : A), P a → Exists P
|
||||
|
||||
notation `exists` binders `,` r:(scoped P, Exists P) := r
|
||||
notation `∃` binders `,` r:(scoped P, Exists P) := r
|
||||
|
||||
theorem exists_elim {A : Type} {p : A → Prop} {B : Prop} (H1 : ∃x, p x) (H2 : ∀ (a : A) (H : p a), B) : B
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue