frap/LogicProgramming.v

968 lines
32 KiB
Coq
Raw Normal View History

2017-03-14 21:16:09 +00:00
(** Formal Reasoning About Programs <http://adam.chlipala.net/frap/>
* Supplementary Coq material: proof by reflection
* Author: Adam Chlipala
* License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/
* Much of the material comes from CPDT <http://adam.chlipala.net/cpdt/> by the same author. *)
Require Import Frap.
Set Implicit Arguments.
(** * Introducing Logic Programming *)
(* Recall the definition of addition from the standard library. *)
Definition real_plus := Eval compute in plus.
Print real_plus.
(* This is a recursive definition, in the style of functional programming. We
* might also follow the style of logic programming, which corresponds to the
* inductive relations we have defined in previous chapters. *)
Inductive plusR : nat -> nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| PlusO : forall m, plusR O m m
| PlusS : forall n m r, plusR n m r
-> plusR (S n) m (S r).
(* Intuitively, a fact [plusR n m r] only holds when [plus n m = r]. It is not
* hard to prove this correspondence formally. *)
Theorem plus_plusR : forall n m,
plusR n m (n + m).
Proof.
induct n; simplify.
constructor.
constructor.
apply IHn.
Qed.
(* We see here another instance of the very mechanical proof pattern that came
* up before: keep trying constructors and hypotheses. The tactic [auto] will
* automate searching through sequences of that kind, when we prime it with good
* suggestions of single proof steps to try, as with this command: *)
Hint Constructors plusR.
(* That is, every constructor of [plusR] should be considered as an atomic proof
* step, from which we enumerate step sequences. *)
Theorem plus_plusR_snazzy : forall n m,
plusR n m (n + m).
Proof.
induct n; simplify; auto.
Qed.
Theorem plusR_plus : forall n m r,
plusR n m r
-> r = n + m.
Proof.
induct 1; simplify; linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
(* With the functional definition of [plus], simple equalities about arithmetic
* follow by computation. *)
Example four_plus_three : 4 + 3 = 7.
Proof.
reflexivity.
Qed.
Print four_plus_three.
(* With the relational definition, the same equalities take more steps to prove,
* but the process is completely mechanical. For example, consider this
* simple-minded manual proof search strategy. The steps prefaced by [Fail] are
* intended to fail; they're included for explanatory value, to mimic a
* simple-minded try-everything strategy. *)
Example four_plus_three' : plusR 4 3 7.
Proof.
Fail apply PlusO.
apply PlusS.
Fail apply PlusO.
apply PlusS.
Fail apply PlusO.
apply PlusS.
Fail apply PlusO.
apply PlusS.
apply PlusO.
(* At this point the proof is completed. It is no doubt clear that a simple
* procedure could find all proofs of this kind for us. We are just exploring
* all possible proof trees, built from the two candidate steps [apply PlusO]
* and [apply PlusS]. Thus, [auto] is another great match! *)
Restart.
auto.
Qed.
Print four_plus_three'.
(* Let us try the same approach on a slightly more complex goal. *)
Example five_plus_three : plusR 5 3 8.
Proof.
auto.
(* This time, [auto] is not enough to make any progress. Since even a single
* candidate step may lead to an infinite space of possible proof trees,
* [auto] is parameterized on the maximum depth of trees to consider. The
* default depth is 5, and it turns out that we need depth 6 to prove the
* goal. *)
auto 6.
(* Sometimes it is useful to see a description of the proof tree that [auto]
* finds, with the [info_auto] variant. *)
Restart.
info_auto 6.
Qed.
(* The two key components of logic programming are _backtracking_ and
* _unification_. To see these techniques in action, consider this further
* silly example. Here our candidate proof steps will be reflexivity and
* quantifier instantiation. *)
Example seven_minus_three : exists x, x + 3 = 7.
Proof.
(* For explanatory purposes, let us simulate a user with minimal understanding
* of arithmetic. We start by choosing an instantiation for the quantifier.
* It is relevant that [ex_intro] is the proof rule for existential-quantifier
* instantiation. *)
apply ex_intro with 0.
Fail reflexivity.
(* This seems to be a dead end. Let us _backtrack_ to the point where we ran
* [apply] and make a better alternative choice. *)
Restart.
apply ex_intro with 4.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(* The above was a fairly tame example of backtracking. In general, any node in
* an under-construction proof tree may be the destination of backtracking an
* arbitrarily large number of times, as different candidate proof steps are
* found not to lead to full proof trees, within the depth bound passed to [auto].
*
* Next we demonstrate unification, which will be easier when we switch to the
* relational formulation of addition. *)
Example seven_minus_three' : exists x, plusR x 3 7.
Proof.
(* We could attempt to guess the quantifier instantiation manually as before,
* but here there is no need. Instead of [apply], we use [eapply], which
* proceeds with placeholder _unification variables_ standing in for those
* parameters we wish to postpone guessing. *)
eapply ex_intro.
(* Now we can finish the proof with the right applications of [plusR]'s
* constructors. Note that new unification variables are being generated to
* stand for new unknowns. *)
apply PlusS.
apply PlusS. apply PlusS. apply PlusS.
apply PlusO.
(* The [auto] tactic will not perform these sorts of steps that introduce
* unification variables, but the [eauto] tactic will. It is helpful to work
* with two separate tactics, because proof search in the [eauto] style can
* uncover many more potential proof trees and hence take much longer to
* run. *)
Restart.
info_eauto 6.
Qed.
(* This proof gives us our first example where logic programming simplifies
* proof search compared to functional programming. In general, functional
* programs are only meant to be run in a single direction; a function has
* disjoint sets of inputs and outputs. In the last example, we effectively ran
* a logic program backwards, deducing an input that gives rise to a certain
* output. The same works for deducing an unknown value of the other input. *)
Example seven_minus_four' : exists x, plusR 4 x 7.
Proof.
eauto 6.
Qed.
(* By proving the right auxiliary facts, we can reason about specific functional
* programs in the same way as we did above for a logic program. Let us prove
* that the constructors of [plusR] have natural interpretations as lemmas about
* [plus]. We can find the first such lemma already proved in the standard
* library, using the [SearchRewrite] command to find a library function proving
* an equality whose lefthand or righthand side matches a pattern with
* wildcards. *)
SearchRewrite (O + _).
(* The command [Hint Immediate] asks [auto] and [eauto] to consider this lemma
* as a candidate step for any leaf of a proof tree, meaning that all premises
* of the rule need to match hypotheses. *)
Hint Immediate plus_O_n.
(* The counterpart to [PlusS] we will prove ourselves. *)
Lemma plusS : forall n m r,
n + m = r
-> S n + m = S r.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
(* The command [Hint Resolve] adds a new candidate proof step, to be attempted
* at any level of a proof tree, not just at leaves. *)
Hint Resolve plusS.
(* Now that we have registered the proper hints, we can replicate our previous
* examples with the normal, functional addition [plus]. *)
Example seven_minus_three'' : exists x, x + 3 = 7.
Proof.
eauto 6.
Qed.
Example seven_minus_four : exists x, 4 + x = 7.
Proof.
eauto 6.
Qed.
(* This new hint database is far from a complete decision procedure, as we see in
* a further example that [eauto] does not finish. *)
Example seven_minus_four_zero : exists x, 4 + x + 0 = 7.
Proof.
eauto 6.
Abort.
(* A further lemma will be helpful. *)
Lemma plusO : forall n m,
n = m
-> n + 0 = m.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
Hint Resolve plusO.
(* Note that, if we consider the inputs to [plus] as the inputs of a
* corresponding logic program, the new rule [plusO] introduces an ambiguity.
* For instance, a sum [0 + 0] would match both of [plus_O_n] and [plusO],
* depending on which operand we focus on. This ambiguity may increase the
* number of potential search trees, slowing proof search, but semantically it
* presents no problems, and in fact it leads to an automated proof of the
* present example. *)
Example seven_minus_four_zero : exists x, 4 + x + 0 = 7.
Proof.
eauto 7.
Qed.
(* Just how much damage can be done by adding hints that grow the space of
* possible proof trees? A classic gotcha comes from unrestricted use of
* transitivity, as embodied in this library theorem about equality: *)
Check eq_trans.
(* Hints are scoped over sections, so let us enter a section to contain the
* effects of an unfortunate hint choice. *)
Section slow.
Hint Resolve eq_trans.
(* The following fact is false, but that does not stop [eauto] from taking a
* very long time to search for proofs of it. We use the handy [Time] command
* to measure how long a proof step takes to run. None of the following steps
* make any progress. *)
Example zero_minus_one : exists x, 1 + x = 0.
Time eauto 1.
Time eauto 2.
Time eauto 3.
Time eauto 4.
Time eauto 5.
(* We see worrying exponential growth in running time, and the [debug]
* tactical helps us see where [eauto] is wasting its time, outputting a
* trace of every proof step that is attempted. The rule [eq_trans] applies
* at every node of a proof tree, and [eauto] tries all such positions. *)
debug eauto 3.
Abort.
End slow.
(* Sometimes, though, transitivity is just what is needed to get a proof to go
* through automatically with [eauto]. For those cases, we can use named
* _hint databases_ to segregate hints into different groups that may be called
* on as needed. Here we put [eq_trans] into the database [slow]. *)
Hint Resolve eq_trans : slow.
Example from_one_to_zero : exists x, 1 + x = 0.
Proof.
Time eauto.
(* This [eauto] fails to prove the goal, but at least it takes substantially
* less than the 2 seconds required above! *)
Abort.
(* One simple example from before runs in the same amount of time, avoiding
* pollution by transitivity. *)
Example seven_minus_three_again : exists x, x + 3 = 7.
Proof.
Time eauto 6.
Qed.
(* When we _do_ need transitivity, we ask for it explicitly. *)
Example needs_trans : forall x y, 1 + x = y
-> y = 2
-> exists z, z + x = 3.
Proof.
info_eauto with slow.
Qed.
(* The [info] trace shows that [eq_trans] was used in just the position where it
* is needed to complete the proof. We also see that [auto] and [eauto] always
* perform [intro] steps without counting them toward the bound on proof-tree
* depth. *)
(** * Searching for Underconstrained Values *)
(* Recall the definition of the list length function. *)
Print Datatypes.length.
(* This function is easy to reason about in the forward direction, computing
* output from input. *)
Example length_1_2 : length (1 :: 2 :: nil) = 2.
Proof.
auto.
Qed.
Print length_1_2.
(* As in the last section, we will prove some lemmas to recast [length] in
* logic-programming style, to help us compute inputs from outputs. *)
Theorem length_O : forall A, length (nil (A := A)) = O.
Proof.
simplify; equality.
Qed.
Theorem length_S : forall A (h : A) t n,
length t = n
-> length (h :: t) = S n.
Proof.
simplify; equality.
Qed.
Hint Resolve length_O length_S.
(* Let us apply these hints to prove that a [list nat] of length 2 exists.
* (Here we register [length_O] with [Hint Resolve] instead of [Hint Immediate]
* merely as a convenience to use the same command as for [length_S]; [Resolve]
* and [Immediate] have the same meaning for a premise-free hint.) *)
Example length_is_2 : exists ls : list nat, length ls = 2.
Proof.
eauto.
(* Coq leaves for us two subgoals to prove... [nat]?! We are being asked to
* show that natural numbers exists. Why? Some unification variables of that
* type were left undetermiend, by the end of the proof. Specifically, these
* variables stand for the 2 elements of the list we find. Of course it makes
* sense that the list length follows without knowing the data values. In Coq
* 8.6, the [Unshelve] command brings these goals to the forefront, where we
* can solve each one with [exact O], but usually it is better to avoid
* getting to such a point.
*
* To debug such situations, it can be helpful to print the current internal
* representation of the proof, so we can see where the unification variables
* show up. *)
Show Proof.
Abort.
(* Paradoxically, we can make the proof search process easier by constraining
* the list further, so that proof search naturally locates appropriate data
* elements by unification. The library predicate [Forall] will be helpful. *)
Print Forall.
Example length_is_2 : exists ls : list nat, length ls = 2
/\ Forall (fun n => n >= 1) ls.
Proof.
eauto 9.
Qed.
(* We can see which list [eauto] found by printing the proof term. *)
Print length_is_2.
(* Let us try one more, fancier example. First, we use a standard higher
* order function to define a function for summing all data elements of a
* list. *)
Definition sum := fold_right plus O.
(* Another basic lemma will be helpful to guide proof search. *)
Lemma plusO' : forall n m,
n = m
-> 0 + n = m.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
Hint Resolve plusO'.
(* Finally, we meet [Hint Extern], the command to register a custom hint. That
* is, we provide a pattern to match against goals during proof search.
* Whenever the pattern matches, a tactic (given to the right of an arrow [=>])
* is attempted. Below, the number [1] gives a priority for this step. Lower
* priorities are tried before higher priorities, which can have a significant
* effect on proof search time, i.e. when we manage to give lower priorities to
* the cheaper rules. *)
Hint Extern 1 (sum _ = _) => simplify.
(* Now we can find a length-2 list whose sum is 0. *)
Example length_and_sum : exists ls : list nat, length ls = 2
/\ sum ls = O.
Proof.
eauto 7.
Qed.
Print length_and_sum.
(* Printing the proof term shows the unsurprising list that is found. Here is
* an example where it is less obvious which list will be used. Can you guess
* which list [eauto] will choose? *)
Example length_and_sum' : exists ls : list nat, length ls = 5
/\ sum ls = 42.
Proof.
eauto 15.
Qed.
Print length_and_sum'.
(* We will give away part of the answer and say that the above list is less
* interesting than we would like, because it contains too many zeroes. A
* further constraint forces a different solution for a smaller instance of the
* problem. *)
Example length_and_sum'' : exists ls : list nat, length ls = 2
/\ sum ls = 3
/\ Forall (fun n => n <> 0) ls.
Proof.
eauto 11.
Qed.
Print length_and_sum''.
(* We could continue through exercises of this kind, but even more interesting
* than finding lists automatically is finding _programs_ automatically. *)
(** * Synthesizing Programs *)
(* Here is a simple syntax type for arithmetic expressions, similar to those we
* have used several times before. In this case, we allow expressions to
* mention exactly one distinguished variable. *)
Inductive exp : Set :=
| Const (n : nat)
| Var
| Plus (e1 e2 : exp).
(* An inductive relation specifies the semantics of an expression, relating a
* variable value and an expression to the expression value. *)
Inductive eval (var : nat) : exp -> nat -> Prop :=
| EvalConst : forall n, eval var (Const n) n
| EvalVar : eval var Var var
| EvalPlus : forall e1 e2 n1 n2, eval var e1 n1
-> eval var e2 n2
-> eval var (Plus e1 e2) (n1 + n2).
Hint Constructors eval.
(* We can use [auto] to execute the semantics for specific expressions. *)
Example eval1 : forall var, eval var (Plus Var (Plus (Const 8) Var)) (var + (8 + var)).
Proof.
auto.
Qed.
(* Unfortunately, just the constructors of [eval] are not enough to prove
* theorems like the following, which depends on an arithmetic identity. *)
Example eval1' : forall var, eval var (Plus Var (Plus (Const 8) Var)) (2 * var + 8).
Proof.
eauto.
Abort.
(* To help prove [eval1'], we prove an alternative version of [EvalPlus] that
* inserts an extra equality premise. This sort of staging is helpful to get
* around limitations of [eauto]'s unification: [EvalPlus] as a direct hint will
* only match goals whose results are already expressed as additions, rather
* than as constants. With the alternative version below, to prove the first
* two premises, [eauto] is given free reign in deciding the values of [n1] and
* [n2], while the third premise can then be proved by [reflexivity], no matter
* how each of its sides is decomposed as a tree of additions. *)
Theorem EvalPlus' : forall var e1 e2 n1 n2 n, eval var e1 n1
-> eval var e2 n2
-> n1 + n2 = n
-> eval var (Plus e1 e2) n.
Proof.
simplify; subst; auto.
Qed.
Hint Resolve EvalPlus'.
(* Further, we instruct [eauto] to apply [ring], via [Hint Extern]. We should
* try this step for any equality goal. *)
Section use_ring.
Hint Extern 1 (_ = _) => ring.
(* Now we can return to [eval1'] and prove it automatically. *)
Example eval1' : forall var, eval var (Plus Var (Plus (Const 8) Var)) (2 * var + 8).
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
(* Now we are ready to take advantage of logic programming's flexibility by
* searching for a program (arithmetic expression) that always evaluates to a
* particular symbolic value. *)
Example synthesize1 : exists e, forall var, eval var e (var + 7).
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
Print synthesize1.
(* Here are two more examples showing off our program-synthesis abilities. *)
Example synthesize2 : exists e, forall var, eval var e (2 * var + 8).
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
Print synthesize2.
Example synthesize3 : exists e, forall var, eval var e (3 * var + 42).
Proof.
eauto.
Qed.
Print synthesize3.
End use_ring.
(* These examples show linear expressions over the variable [var]. Any such
* expression is equivalent to [k * var + n] for some [k] and [n]. It is
* probably not so surprising that we can prove that any expression's semantics
* is equivalent to some such linear expression, but it is tedious to prove such
* a fact manually. To finish this section, we will use [eauto] to complete the
* proof, finding [k] and [n] values automatically.
*
* We prove a series of lemmas and add them as hints. We have alternate [eval]
* constructor lemmas and some facts about arithmetic. *)
Theorem EvalConst' : forall var n m, n = m
-> eval var (Const n) m.
Proof.
simplify; subst; auto.
Qed.
Theorem EvalVar' : forall var n,
var = n
-> eval var Var n.
Proof.
simplify; subst; auto.
Qed.
Hint Resolve EvalConst' EvalVar'.
(* Next, we prove a few hints that feel a bit like cheating, as they telegraph
* the procedure for choosing values of [k] and [n]. Nonetheless, with these
* lemmas in place, we achieve an automated proof without explicitly
* orchestrating the lemmas' composition. *)
Section cheap_hints.
Theorem zero_times : forall n m r,
r = m
-> r = 0 * n + m.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
Theorem plus_0 : forall n r,
r = n
-> r = n + 0.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
Theorem times_1 : forall n, n = 1 * n.
Proof.
linear_arithmetic.
Qed.
Theorem combine : forall x k1 k2 n1 n2,
(k1 * x + n1) + (k2 * x + n2) = (k1 + k2) * x + (n1 + n2).
Proof.
simplify; ring.
Qed.
Hint Resolve zero_times plus_0 times_1 combine.
Theorem linear : forall e, exists k n,
forall var, eval var e (k * var + n).
Proof.
induct e; first_order; eauto.
Qed.
End cheap_hints.
(* Let's try that again, without using those hints that give away the answer.
* We should be able to coerce Coq into doing more of the thinking for us. *)
(* First, we will want to be able to use built-in tactic [ring_simplify] on
* goals that contain unification variables, which will be the case at
* intermediate points in our proof search. We also want a bit more
* standardization on ordering of variables within multiplications, to increase
* the odds that different calculations can unify with each other. Here is a
* tactic that realizes those wishes. *)
Ltac robust_ring_simplify :=
(* First, introduce regular names for all unification variables, because
* [ring_simplify] freaks out when it meets a unification variable. *)
repeat match goal with
| [ |- context[?v] ] => is_evar v; remember v
end;
(* Now call the standard tactic. *)
ring_simplify;
(* Replace uses of the new variables with the original unification
* variables. *)
subst;
(* Find and correct cases where commutativity doesn't agree across subterms of
* the goal. *)
repeat match goal with
| [ |- context[?X * ?Y] ] =>
match goal with
| [ |- context[?Z * X] ] => rewrite (mult_comm Z X)
end
end.
(* This tactic is pretty expensive, but let's try it eventually whenever the
* goal is an equality. *)
Hint Extern 5 (_ = _) => robust_ring_simplify.
(* The only other missing ingredient is priming Coq with some good ideas for
* instantiating existential quantifiers. These will all be tried in some
* order, in a particular proof search. *)
Hint Extern 1 (exists n : nat, _) => exists 0.
Hint Extern 1 (exists n : nat, _) => exists 1.
Hint Extern 1 (exists n : nat, _) => eexists (_ + _).
(* Note how this last hint uses [eexists] to provide an instantiation with
* wildcards inside it. Each underscore is replaced with a fresh unification
* variable. *)
(* Now Coq figures out the recipe for us, and quite quickly, at that! *)
Theorem linear_snazzy : forall e, exists k n,
forall var, eval var e (k * var + n).
Proof.
induct e; first_order; eauto.
Qed.
(* With Coq doing so much of the proof-search work for us, we might get
* complacent and consider that any successful [eauto] invocation is as good as
* any other. However, because introduced unification variables may wind up
* spread across multiple subgoals, running [eauto] can have a surprising kind
* of _side effect_ across goals! When a proof isn't solved completely by one
* [eauto] call, the cross-subgoal side effects can break proofs that used to
* work, when we introduce new premises or hints. Here's an illustrative
* example. *)
Section side_effect_sideshow.
Variable A : Set.
Variables P Q : A -> Prop.
Variable x : A.
Hypothesis Px : P x.
Hypothesis Qx : Q x.
Theorem double_threat : exists y, P y /\ Q y.
Proof.
eexists; propositional.
eauto.
eauto.
Qed.
(* That was easy enough. [eauto] could have solved the whole thing, but humor
* me by considering this slightly less automated proof. Watch what happens
* when we add a new premise. *)
Variable z : A.
Hypothesis Pz : P z.
Theorem double_threat' : exists y, P y /\ Q y.
Proof.
eexists; propositional.
eauto.
eauto.
(* Oh no! The second subgoal isn't true anymore, because the first [eauto]
* now matched [Pz] instead of [Px]. *)
Restart.
eauto.
(* [eauto] can still find the whole proof, though. *)
Qed.
End side_effect_sideshow.
(* Again, the moral of the story is: while proof search in Coq often feels
* purely functional, unification variables allow imperative side effects to
* reach across subgoals. That's a tremendously useful feature for effective
* proof automation, but it can also sneak up on you at times. *)
(** * More on [auto] Hints *)
(* Let us stop at this point and take stock of the possibilities for [auto] and
* [eauto] hints. Hints are contained within _hint databases_, which we have
* seen extended in many examples so far. When no hint database is specified, a
* default database is used. Hints in the default database are always used by
* [auto] or [eauto]. The chance to extend hint databases imperatively is
* important, because, in Ltac programming, we cannot create "global variables"
* whose values can be extended seamlessly by different modules in different
* source files. We have seen the advantages of hints so far, where a proof
* script using [auto] or [eauto] can automatically adapt to presence of new
* hints.
*
* The basic hints for [auto] and [eauto] are:
* - [Hint Immediate lemma], asking to try solving a goal immediately by
* applying a lemma and discharging any hypotheses with a single proof step
* each
* - [Hint Resolve lemma], which does the same but may add new premises that are
* themselves to be subjects of nested proof search
* - [Hint Constructors pred], which acts like [Resolve] applied to every
* constructor of an inductive predicate
* - [Hint Unfold ident], which tries unfolding [ident] when it appears at the
* head of a proof goal
* Each of these [Hint] commands may be used with a suffix, as in
* [Hint Resolve lemma : my_db], to add the hint only to the specified database,
* so that it would only be used by, for instance, [auto with my_db]. An
* additional argument to [auto] specifies the maximum depth of proof trees to
* search in depth-first order, as in [auto 8] or [auto 8 with my_db]. The
* default depth is 5.
*
* All of these [Hint] commands can be expressed with a more primitive hint
* kind, [Extern]. A few more examples of [Hint Extern] should illustrate more
* of the possibilities. *)
Theorem bool_neq : true <> false.
Proof.
auto.
(* No luck so far. *)
Abort.
(* It is hard to come up with a [bool]-specific hint that is not just a
* restatement of the theorem we mean to prove. Luckily, a simpler form
* suffices, by appealing to the [equality] tactic. *)
Hint Extern 1 (_ <> _) => equality.
Theorem bool_neq : true <> false.
Proof.
auto.
Qed.
(* A [Hint Extern] may be implemented with the full Ltac language. This example
* shows a case where a hint uses a [match]. *)
Section forall_and.
Variable A : Set.
Variables P Q : A -> Prop.
Hypothesis both : forall x, P x /\ Q x.
Theorem forall_and : forall z, P z.
Proof.
auto.
(* The [auto] invocation makes no progress beyond what [intros] would have
* accomplished. An [auto] call will not apply the hypothesis [both] to
* prove the goal, because the conclusion of [both] does not unify with the
* conclusion of the goal. However, we can teach [auto] to handle this
* kind of goal. *)
Hint Extern 1 (P ?X) =>
match goal with
| [ H : forall x, P x /\ _ |- _ ] => apply (proj1 (H X))
end.
auto.
Qed.
(* We see that an [Extern] pattern may bind unification variables that we use
* in the associated tactic. The function [proj1] is from the standard
* library, for extracting a proof of [U] from a proof of [U /\ V]. *)
End forall_and.
(* After our success on this example, we might get more ambitious and seek to
* generalize the hint to all possible predicates [P]. *)
Fail Hint Extern 1 (?P ?X) =>
match goal with
| [ H : forall x, P x /\ _ |- _ ] => apply (proj1 (H X))
end.
(* Coq's [auto] hint databases work as tables mapping _head symbols_ to lists of
* tactics to try. Because of this, the constant head of an [Extern] pattern
* must be determinable statically. In our first [Extern] hint, the head symbol
* was [not], since [x <> y] desugars to [not (x = y)]; and, in the second
* example, the head symbol was [P].
*
* Fortunately, a more basic form of [Hint Extern] also applies. We may simply
* leave out the pattern to the left of the [=>], incorporating the
* corresponding logic into the Ltac script. *)
Hint Extern 1 =>
match goal with
| [ H : forall x, ?P x /\ _ |- ?P ?X ] => apply (proj1 (H X))
end.
(* Be forewarned that a [Hint Extern] of this kind will be applied at _every_
* node of a proof tree, so an expensive Ltac script may slow proof search
* significantly. *)
(** * Rewrite Hints *)
(* Another dimension of extensibility with hints is rewriting with quantified
* equalities. We have used the associated command %[Hint Rewrite] in several
* examples so far. The [simplify] tactic uses these hints by calling the
* built-in tactic [autorewrite]. Our rewrite hints have taken the form
* [Hint Rewrite lemma], which by default adds them to the default hint database
* [core]; but alternate hint databases may also be specified just as with,
* e.g., [Hint Resolve].
*
* The next example shows a direct use of [autorewrite]. Note that, while
* [Hint Rewrite] uses a default database, [autorewrite] requires that a
* database be named. *)
Section autorewrite.
Variable A : Set.
Variable f : A -> A.
Hypothesis f_f : forall x, f (f x) = f x.
Hint Rewrite f_f.
Lemma f_f_f : forall x, f (f (f x)) = f x.
Proof.
intros; autorewrite with core; reflexivity.
Qed.
(* There are a few ways in which [autorewrite] can lead to trouble when
* insufficient care is taken in choosing hints. First, the set of hints may
* define a nonterminating rewrite system, in which case invocations to
* [autorewrite] may not terminate. Second, we may add hints that "lead
* [autorewrite] down the wrong path." For instance: *)
Section garden_path.
Variable g : A -> A.
Hypothesis f_g : forall x, f x = g x.
Hint Rewrite f_g.
Lemma f_f_f' : forall x, f (f (f x)) = f x.
intros; autorewrite with core.
Abort.
(* Our new hint was used to rewrite the goal into a form where the old hint
* could no longer be applied. This "non-monotonicity" of rewrite hints
* contrasts with the situation for [auto], where new hints may slow down
* proof search but can never "break" old proofs. The key difference is
* that [auto] either solves a goal or makes no changes to it, while
* [autorewrite] may change goals without solving them. The situation for
* [eauto] is slightly more complicated, as changes to hint databases may
* change the proof found for a particular goal, and that proof may
* influence the settings of unification variables that appear elsewhere in
* the proof state. *)
Reset garden_path.
(* The [autorewrite] tactic also works with quantified equalities that include
* additional premises, but we must be careful to avoid similar incorrect
* rewritings. *)
Section garden_path.
Variable P : A -> Prop.
Variable g : A -> A.
Hypothesis f_g : forall x, P x -> f x = g x.
Hint Rewrite f_g.
Lemma f_f_f' : forall x, f (f (f x)) = f x.
intros; autorewrite with core.
Abort.
(* The inappropriate rule fired the same three times as before, even though
* we know we will not be able to prove the premises. *)
Reset garden_path.
(* Our final, successful attempt uses an extra argument to [Hint Rewrite] that
* specifies a tactic to apply to generated premises. Such a hint is only
* used when the tactic succeeds for all premises, possibly leaving further
* subgoals for some premises. *)
Section garden_path.
Variable P : A -> Prop.
Variable g : A -> A.
Hypothesis f_g : forall x, P x -> f x = g x.
Hint Rewrite f_g using assumption.
Lemma f_f_f' : forall x, f (f (f x)) = f x.
Proof.
intros; autorewrite with core; reflexivity.
Qed.
(* We may still use [autorewrite] to apply [f_g] when the generated premise
* is among our assumptions. *)
Lemma f_f_f_g : forall x, P x -> f (f x) = g x.
Proof.
intros; autorewrite with core; reflexivity.
Qed.
End garden_path.
(* It can also be useful to apply the [autorewrite with db in *] form, which
* does rewriting in hypotheses, as well as in the conclusion. *)
Lemma in_star : forall x y, f (f (f (f x))) = f (f y)
-> f x = f (f (f y)).
Proof.
intros; autorewrite with core in *; assumption.
Qed.
End autorewrite.
(* Many proofs can be automated in pleasantly modular ways with deft
* combinations of [auto] and [autorewrite]. *)