mirror of
https://github.com/achlipala/frap.git
synced 2024-12-01 00:26:18 +00:00
Start of AbstractInterpretation book chapter
This commit is contained in:
parent
70974db013
commit
21999625ea
1 changed files with 124 additions and 0 deletions
124
frap_book.tex
124
frap_book.tex
|
@ -1696,6 +1696,130 @@ As we study new kinds of programming languages, we will see how to model them op
|
|||
Almost every new proof technique is phrased as an approach to establishing invariants of transition systems based on small-step semantics.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
|
||||
|
||||
\chapter{Abstract Interpretation and Dataflow Analysis}
|
||||
|
||||
The last two chapters showed us both how to build a transition system from a program automatically and how to find an invariant for a transition system automatically.
|
||||
Let's now combine these ideas to find invariants for programs automatically, in a particular way associated with the technique of \emph{dataflow analysis}\index{dataflow analysis} used to drive many compiler optimizations.
|
||||
Throughout, we'll stick with the example of the small imperative language whose semantics we studied in the last chapter.
|
||||
We'll confine our attention to its basic small-step semantics via the $\to$ relation.
|
||||
|
||||
Model checking builds up increasingly larger finite sets of reachable states in a system.
|
||||
A state $(v, c)$ of our imperative language combines \emph{control state}\index{control state} $c$ (the next command to execute) with \emph{data state} $v$ (the values of the variables), and so model checking will find invariants that restrict both components.
|
||||
We say that model checking is \emph{path-sensitive}\index{path-sensitive analysis} because its invariants can distinguish between the different data states that can be associated with the same control state, reached along different paths in the program's executions.
|
||||
Path-sensitive analyses tend to be much more computationally expensive than \emph{path-insensitive}\index{path-insensitive analysis} analyses, whose invariants collapse together all ways of reaching the same control state.
|
||||
Dataflow analysis is one such path-insensitive approach, and its underlying theory is \emph{abstract interpretation}\index{abstract interpretation}.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
\section{Definition of an Abstract Interpretation}
|
||||
|
||||
An abstract interpretation is a particular sort of abstraction, of the kind we met in studying model checking.
|
||||
In that more general setting, we can represent concrete states with any sorts of abstract states.
|
||||
In abstract interpretation, we most commonly associate each variable with an independent abstract description.
|
||||
One example, which we'll formalize in more detail shortly, would be to label each variable as ``even,'' ``odd,'' or ``either.''
|
||||
|
||||
\newcommand{\join}[0]{\sqcup}
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{definition}
|
||||
An \emph{abstract interpretation} (for our example imperative language) is a tuple $\angled{\mathbb D, \top, \mathcal C, \hat{+}, \hat{-}, \hat{\times}, \join, \mathcal R}$, where $\mathbb D$ is a set (the domain of the analysis); $\top \in \mathbb D$; $\mathcal C : \mathbb N \to \mathbb D$; $\hat{+}, \hat{-}, \hat{\times}, \join : \mathbb D \times \mathbb D \to \mathbb D$; and $\mathcal R \subseteq \mathbb N \times \mathbb D$.
|
||||
The idea is that:
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item Abstract versions of numbers are $\mathbb D$ values.
|
||||
\item $\top$ (``top'')\index{top element of an abstract interpretation} is the least specific abstract value, representing any concrete value.
|
||||
\item $\mathcal C$ maps any constant to its most precise abstraction.
|
||||
\item $\hat{+}$, $\hat{-}$, and $\hat{\times}$ push abstraction through arithmetic operators, calculating their most precise abstractions.
|
||||
\item $\join$ (``join'')\index{join operation of an abstract interpretation} computes the \emph{least upper bound}\index{least upper bound} of two abstract values: the most specific value that represents any value associated with either input.
|
||||
\item $\mathcal R$ formalizes the idea of which concrete values are covered by which abstract values.
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
|
||||
For $a, b \in \mathbb D$, define $a \sqsubseteq b$ to mean $\forall n \in \mathbb N. \; (n \; \mathcal R \; a) \Rightarrow (n \; \mathcal R \; b)$. That is, $b$ is at least as general as $a$.
|
||||
An abstract interpretation must satsify the following algebraic laws:
|
||||
\begin{itemize}
|
||||
\item $\forall a \in \mathbb D. \; a \sqsubseteq \top$
|
||||
\item $\forall n \in \mathbb N. \; n \; \mathcal R \; \mathcal C(n)$
|
||||
\item $\forall n, m \in \mathbb N. \; \forall a, b \in \mathbb D. \; n \; \mathcal R \; a \land m \; \mathcal R \; b \Rightarrow (n + m) \; \mathcal R \; (a \hat{+} b)$
|
||||
\item $\forall n, m \in \mathbb N. \; \forall a, b \in \mathbb D. \; n \; \mathcal R \; a \land m \; \mathcal R \; b \Rightarrow (n - m) \; \mathcal R \; (a \hat{-} b)$
|
||||
\item $\forall n, m \in \mathbb N. \; \forall a, b \in \mathbb D. \; n \; \mathcal R \; a \land m \; \mathcal R \; b \Rightarrow (n \times m) \; \mathcal R \; (a \hat{\times} b)$
|
||||
\item $\forall a, b, a', b' \in \mathbb D. \; a \sqsubseteq a' \land b \sqsubseteq b' \Rightarrow (a \hat{+} b) \sqsubseteq (a' \hat{+} b')$
|
||||
\item $\forall a, b, a', b' \in \mathbb D. \; a \sqsubseteq a' \land b \sqsubseteq b' \Rightarrow (a \hat{-} b) \sqsubseteq (a' \hat{-} b')$
|
||||
\item $\forall a, b, a', b' \in \mathbb D. \; a \sqsubseteq a' \land b \sqsubseteq b' \Rightarrow (a \hat{\times} b) \sqsubseteq (a' \hat{\times} b')$
|
||||
\item $\forall a, b \in \mathbb D. \; a \sqsubseteq (a \join b)$
|
||||
\item $\forall a, b \in \mathbb D. \; b \sqsubseteq (a \join b)$
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
\end{definition}
|
||||
|
||||
As an example, consider this formalization of even-odd analysis, whose proof of soundness is left as an exercise to the reader.
|
||||
|
||||
\newcommand{\E}[0]{\mathsf{E}}
|
||||
\renewcommand{\O}[0]{\mathsf{O}}
|
||||
\begin{eqnarray*}
|
||||
\mathbb D &=& \{\E, \O, \top\} \\
|
||||
\mathcal C(n) &=& \textrm{$\E$ or $\O$, depending on parity of $n$} \\
|
||||
\E \; \hat{+} \; \E &=& \E \\
|
||||
\E \; \hat{+} \; \O &=& \O \\
|
||||
\O \; \hat{+} \; \E &=& \O \\
|
||||
\O \; \hat{+} \; \O &=& \E \\
|
||||
\_ \; \hat{+} \; \_ &=& \top \\
|
||||
\E \; \hat{-} \; \E &=& \E \\
|
||||
\_ \; \hat{-} \; \_ &=& \top \\
|
||||
\E \; \hat{\times} \; \_ &=& \E \\
|
||||
\_ \; \hat{\times} \; \E &=& \E \\
|
||||
\O \; \hat{\times} \; \O &=& \O \\
|
||||
\top \; \hat{\times} \; \top &=& \top \\
|
||||
\E \join \E &=& \E \\
|
||||
\O \join \O &=& \O \\
|
||||
\_ \join \_ &=& \top \\
|
||||
n \; \mathcal R \; \E &=& \textrm{$n$ is even} \\
|
||||
n \; \mathcal R \; \O &=& \textrm{$n$ is odd} \\
|
||||
n \; \mathcal R \; \top &=& \textrm{always}
|
||||
\end{eqnarray*}
|
||||
|
||||
We generally think of an abstract interpretation as forming a \emph{lattice}\index{lattice}, which is roughly the algebraic structure characterized by operations like $\join$, when $\join$ truly returns the \emph{most specific} or \emph{least} upper bound of its two arguments. We visualize the even-odd lattice like so.
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{center}\begin{tikzpicture}[node distance=1.5cm]
|
||||
\node(top) {$\top$};
|
||||
\node(E) [below left of=top] {$\E$};
|
||||
\node(O) [below right of=top] {$\O$};
|
||||
|
||||
\draw(top) -- (E);
|
||||
\draw(top) -- (O);
|
||||
\end{tikzpicture}\end{center}
|
||||
|
||||
The idea is that taking the join of two elements moves us \emph{up} the lattice to their lowest common ancestor.
|
||||
|
||||
An edge going up from $a$ to $b$ indicates that $a \sqsubseteq b$.
|
||||
As another example, consider a lattice tracking prime factors of numbers, up to 5.
|
||||
Then the picture version might go like so:
|
||||
|
||||
\begin{center}\begin{tikzpicture}[node distance=1.5cm]
|
||||
\node(top) {$\{2, 3, 5\}$};
|
||||
\node(twothree) [below left of=top] {$\{2, 3\}$};
|
||||
\node(twofive) [below of=top] {$\{2, 5\}$};
|
||||
\node(threefive) [below right of=top] {$\{3, 5\}$};
|
||||
\node(two) [below of=twothree] {$\{2\}$};
|
||||
\node(three) [below of=twofive] {$\{3\}$};
|
||||
\node(five) [below of=threefive] {$\{5\}$};
|
||||
\node(emp) [below of=three] {$\{\}$};
|
||||
|
||||
\draw(top) -- (twothree);
|
||||
\draw(top) -- (twofive);
|
||||
\draw(top) -- (threefive);
|
||||
\draw(twothree) -- (two);
|
||||
\draw(twothree) -- (three);
|
||||
\draw(twofive) -- (two);
|
||||
\draw(twofive) -- (five);
|
||||
\draw(threefive) -- (three);
|
||||
\draw(threefive) -- (five);
|
||||
\draw(two) -- (emp);
|
||||
\draw(three) -- (emp);
|
||||
\draw(five) -- (emp);
|
||||
\end{tikzpicture}\end{center}
|
||||
|
||||
Since $\sqsubseteq$ is clearly transitive, upward-moving paths across multiple nodes also imply $\sqsubseteq$ relationships between their endpoints.
|
||||
It's worth verifying quickly that any two nodes in this graph have a unique lowest common ancestor, which is the proper result of the $\join$ operation on those nodes.
|
||||
|
||||
|
||||
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
|
||||
|
||||
\appendix
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue