mirror of
https://github.com/achlipala/frap.git
synced 2024-11-28 07:16:20 +00:00
Proofreading pass through Chapter 2
This commit is contained in:
parent
f39f2ab0d3
commit
48c8906d10
1 changed files with 21 additions and 13 deletions
34
frap.tex
34
frap.tex
|
@ -118,6 +118,8 @@ When we encounter a new challenge, to prove a new kind of property about a new k
|
|||
We can even alternate between strategies, breaking a system into parts, abstracting one as a simpler part, further decomposing that part into pieces, and so on.
|
||||
\end{itemize}
|
||||
|
||||
\newcommand{\encoding}[0]{\marginpar{\fbox{\textbf{Encoding}}}}
|
||||
|
||||
In the course of the book, we will never quite define any of these meta-techniques in complete formality.
|
||||
Instead, we'll meet many examples of each, called out by eye-catching margin notes.
|
||||
Generalizing from the examples should help the reader start developing an intuition for when to use each element and for the common design patterns that apply.
|
||||
|
@ -166,6 +168,7 @@ $$\begin{array}{l}
|
|||
Rather than appeal to our intuition about grade-school arithmetic, we prefer to formalize concrete syntax with a \emph{grammar}\index{grammar}, following a style known as \emph{Backus-Naur Form (BNF)}\index{Backus-Naur Form}\index{BNF}.
|
||||
We have a set of \emph{nonterminals}\index{nonterminal} (e.g., $e$ below), standing for sets of allowable strings.
|
||||
Some are defined by appeal to existing sets, as below, when we define constants $n$ in terms of the well-known set $\mathbb N$\index{N@$\mathbb N$} of natural numbers\index{natural numbers} (nonnegative integers).
|
||||
\encoding
|
||||
$$\begin{array}{rrcl}
|
||||
\textrm{Constants} & n &\in& \mathbb N \\
|
||||
\textrm{Variables} & x &\in& \mathsf{Strings} \\
|
||||
|
@ -185,6 +188,7 @@ A more general notation for inductive definitions provides a series of \emph{inf
|
|||
Formally, the set is defined to be \emph{the smallest one that satisfies all the rules}.
|
||||
Each rule has \emph{premises}\index{premise} and a \emph{conclusion}\index{conclusion}.
|
||||
We illustrate with four rules that together are equivalent to the BNF grammar above, for defining a set $\mathsf{Exp}$ of expressions.
|
||||
\encoding
|
||||
$$\infer{n \in \mathsf{Exp}}{
|
||||
n \in \mathbb N
|
||||
}
|
||||
|
@ -211,6 +215,7 @@ After that brief interlude with concrete syntax, we now drop all formal treatmen
|
|||
Instead, we concern ourselves with \emph{abstract syntax}\index{abstract syntax}, the real heart of language definitions.
|
||||
Now programs are \emph{abstract syntax trees}\index{abstract syntax tree} (\emph{ASTs}\index{AST}), corresponding to inductive type definitions in Coq or algebraic datatype\index{algebraic datatype} definitions in Haskell\index{Haskell}.
|
||||
Such types can be defined by enumerating their \emph{constructor}\index{constructor} functions with types.
|
||||
\encoding
|
||||
\begin{eqnarray*}
|
||||
\mathsf{Const} &:& \mathbb{N} \to \mathsf{Exp} \\
|
||||
\mathsf{Var} &:& \mathsf{Strings} \to \mathsf{Exp} \\
|
||||
|
@ -220,6 +225,7 @@ Such types can be defined by enumerating their \emph{constructor}\index{construc
|
|||
|
||||
Such a list of constructors defines the set $\mathsf{Exp}$ to contain exactly those terms that can be built up with the constructors.
|
||||
In inference-rule notation:
|
||||
\encoding
|
||||
$$\infer{\mathsf{Const}(n) \in \mathsf{Exp}}{
|
||||
n \in \mathbb N
|
||||
}
|
||||
|
@ -245,8 +251,8 @@ Here is one in the clausal\index{clausal function definition} style of Haskell\i
|
|||
\begin{eqnarray*}
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Const}(n)) &=& 1 \\
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Var}(x)) &=& 1 \\
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Plus}(e_1, e_2)) &=& \mathsf{size}(e_1) + \mathsf{size}(e_2) \\
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Times}(e_1, e_2)) &=& \mathsf{size}(e_1) + \mathsf{size}(e_2)
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Plus}(e_1, e_2)) &=& 1 + \mathsf{size}(e_1) + \mathsf{size}(e_2) \\
|
||||
\mathsf{size}(\mathsf{Times}(e_1, e_2)) &=& 1 + \mathsf{size}(e_1) + \mathsf{size}(e_2)
|
||||
\end{eqnarray*}
|
||||
|
||||
It is important that we include \emph{one clause per constructor of the inductive type}.
|
||||
|
@ -334,7 +340,7 @@ For that reason, we stick to machine-checked proofs here, using the book chapter
|
|||
We do, however, need to get all the proof details filled in somehow.
|
||||
One of the most convenient cases is when a proof goal fits into some \emph{decidable theory}\index{decidable theory}.
|
||||
We follow the sense from computability theory\index{computability theory}, where we consider some \emph{decision problem}\index{decision problem}, as a (usually infinite) set $F$ of formulas and some subset $T \subseteq F$ of \emph{true} formulas, possibly considering only those provable using some limited set of inference rules.
|
||||
The decision problem is \emph{decidable} if and only if there exists some always terminating program that, when passed some $f \in F$ as input, returns ``true'' if and only if $f \in T$.
|
||||
The decision problem is \emph{decidable} if and only if there exists some always-terminating program that, when passed some $f \in F$ as input, returns ``true'' if and only if $f \in T$.
|
||||
Decidability of theories is handy because, whenever our goal belongs to the $F$ set of a decidable theory, we can discharge the goal automatically by running the deciding program that must exist.
|
||||
|
||||
One common decidable theory is \emph{linear arithmetic}\index{linear arithmetic}, whose $F$ set is generated by the following grammar as $\phi$.
|
||||
|
@ -348,9 +354,9 @@ $$\begin{array}{rrcl}
|
|||
The arithmetic terms used here are \emph{linear} in the same sense as \emph{linear algebra}\index{linear algebra}: we never multiply together two terms containing variables.
|
||||
Actually, multiplication is prohibited outright, but we allow multiplication by a constant as an abbreviation (logically speaking) for repeated addition.
|
||||
Propositions are formed out of equality and less-than tests on terms, and we also have the Boolean negation (``not'') operator $\neg$ and conjunction (``and'') operator $\land$.
|
||||
This set of propositional operators is enough to encode the other usual inequality and propositional operators, so we allow them, too, as convenient shorthands.
|
||||
This set of propositional\index{propositional logic} operators is enough to encode the other usual inequality and propositional operators, so we allow them, too, as convenient shorthands.
|
||||
|
||||
Applying decidable theories in a proof assistant like Coq, it is important to understand how a theory may apply to formulas that don't actually satisfy its grammar literally.
|
||||
Using decidable theories in a proof assistant like Coq, it is important to understand how a theory may apply to formulas that don't actually satisfy its grammar literally.
|
||||
For instance, we may want to prove $f(x) - f(x) = 0$, for some fancy function $f$ well outside the grammar above.
|
||||
However, we only need to introduce a new variable $y$, defined with the equation $y = f(x)$, to arrive at a new goal $y - y = 0$.
|
||||
A linear-arithmetic procedure makes short work of this goal, and we may then derive the original goal by substituting back in for $y$.
|
||||
|
@ -376,14 +382,16 @@ $$\infer[\mathsf{Reflexivity}]{e = e}{}
|
|||
e_1 = e_3
|
||||
& e_3 = e_2
|
||||
}$$
|
||||
$$\infer[\mathsf{Congruence}]{f_1(e_1) = f_2(e_2)}{
|
||||
f_1 = f_2
|
||||
& e_1 = e_2
|
||||
$$\infer[\mathsf{Congruence}]{f(e_1, \ldots, e_n) = f'(e'_1, \ldots, e'_n)}{
|
||||
f = f'
|
||||
& e_1 = e'_1
|
||||
& \ldots
|
||||
& e_n = e'_n
|
||||
}$$
|
||||
|
||||
\medskip
|
||||
|
||||
As one more example of a decidable theory, consider the algebraic structure of \emph{semirings}\index{semirings}, which may profitably be remembered as ``things that act like natural numbers.''
|
||||
As one more example of a decidable theory, consider the algebraic structure of \emph{semirings}\index{semirings}, which may profitably be remembered as ``types that act like natural numbers.''
|
||||
A semiring is any set containing two elements notated 0 and 1, closed under two binary operators notated $+$ and $\times$.
|
||||
The notations are suggestive, but in fact we have free reign in choosing the set, elements, and operators, so long as the following axioms\footnote{The equations are taken almost literally from \url{https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Semiring}.} are satisfied:
|
||||
\begin{eqnarray*}
|
||||
|
@ -400,10 +408,9 @@ The notations are suggestive, but in fact we have free reign in choosing the set
|
|||
a \times 0 &=& 0
|
||||
\end{eqnarray*}
|
||||
|
||||
The formal theory is then as follows.
|
||||
The formal theory is then as follows, where we consider as ``true'' only those equalities that follow from the axioms.
|
||||
$$\begin{array}{rrcl}
|
||||
\textrm{Variables} & x &\in& \mathsf{Strings} \\
|
||||
\textrm{Functions} & f &\in& \mathsf{Strings} \\
|
||||
\textrm{Terms} & e &::=& x \mid e + e \mid e \times e \\
|
||||
\textrm{Propositions} & \phi &::=& e = e
|
||||
\end{array}$$
|
||||
|
@ -414,7 +421,7 @@ For instance, by the semiring theory, we can prove $x \times y = y \times x$, wh
|
|||
|
||||
\section{Simplification and Rewriting}
|
||||
|
||||
While we leave most proof details to the accompanying Coq code, it does seem important to introduce two important principles that are often implicit in proofs on paper.
|
||||
While we leave most proof details to the accompanying Coq code, it does seem important to introduce two key principles that are often implicit in proofs on paper.
|
||||
|
||||
The first is \emph{algebraic simplification}\index{algebraic simplification}, where we apply the defining equations of a recursive definition to simplify a goal.
|
||||
For example, recall that our definition of expression size included this clause.
|
||||
|
@ -424,7 +431,7 @@ For example, recall that our definition of expression size included this clause.
|
|||
Now imagine that we are trying to prove this formula.
|
||||
$$\size{\mathsf{Plus}(e, \mathsf{Const}(7))} = 8 + \size{e}$$
|
||||
We may apply the defining equation to rewrite into a different formula, where we have essential pushed the definition of $\size{\cdot}$ through the $\mathsf{Plus}$.
|
||||
$$1 + \size{e} + \size{\mathsf{Const}(7)} = 7 + \size{e}$$
|
||||
$$1 + \size{e} + \size{\mathsf{Const}(7)} = 8 + \size{e}$$
|
||||
Another application of a different defining equation, this time for $\mathsf{Const}$, takes us to here.
|
||||
$$1 + \size{e} + 7 = 8 + \size{e}$$
|
||||
From here, the goal follows by linear arithmetic.
|
||||
|
@ -443,6 +450,7 @@ Here, unification found the assignment $e = \mathsf{Var}(x)$.
|
|||
|
||||
\medskip
|
||||
|
||||
\encoding
|
||||
We close the chapter with an important note on terminology.
|
||||
A formula like $P(\size{\mathsf{Plus}(\mathsf{Var}(x), \mathsf{Const}(7))})$ combines several levels of notation.
|
||||
We consider that we are doing our mathematical reasoning in some \emph{metalanguage}\index{metalanguage}, which is often applicable to a wide variety of proof tasks.
|
||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue