mirror of
https://github.com/achlipala/frap.git
synced 2024-12-01 00:26:18 +00:00
1039 lines
26 KiB
Coq
1039 lines
26 KiB
Coq
(** Formal Reasoning About Programs <http://adam.chlipala.net/frap/>
|
|
* Chapter 8: Lambda Calculus and Simple Type Soundness
|
|
* Author: Adam Chlipala
|
|
* License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ *)
|
|
|
|
Require Import Frap.
|
|
|
|
(* The last few chapters have focused on small programming languages that are
|
|
* representative of the essence of the imperative languages. We now turn to
|
|
* lambda-calculus, the usual representative of functional languages. *)
|
|
|
|
Module Ulc.
|
|
(* Programs are expressions, which we evaluate algebraically, rather than
|
|
* executing for side effects. *)
|
|
Inductive exp : Set :=
|
|
| Var (x : var)
|
|
| Abs (x : var) (body : exp)
|
|
(* A function that binds its argument to the given variable, evaluating the
|
|
* body expression *)
|
|
| App (e1 e2 : exp).
|
|
(* Applying a function to an argument *)
|
|
|
|
(* Key operation: within [e], changing every occurrence of variable [x] into
|
|
* [rep]. IMPORTANT: we will only apply this operation in contexts where
|
|
* [rep] is *closed*, meaning every [Var] refers to some enclosing [Abs], so
|
|
* as to avoid *variable capture*. See the book proper for a little more
|
|
* discussion. *)
|
|
Fixpoint subst (rep : exp) (x : var) (e : exp) : exp :=
|
|
match e with
|
|
| Var y => if string_dec y x then rep else Var y
|
|
| Abs y e1 => Abs y (if y ==v x then e1 else subst rep x e1)
|
|
| App e1 e2 => App (subst rep x e1) (subst rep x e2)
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Big-step semantics *)
|
|
|
|
(* This is the most straightforward way to give semantics to lambda terms:
|
|
* We evaluate any closed term into a value (that is, an [Abs]). *)
|
|
Inductive eval : exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| BigAbs : forall x e,
|
|
eval (Abs x e) (Abs x e)
|
|
| BigApp : forall e1 x e1' e2 v2 v,
|
|
eval e1 (Abs x e1')
|
|
-> eval e2 v2
|
|
-> eval (subst v2 x e1') v
|
|
-> eval (App e1 e2) v.
|
|
|
|
(* Note that we omit a [Var] case, since variable terms can't be *closed*,
|
|
* and therefore they aren't meaningful as top-level programs. *)
|
|
|
|
(** Which terms are values, that is, final results of execution? *)
|
|
Inductive value : exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| Value : forall x e, value (Abs x e).
|
|
(** We're cheating a bit here, *assuming* that the term is also closed. *)
|
|
|
|
Hint Constructors eval value.
|
|
|
|
(* Every value executes to itself. *)
|
|
Theorem value_eval : forall v,
|
|
value v
|
|
-> eval v v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve value_eval.
|
|
|
|
(** Conversely, let's prove that [eval] only produces values. *)
|
|
Theorem eval_value : forall e v,
|
|
eval e v
|
|
-> value v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve eval_value.
|
|
|
|
(* Some notations, to let us write more normal-looking lambda terms *)
|
|
Coercion Var : var >-> exp.
|
|
Notation "\ x , e" := (Abs x e) (at level 50).
|
|
Infix "@" := App (at level 49, left associativity).
|
|
|
|
(* Believe it or not, this is a Turing-complete language! Here's an example
|
|
* nonterminating program. *)
|
|
Example omega := (\"x", "x" @ "x") @ (\"x", "x" @ "x").
|
|
|
|
Theorem omega_no_eval : forall v, eval omega v -> False.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1.
|
|
|
|
invert H.
|
|
invert H0.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
apply IHeval3.
|
|
trivial.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Church Numerals, everyone's favorite example of lambda terms in
|
|
* action *)
|
|
|
|
(* Here are two curious definitions. *)
|
|
Definition zero := \"f", \"x", "x".
|
|
Definition plus1 := \"n", \"f", \"x", "f" @ ("n" @ "f" @ "x").
|
|
|
|
(* We can build up any natural number [n] as [plus1^n @ zero]. Let's prove
|
|
* that, in fact, these definitions constitute a workable embedding of the
|
|
* natural numbers in lambda-calculus. *)
|
|
|
|
(* A term [plus^n @ zero] evaluates to something very close to what this
|
|
* function returns. *)
|
|
Fixpoint canonical' (n : nat) : exp :=
|
|
match n with
|
|
| O => "x"
|
|
| S n' => "f" @ ((\"f", \"x", canonical' n') @ "f" @ "x")
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
(* This missing piece is this wrapper. *)
|
|
Definition canonical n := \"f", \"x", canonical' n.
|
|
|
|
(* Let's formalize our definition of what it means to represent a number. *)
|
|
Definition represents (e : exp) (n : nat) :=
|
|
eval e (canonical n).
|
|
|
|
(* Zero passes the test. *)
|
|
Theorem zero_ok : represents zero 0.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
unfold zero, represents, canonical.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* So does our successor operation. *)
|
|
Theorem plus1_ok : forall e n, represents e n
|
|
-> represents (plus1 @ e) (S n).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
unfold plus1, represents, canonical; simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* What's basically going on here? The representation of number [n] is [N]
|
|
* such that, for any function [f]:
|
|
* N(f) = f^n
|
|
* That is, we represent a number as its repeated-composition operator.
|
|
* So, given a number, we can use it to repeat any operation. In particular,
|
|
* to implement addition, we can just repeat [plus1]! *)
|
|
Definition add := \"n", \"m", "n" @ plus1 @ "m".
|
|
|
|
(* Our addition works properly on this test case. *)
|
|
Example add_1_2 : exists v,
|
|
eval (add @ (plus1 @ zero) @ (plus1 @ (plus1 @ zero))) v
|
|
/\ eval (plus1 @ (plus1 @ (plus1 @ zero))) v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
eexists; propositional.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
repeat econstructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* By the way: since [canonical'] doesn't mention variable "m", substituting
|
|
* for "m" has no effect. This fact will come in handy shortly. *)
|
|
Lemma subst_m_canonical' : forall m n,
|
|
subst m "m" (canonical' n) = canonical' n.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct n; simplify; equality.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* This inductive proof is the workhorse for the next result, so let's skip
|
|
* ahead there. *)
|
|
Lemma add_ok' : forall m n,
|
|
eval
|
|
(subst (\ "f", (\ "x", canonical' m)) "x"
|
|
(subst (\ "n", (\ "f", (\ "x", "f" @ (("n" @ "f") @ "x")))) "f"
|
|
(canonical' n))) (canonical (n + m)).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct n; simplify.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* [add] properly encodes the usual addition. *)
|
|
Theorem add_ok : forall n ne m me,
|
|
represents ne n
|
|
-> represents me m
|
|
-> represents (add @ ne @ me) (n + m).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
unfold represents; simplify.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
rewrite subst_m_canonical'.
|
|
apply add_ok'.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* Let's repeat the same exercise for multiplication. *)
|
|
|
|
Definition mult := \"n", \"m", "n" @ (add @ "m") @ zero.
|
|
|
|
Example mult_1_2 : exists v,
|
|
eval (mult @ (plus1 @ zero) @ (plus1 @ (plus1 @ zero))) v
|
|
/\ eval (plus1 @ (plus1 @ zero)) v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
eexists; propositional.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
repeat econstructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Lemma mult_ok' : forall m n,
|
|
eval
|
|
(subst (\ "f", (\ "x", "x")) "x"
|
|
(subst
|
|
(\ "m",
|
|
((\ "f", (\ "x", canonical' m)) @
|
|
(\ "n", (\ "f", (\ "x", "f" @ (("n" @ "f") @ "x"))))) @ "m")
|
|
"f" (canonical' n))) (canonical (n * m)).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct n; simplify.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
rewrite subst_m_canonical'.
|
|
apply add_ok'. (* Note the recursive appeal to correctness of [add]. *)
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Theorem mult_ok : forall n ne m me,
|
|
represents ne n
|
|
-> represents me m
|
|
-> represents (mult @ ne @ me) (n * m).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
unfold represents; simplify.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
rewrite subst_m_canonical'.
|
|
apply mult_ok'.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Small-step semantics with evaluation contexts *)
|
|
|
|
(* We can also port to this setting our small-step semantics style based on
|
|
* evaluation contexts. *)
|
|
|
|
Inductive context : Set :=
|
|
| Hole : context
|
|
| App1 : context -> exp -> context
|
|
| App2 : exp -> context -> context.
|
|
|
|
Inductive plug : context -> exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| PlugHole : forall e,
|
|
plug Hole e e
|
|
| PlugApp1 : forall c e1 e2 e,
|
|
plug c e1 e
|
|
-> plug (App1 c e2) e1 (App e e2)
|
|
| PlugApp2 : forall c e1 e2 e,
|
|
value e1
|
|
-> plug c e2 e
|
|
-> plug (App2 e1 c) e2 (App e1 e).
|
|
(* Subtle point: the [value] hypothesis right above enforces a well-formedness
|
|
* condition on contexts that may actually be plugged. We don't allow
|
|
* skipping over a lefthand subterm of an application when that term has
|
|
* evaluation work left to do. This condition is the essence of
|
|
* *call-by-value* instead of other evaluation strategies. Details are
|
|
* largely beyond our scope here. *)
|
|
|
|
(* Compared to the small-step contextual semantics from two chapters back, we
|
|
* skip a [step0] relation, since function application (called "beta
|
|
* reduction") is the only option here. *)
|
|
Inductive step : exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| ContextBeta : forall c x e v e1 e2,
|
|
value v
|
|
-> plug c (App (Abs x e) v) e1
|
|
-> plug c (subst v x e) e2
|
|
-> step e1 e2.
|
|
|
|
Hint Constructors plug step.
|
|
|
|
(* Here we now go through a proof of equivalence between big- and small-step
|
|
* semantics, though we won't spend any further commentary on it. *)
|
|
|
|
Lemma step_eval'' : forall v c x e e1 e2 v0,
|
|
value v
|
|
-> plug c (App (Abs x e) v) e1
|
|
-> plug c (subst v x e) e2
|
|
-> eval e2 v0
|
|
-> eval e1 v0.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct c; invert 2; invert 1; simplify; eauto.
|
|
invert H0; eauto.
|
|
invert H0; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve step_eval''.
|
|
|
|
Lemma step_eval' : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step e1 e2
|
|
-> forall v, eval e2 v
|
|
-> eval e1 v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; simplify; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve step_eval'.
|
|
|
|
Theorem step_eval : forall e v,
|
|
step^* e v
|
|
-> value v
|
|
-> eval e v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Lemma plug_functional : forall C e e1,
|
|
plug C e e1
|
|
-> forall e2, plug C e e2
|
|
-> e1 = e2.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; invert 1; simplify; try f_equal; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Lemma plug_mirror : forall C e e', plug C e e'
|
|
-> forall e1, exists e1', plug C e1 e1'.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; simplify; eauto.
|
|
|
|
specialize (IHplug e0); first_order; eauto.
|
|
|
|
specialize (IHplug e0); first_order; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint compose (C1 C2 : context) : context :=
|
|
match C2 with
|
|
| Hole => C1
|
|
| App1 C2' e => App1 (compose C1 C2') e
|
|
| App2 v C2' => App2 v (compose C1 C2')
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
Lemma compose_ok : forall C1 C2 e1 e2 e3,
|
|
plug C1 e1 e2
|
|
-> plug C2 e2 e3
|
|
-> plug (compose C1 C2) e1 e3.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 2; simplify; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve compose_ok.
|
|
|
|
Lemma step_plug : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step e1 e2
|
|
-> forall C e1' e2', plug C e1 e1'
|
|
-> plug C e2 e2'
|
|
-> step e1' e2'.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; simplify; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Lemma stepStar_plug : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step^* e1 e2
|
|
-> forall C e1' e2', plug C e1 e1'
|
|
-> plug C e2 e2'
|
|
-> step^* e1' e2'.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
assert (e1' = e2') by (eapply plug_functional; eassumption).
|
|
subst.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
assert (exists y', plug C y y') by eauto using plug_mirror.
|
|
invert H3.
|
|
eapply step_plug in H.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
eapply IHtrc.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve stepStar_plug eval_value.
|
|
|
|
Theorem eval_step : forall e v,
|
|
eval e v
|
|
-> step^* e v.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; eauto.
|
|
|
|
eapply trc_trans.
|
|
eapply stepStar_plug with (e1 := e1) (e2 := Abs x e1') (C := App1 Hole e2); eauto.
|
|
eapply trc_trans.
|
|
eapply stepStar_plug with (e1 := e2) (e2 := v2) (C := App2 (Abs x e1') Hole); eauto.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
End Ulc.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Now we turn to a variant of lambda calculus with static type-checking.
|
|
* This variant is called *simply typed* lambda calculus, and *simple* has a
|
|
* technical meaning, which we will explore relaxing in a problem set. *)
|
|
Module Stlc.
|
|
(* We add expression forms for numeric constants and addition. *)
|
|
Inductive exp : Set :=
|
|
| Var (x : var)
|
|
| Const (n : nat)
|
|
| Plus (e1 e2 : exp)
|
|
| Abs (x : var) (e1 : exp)
|
|
| App (e1 e2 : exp).
|
|
|
|
(* Values (final results of evaluation) *)
|
|
Inductive value : exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| VConst : forall n, value (Const n)
|
|
| VAbs : forall x e1, value (Abs x e1).
|
|
|
|
(* Substitution (not applicable when [e1] isn't closed, to avoid some complexity
|
|
* that we don't need) *)
|
|
Fixpoint subst (e1 : exp) (x : string) (e2 : exp) : exp :=
|
|
match e2 with
|
|
| Var y => if y ==v x then e1 else Var y
|
|
| Const n => Const n
|
|
| Plus e2' e2'' => Plus (subst e1 x e2') (subst e1 x e2'')
|
|
| Abs y e2' => Abs y (if y ==v x then e2' else subst e1 x e2')
|
|
| App e2' e2'' => App (subst e1 x e2') (subst e1 x e2'')
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
(* Evaluation contexts; note that we added cases for [Plus]. *)
|
|
Inductive context : Set :=
|
|
| Hole : context
|
|
| Plus1 : context -> exp -> context
|
|
| Plus2 : exp -> context -> context
|
|
| App1 : context -> exp -> context
|
|
| App2 : exp -> context -> context.
|
|
|
|
(* Plugging an expression into a context *)
|
|
Inductive plug : context -> exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| PlugHole : forall e, plug Hole e e
|
|
| PlugPlus1 : forall e e' C e2,
|
|
plug C e e'
|
|
-> plug (Plus1 C e2) e (Plus e' e2)
|
|
| PlugPlus2 : forall e e' v1 C,
|
|
value v1
|
|
-> plug C e e'
|
|
-> plug (Plus2 v1 C) e (Plus v1 e')
|
|
| PlugApp1 : forall e e' C e2,
|
|
plug C e e'
|
|
-> plug (App1 C e2) e (App e' e2)
|
|
| PlugApp2 : forall e e' v1 C,
|
|
value v1
|
|
-> plug C e e'
|
|
-> plug (App2 v1 C) e (App v1 e').
|
|
|
|
(* Small-step, call-by-value evaluation, using our evaluation contexts *)
|
|
|
|
(* First: the primitive reductions *)
|
|
Inductive step0 : exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| Beta : forall x e v,
|
|
value v
|
|
-> step0 (App (Abs x e) v) (subst v x e)
|
|
| Add : forall n1 n2,
|
|
step0 (Plus (Const n1) (Const n2)) (Const (n1 + n2)).
|
|
|
|
(* Then: running them in context *)
|
|
Inductive step : exp -> exp -> Prop :=
|
|
| StepRule : forall C e1 e2 e1' e2',
|
|
plug C e1 e1'
|
|
-> plug C e2 e2'
|
|
-> step0 e1 e2
|
|
-> step e1' e2'.
|
|
|
|
(* It's easy to wrap everything as a transition system. *)
|
|
Definition trsys_of (e : exp) := {|
|
|
Initial := {e};
|
|
Step := step
|
|
|}.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* That language is suitable to describe with a static *type system*. Here's
|
|
* our modest, but countably infinite, set of types. *)
|
|
Inductive type :=
|
|
| Nat (* Numbers *)
|
|
| Fun (dom ran : type) (* Functions *).
|
|
|
|
(* Our typing relation (also often called a "judgment") uses *typing contexts*
|
|
* (not to be confused with evaluation contexts) to map free variables to
|
|
* their types. Free variables are those that don't refer to enclosing [Abs]
|
|
* binders. *)
|
|
Inductive hasty : fmap var type -> exp -> type -> Prop :=
|
|
| HtVar : forall G x t,
|
|
G $? x = Some t
|
|
-> hasty G (Var x) t
|
|
| HtConst : forall G n,
|
|
hasty G (Const n) Nat
|
|
| HtPlus : forall G e1 e2,
|
|
hasty G e1 Nat
|
|
-> hasty G e2 Nat
|
|
-> hasty G (Plus e1 e2) Nat
|
|
| HtAbs : forall G x e1 t1 t2,
|
|
hasty (G $+ (x, t1)) e1 t2
|
|
-> hasty G (Abs x e1) (Fun t1 t2)
|
|
| HtApp : forall G e1 e2 t1 t2,
|
|
hasty G e1 (Fun t1 t2)
|
|
-> hasty G e2 t1
|
|
-> hasty G (App e1 e2) t2.
|
|
|
|
Hint Constructors value plug step0 step hasty.
|
|
|
|
(* Some notation to make it more pleasant to write programs *)
|
|
Infix "-->" := Fun (at level 60, right associativity).
|
|
Coercion Const : nat >-> exp.
|
|
Infix "^+^" := Plus (at level 50).
|
|
Coercion Var : var >-> exp.
|
|
Notation "\ x , e" := (Abs x e) (at level 51).
|
|
Infix "@" := App (at level 49, left associativity).
|
|
|
|
(* Some examples of typed programs *)
|
|
|
|
Example one_plus_one : hasty $0 (1 ^+^ 1) Nat.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Example add : hasty $0 (\"n", \"m", "n" ^+^ "m") (Nat --> Nat --> Nat).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Example eleven : hasty $0 ((\"n", \"m", "n" ^+^ "m") @ 7 @ 4) Nat.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Example seven_the_long_way : hasty $0 ((\"x", "x") @ (\"x", "x") @ 7) Nat.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
repeat (econstructor; simplify).
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Let's prove type soundness first without much automation. *)
|
|
|
|
(* What useful invariants could we prove about programs in this language? How
|
|
* about that, at every point, either they're finished executing or they can
|
|
* take further steps? For instance, a program that tried to add a function
|
|
* to a number would not satisfy that condition, and we call it *stuck*. We
|
|
* want to prove that typed programs can never become stuck. Here's a good
|
|
* invariant to strive for. *)
|
|
Definition unstuck e := value e
|
|
\/ (exists e' : exp, step e e').
|
|
|
|
(* Now we're ready for the first of the two key properties to establish that
|
|
* invariant: well-typed programs are never stuck. *)
|
|
Lemma progress : forall e t,
|
|
hasty $0 e t
|
|
-> unstuck e.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
unfold unstuck; induct 1; simplify; try equality.
|
|
|
|
left.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
propositional.
|
|
|
|
right.
|
|
(* Some automation is needed here to maintain compatibility with
|
|
* name generation in different Coq versions. *)
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H1 : value e1, H2 : hasty $0 e1 _ |- _ ] => invert H1; invert H2
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H1 : value e2, H2 : hasty $0 e2 _ |- _ ] => invert H1; invert H2
|
|
end.
|
|
exists (Const (n + n0)).
|
|
eapply StepRule with (C := Hole).
|
|
eauto.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, step e1 _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
exists (Plus x e2).
|
|
eapply StepRule with (C := Plus1 C e2).
|
|
eauto.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
left.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
propositional.
|
|
|
|
right.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H1 : value e1, H2 : hasty $0 e1 _ |- _ ] => invert H1; invert H2
|
|
end.
|
|
exists (subst e2 x e0).
|
|
eapply StepRule with (C := Hole).
|
|
eauto.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : exists x, step e1 _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
match goal with
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
end.
|
|
right.
|
|
exists (App x e2).
|
|
eapply StepRule with (C := App1 C e2).
|
|
eauto.
|
|
eauto.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* Inclusion between typing contexts is preserved by adding the same new mapping
|
|
* to both. *)
|
|
Lemma weakening_override : forall (G G' : fmap var type) x t,
|
|
(forall x' t', G $? x' = Some t' -> G' $? x' = Some t')
|
|
-> (forall x' t', G $+ (x, t) $? x' = Some t'
|
|
-> G' $+ (x, t) $? x' = Some t').
|
|
Proof.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
cases (x ==v x'); simplify; eauto.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* This lemma lets us transplant a typing derivation into a new context that
|
|
* includes the old one. *)
|
|
Lemma weakening : forall G e t,
|
|
hasty G e t
|
|
-> forall G', (forall x t, G $? x = Some t -> G' $? x = Some t)
|
|
-> hasty G' e t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
apply H0.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
apply IHhasty1.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
apply IHhasty2.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
apply IHhasty.
|
|
apply weakening_override.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
apply IHhasty1.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
apply IHhasty2.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* Replacing a variable with a properly typed term preserves typing. *)
|
|
Lemma substitution : forall G x t' e t e',
|
|
hasty (G $+ (x, t')) e t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e' t'
|
|
-> hasty G (subst e' x e) t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
cases (x0 ==v x).
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
invert H.
|
|
eapply weakening.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
eapply IHhasty1; equality.
|
|
eapply IHhasty2; equality.
|
|
|
|
cases (x0 ==v x).
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
eapply weakening.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
cases (x0 ==v x1).
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
eapply IHhasty.
|
|
maps_equal.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eapply IHhasty1; equality.
|
|
eapply IHhasty2; equality.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* We're almost ready for the other main property. Let's prove it first
|
|
* for the more basic [step0] relation: steps preserve typing. *)
|
|
Lemma preservation0 : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step0 e1 e2
|
|
-> forall t, hasty $0 e1 t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e2 t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
invert H.
|
|
invert H4.
|
|
eapply substitution.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
invert H.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* We also need this key property, essentially saying that, if [e1] and [e2] are
|
|
* "type-equivalent," then they remain "type-equivalent" after wrapping the same
|
|
* context around both. *)
|
|
Lemma generalize_plug : forall e1 C e1',
|
|
plug C e1 e1'
|
|
-> forall e2 e2', plug C e2 e2'
|
|
-> (forall t, hasty $0 e1 t -> hasty $0 e2 t)
|
|
-> (forall t, hasty $0 e1' t -> hasty $0 e2' t).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
invert H.
|
|
apply H0.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
invert H0.
|
|
invert H2.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
eapply IHplug.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
invert H1.
|
|
invert H3.
|
|
constructor.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
eapply IHplug.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
invert H0.
|
|
invert H2.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eapply IHplug.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
invert H1.
|
|
invert H3.
|
|
econstructor.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
eapply IHplug.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* OK, now we're almost done. Full steps really do preserve typing! *)
|
|
Lemma preservation : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step e1 e2
|
|
-> forall t, hasty $0 e1 t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e2 t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; simplify.
|
|
|
|
eapply generalize_plug with (e1' := e1).
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
eapply preservation0.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
(* Now watch this! Though this syntactic approach to type soundness is usually
|
|
* presented from scratch as a proof technique, it turns out that the two key
|
|
* properties, progress and preservation, are just instances of the same methods
|
|
* we've been applying all along with invariants of transition systems! *)
|
|
Theorem safety : forall e t, hasty $0 e t
|
|
-> invariantFor (trsys_of e) unstuck.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
(* Step 1: strengthen the invariant. In particular, the typing relation is
|
|
* exactly the right stronger invariant! Our progress theorem proves the
|
|
* required invariant inclusion. *)
|
|
apply invariant_weaken with (invariant1 := fun e' => hasty $0 e' t).
|
|
|
|
(* Step 2: apply invariant induction, whose induction step turns out to match
|
|
* our preservation theorem exactly! *)
|
|
apply invariant_induction; simplify.
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
eapply preservation.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
eapply progress.
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Let's do that again with more automation, whose details are beyond the
|
|
* scope of the book. *)
|
|
|
|
Ltac t0 := match goal with
|
|
| [ H : ex _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
| [ H : _ /\ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
| [ |- context[?x ==v ?y] ] => cases (x ==v y)
|
|
| [ H : Some _ = Some _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
|
|
| [ H : step _ _ |- _ ] => invert H
|
|
| [ H : step0 _ _ |- _ ] => invert1 H
|
|
| [ H : hasty _ ?e _, H' : value ?e |- _ ] => invert H'; invert H
|
|
| [ H : hasty _ _ _ |- _ ] => invert1 H
|
|
| [ H : plug _ _ _ |- _ ] => invert1 H
|
|
end; subst.
|
|
|
|
Ltac t := simplify; propositional; repeat (t0; simplify); try equality; eauto 6.
|
|
|
|
Lemma progress_snazzy : forall e t,
|
|
hasty $0 e t
|
|
-> value e
|
|
\/ (exists e' : exp, step e e').
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve weakening_override.
|
|
|
|
Lemma weakening_snazzy : forall G e t,
|
|
hasty G e t
|
|
-> forall G', (forall x t, G $? x = Some t -> G' $? x = Some t)
|
|
-> hasty G' e t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve weakening_snazzy.
|
|
|
|
(* Replacing a typing context with an equal one has no effect (useful to guide
|
|
* proof search as a hint). *)
|
|
Lemma hasty_change : forall G e t,
|
|
hasty G e t
|
|
-> forall G', G' = G
|
|
-> hasty G' e t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve hasty_change.
|
|
|
|
Lemma substitution_snazzy : forall G x t' e t e',
|
|
hasty (G $+ (x, t')) e t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e' t'
|
|
-> hasty G (subst e' x e) t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve substitution_snazzy.
|
|
|
|
Lemma preservation0_snazzy : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step0 e1 e2
|
|
-> forall t, hasty $0 e1 t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e2 t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve preservation0_snazzy.
|
|
|
|
Lemma generalize_plug_snazzy : forall e1 C e1',
|
|
plug C e1 e1'
|
|
-> forall e2 e2', plug C e2 e2'
|
|
-> (forall t, hasty $0 e1 t -> hasty $0 e2 t)
|
|
-> (forall t, hasty $0 e1' t -> hasty $0 e2' t).
|
|
Proof.
|
|
induct 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve generalize_plug_snazzy.
|
|
|
|
Lemma preservation_snazzy : forall e1 e2,
|
|
step e1 e2
|
|
-> forall t, hasty $0 e1 t
|
|
-> hasty $0 e2 t.
|
|
Proof.
|
|
invert 1; t.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
Hint Resolve progress_snazzy preservation_snazzy.
|
|
|
|
Theorem safety_snazzy : forall e t, hasty $0 e t
|
|
-> invariantFor (trsys_of e)
|
|
(fun e' => value e'
|
|
\/ exists e'', step e' e'').
|
|
Proof.
|
|
simplify.
|
|
apply invariant_weaken with (invariant1 := fun e' => hasty $0 e' t); eauto.
|
|
apply invariant_induction; simplify; eauto; equality.
|
|
Qed.
|
|
End Stlc.
|