logical-foundations/IndProp.v
2020-06-03 21:46:06 -05:00

2089 lines
71 KiB
Coq

(** * IndProp: Inductively Defined Propositions *)
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing".
From LF Require Export Logic.
Require Coq.omega.Omega.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Inductively Defined Propositions *)
(** In the [Logic] chapter, we looked at several ways of writing
propositions, including conjunction, disjunction, and existential
quantification. In this chapter, we bring yet another new tool
into the mix: _inductive definitions_. *)
(** In past chapters, we have seen two ways of stating that a number
[n] is even: We can say
(1) [evenb n = true], or
(2) [exists k, n = double k].
Yet another possibility is to say that [n] is even if we can
establish its evenness from the following rules:
- Rule [ev_0]: The number [0] is even.
- Rule [ev_SS]: If [n] is even, then [S (S n)] is even. *)
(** To illustrate how this new definition of evenness works,
let's imagine using it to show that [4] is even. By rule [ev_SS],
it suffices to show that [2] is even. This, in turn, is again
guaranteed by rule [ev_SS], as long as we can show that [0] is
even. But this last fact follows directly from the [ev_0] rule. *)
(** We will see many definitions like this one during the rest
of the course. For purposes of informal discussions, it is
helpful to have a lightweight notation that makes them easy to
read and write. _Inference rules_ are one such notation:
------------ (ev_0)
even 0
even n
---------------- (ev_SS)
even (S (S n))
*)
(** Each of the textual rules above is reformatted here as an
inference rule; the intended reading is that, if the _premises_
above the line all hold, then the _conclusion_ below the line
follows. For example, the rule [ev_SS] says that, if [n]
satisfies [even], then [S (S n)] also does. If a rule has no
premises above the line, then its conclusion holds
unconditionally.
We can represent a proof using these rules by combining rule
applications into a _proof tree_. Here's how we might transcribe
the above proof that [4] is even:
-------- (ev_0)
even 0
-------- (ev_SS)
even 2
-------- (ev_SS)
even 4
*)
(** (Why call this a "tree" (rather than a "stack", for example)?
Because, in general, inference rules can have multiple premises.
We will see examples of this shortly. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Inductive Definition of Evenness *)
(** Putting all of this together, we can translate the definition of
evenness into a formal Coq definition using an [Inductive]
declaration, where each constructor corresponds to an inference
rule: *)
Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
| ev_0 : even 0
| ev_SS (n : nat) (H : even n) : even (S (S n)).
(** This definition is different in one crucial respect from previous
uses of [Inductive]: the thing we are defining is not a [Type],
but rather a function from [nat] to [Prop] -- that is, a property
of numbers. We've already seen other inductive definitions that
result in functions -- for example, [list], whose type is [Type ->
Type]. What is really new here is that, because the [nat]
argument of [even] appears to the _right_ of the colon, it is
allowed to take different values in the types of different
constructors: [0] in the type of [ev_0] and [S (S n)] in the type
of [ev_SS].
In contrast, the definition of [list] names the [X] parameter
_globally_, to the _left_ of the colon, forcing the result of
[nil] and [cons] to be the same ([list X]). Had we tried to bring
[nat] to the left in defining [even], we would have seen an
error: *)
Fail Inductive wrong_ev (n : nat) : Prop :=
| wrong_ev_0 : wrong_ev 0
| wrong_ev_SS : wrong_ev n -> wrong_ev (S (S n)).
(* ===> Error: Last occurrence of "[wrong_ev]" must have "[n]"
as 1st argument in "[wrong_ev 0]". *)
(** In an [Inductive] definition, an argument to the type
constructor on the left of the colon is called a "parameter",
whereas an argument on the right is called an "index".
For example, in [Inductive list (X : Type) := ...], [X] is a
parameter; in [Inductive even : nat -> Prop := ...], the
unnamed [nat] argument is an index. *)
(** We can think of the definition of [even] as defining a Coq
property [even : nat -> Prop], together with primitive theorems
[ev_0 : even 0] and [ev_SS : forall n, even n -> even (S (S n))]. *)
(** That definition can also be written as follows...
Inductive even : nat -> Prop :=
| ev_0 : even 0
| ev_SS : forall n, even n -> even (S (S n)).
*)
(** ... making explicit the type of the rule [ev_SS]. *)
(** Such "constructor theorems" have the same status as proven
theorems. In particular, we can use Coq's [apply] tactic with the
rule names to prove [even] for particular numbers... *)
Theorem ev_4 : even 4.
Proof. apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply ev_0. Qed.
(** ... or we can use function application syntax: *)
Theorem ev_4' : even 4.
Proof. apply (ev_SS 2 (ev_SS 0 ev_0)). Qed.
(** We can also prove theorems that have hypotheses involving [even]. *)
Theorem ev_plus4 : forall n, even n -> even (4 + n).
Proof.
intros n. simpl. intros Hn.
apply ev_SS. apply ev_SS. apply Hn.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (ev_double) *)
Theorem ev_double : forall n,
even (double n).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Using Evidence in Proofs *)
(** Besides _constructing_ evidence that numbers are even, we can also
_reason about_ such evidence.
Introducing [even] with an [Inductive] declaration tells Coq not
only that the constructors [ev_0] and [ev_SS] are valid ways to
build evidence that some number is even, but also that these two
constructors are the _only_ ways to build evidence that numbers
are even (in the sense of [even]). *)
(** In other words, if someone gives us evidence [E] for the assertion
[even n], then we know that [E] must have one of two shapes:
- [E] is [ev_0] (and [n] is [O]), or
- [E] is [ev_SS n' E'] (and [n] is [S (S n')], where [E'] is
evidence for [even n']). *)
(** This suggests that it should be possible to analyze a
hypothesis of the form [even n] much as we do inductively defined
data structures; in particular, it should be possible to argue by
_induction_ and _case analysis_ on such evidence. Let's look at a
few examples to see what this means in practice. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Inversion on Evidence *)
(** Suppose we are proving some fact involving a number [n], and
we are given [even n] as a hypothesis. We already know how to
perform case analysis on [n] using [destruct] or [induction],
generating separate subgoals for the case where [n = O] and the
case where [n = S n'] for some [n']. But for some proofs we may
instead want to analyze the evidence that [even n] _directly_. As
a tool, we can prove our characterization of evidence for
[even n], using [destruct]. *)
Theorem ev_inversion :
forall (n : nat), even n ->
(n = 0) \/ (exists n', n = S (S n') /\ even n').
Proof.
intros n E.
destruct E as [ | n' E'].
- (* E = ev_0 : even 0 *)
left. reflexivity.
- (* E = ev_SS n' E' : even (S (S n')) *)
right. exists n'. split. reflexivity. apply E'.
Qed.
(** The following theorem can easily be proved using [destruct] on
evidence. *)
Theorem ev_minus2 : forall n,
even n -> even (pred (pred n)).
Proof.
intros n E.
destruct E as [| n' E'].
- (* E = ev_0 *) simpl. apply ev_0.
- (* E = ev_SS n' E' *) simpl. apply E'.
Qed.
(** However, this variation cannot easily be handled with [destruct]. *)
Theorem evSS_ev : forall n,
even (S (S n)) -> even n.
(** Intuitively, we know that evidence for the hypothesis cannot
consist just of the [ev_0] constructor, since [O] and [S] are
different constructors of the type [nat]; hence, [ev_SS] is the
only case that applies. Unfortunately, [destruct] is not smart
enough to realize this, and it still generates two subgoals. Even
worse, in doing so, it keeps the final goal unchanged, failing to
provide any useful information for completing the proof. *)
Proof.
intros n E.
destruct E as [| n' E'].
- (* E = ev_0. *)
(* We must prove that [n] is even from no assumptions! *)
Abort.
(** What happened, exactly? Calling [destruct] has the effect of
replacing all occurrences of the property argument by the values
that correspond to each constructor. This is enough in the case
of [ev_minus2] because that argument [n] is mentioned directly
in the final goal. However, it doesn't help in the case of
[evSS_ev] since the term that gets replaced ([S (S n)]) is not
mentioned anywhere. *)
(** We could patch this proof by replacing the goal [even n],
which does not mention the replaced term [S (S n)], by the
equivalent goal [even (pred (pred (S (S n))))], which does mention
this term, after which [destruct] can make progress. But it is
more straightforward to use our inversion lemma. *)
Theorem evSS_ev : forall n, even (S (S n)) -> even n.
Proof. intros n H. apply ev_inversion in H. destruct H.
- discriminate H.
- destruct H as [n' [Hnm Hev]]. injection Hnm.
intro Heq. rewrite Heq. apply Hev.
Qed.
(** Coq provides a tactic called [inversion], which does the work of
our inversion lemma and more besides. *)
(** The [inversion] tactic can detect (1) that the first case
([n = 0]) does not apply and (2) that the [n'] that appears in the
[ev_SS] case must be the same as [n]. It has an "[as]" variant
similar to [destruct], allowing us to assign names rather than
have Coq choose them. *)
Theorem evSS_ev' : forall n,
even (S (S n)) -> even n.
Proof.
intros n E.
inversion E as [| n' E'].
(* We are in the [E = ev_SS n' E'] case now. *)
apply E'.
Qed.
(** The [inversion] tactic can apply the principle of explosion to
"obviously contradictory" hypotheses involving inductive
properties, something that takes a bit more work using our
inversion lemma. For example: *)
Theorem one_not_even : ~ even 1.
Proof.
intros H. apply ev_inversion in H.
destruct H as [ | [m [Hm _]]].
- discriminate H.
- discriminate Hm.
Qed.
Theorem one_not_even' : ~ even 1.
intros H. inversion H. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (inversion_practice)
Prove the following result using [inversion]. For extra practice,
prove it using the inversion lemma. *)
Theorem SSSSev__even : forall n,
even (S (S (S (S n)))) -> even n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (even5_nonsense)
Prove the following result using [inversion]. *)
Theorem even5_nonsense :
even 5 -> 2 + 2 = 9.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** The [inversion] tactic does quite a bit of work. When
applied to equalities, as a special case, it does the work of both
[discriminate] and [injection]. In addition, it carries out the
[intros] and [rewrite]s that are typically necessary in the case
of [injection]. It can also be applied, more generally, to analyze
evidence for inductively defined propositions. As examples, we'll
use it to reprove some theorems from [Tactics.v]. *)
Theorem inversion_ex1 : forall (n m o : nat),
[n; m] = [o; o] ->
[n] = [m].
Proof.
intros n m o H. inversion H. reflexivity. Qed.
Theorem inversion_ex2 : forall (n : nat),
S n = O ->
2 + 2 = 5.
Proof.
intros n contra. inversion contra. Qed.
(** Here's how [inversion] works in general. Suppose the name
[H] refers to an assumption [P] in the current context, where [P]
has been defined by an [Inductive] declaration. Then, for each of
the constructors of [P], [inversion H] generates a subgoal in which
[H] has been replaced by the exact, specific conditions under
which this constructor could have been used to prove [P]. Some of
these subgoals will be self-contradictory; [inversion] throws
these away. The ones that are left represent the cases that must
be proved to establish the original goal. For those, [inversion]
adds all equations into the proof context that must hold of the
arguments given to [P] (e.g., [S (S n') = n] in the proof of
[evSS_ev]). *)
(** The [ev_double] exercise above shows that our new notion of
evenness is implied by the two earlier ones (since, by
[even_bool_prop] in chapter [Logic], we already know that
those are equivalent to each other). To show that all three
coincide, we just need the following lemma. *)
Lemma ev_even_firsttry : forall n,
even n -> exists k, n = double k.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
(** We could try to proceed by case analysis or induction on [n]. But
since [even] is mentioned in a premise, this strategy would
probably lead to a dead end, as in the previous section. Thus, it
seems better to first try [inversion] on the evidence for [even].
Indeed, the first case can be solved trivially. *)
intros n E. inversion E as [| n' E'].
- (* E = ev_0 *)
exists 0. reflexivity.
- (* E = ev_SS n' E' *) simpl.
(** Unfortunately, the second case is harder. We need to show [exists
k, S (S n') = double k], but the only available assumption is
[E'], which states that [even n'] holds. Since this isn't
directly useful, it seems that we are stuck and that performing
case analysis on [E] was a waste of time.
If we look more closely at our second goal, however, we can see
that something interesting happened: By performing case analysis
on [E], we were able to reduce the original result to a similar
one that involves a _different_ piece of evidence for [even]:
namely [E']. More formally, we can finish our proof by showing
that
exists k', n' = double k',
which is the same as the original statement, but with [n'] instead
of [n]. Indeed, it is not difficult to convince Coq that this
intermediate result suffices. *)
assert (I : (exists k', n' = double k') ->
(exists k, S (S n') = double k)).
{ intros [k' Hk']. rewrite Hk'. exists (S k'). reflexivity. }
apply I. (* reduce the original goal to the new one *)
Abort.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Induction on Evidence *)
(** If this looks familiar, it is no coincidence: We've
encountered similar problems in the [Induction] chapter, when
trying to use case analysis to prove results that required
induction. And once again the solution is... induction!
The behavior of [induction] on evidence is the same as its
behavior on data: It causes Coq to generate one subgoal for each
constructor that could have used to build that evidence, while
providing an induction hypotheses for each recursive occurrence of
the property in question.
To prove a property of [n] holds for all numbers for which [even
n] holds, we can use induction on [even n]. This requires us to
prove two things, corresponding to the two ways in which [even n]
could have been constructed. If it was constructed by [ev_0], then
[n=0], and the property must hold of [0]. If it was constructed by
[ev_SS], then the evidence of [even n] is of the form [ev_SS n'
E'], where [n = S (S n')] and [E'] is evidence for [even n']. In
this case, the inductive hypothesis says that the property we are
trying to prove holds for [n']. *)
(** Let's try our current lemma again: *)
Lemma ev_even : forall n,
even n -> exists k, n = double k.
Proof.
intros n E.
induction E as [|n' E' IH].
- (* E = ev_0 *)
exists 0. reflexivity.
- (* E = ev_SS n' E'
with IH : exists k', n' = double k' *)
destruct IH as [k' Hk'].
rewrite Hk'. exists (S k'). reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Here, we can see that Coq produced an [IH] that corresponds
to [E'], the single recursive occurrence of [even] in its own
definition. Since [E'] mentions [n'], the induction hypothesis
talks about [n'], as opposed to [n] or some other number. *)
(** The equivalence between the second and third definitions of
evenness now follows. *)
Theorem ev_even_iff : forall n,
even n <-> exists k, n = double k.
Proof.
intros n. split.
- (* -> *) apply ev_even.
- (* <- *) intros [k Hk]. rewrite Hk. apply ev_double.
Qed.
(** As we will see in later chapters, induction on evidence is a
recurring technique across many areas, and in particular when
formalizing the semantics of programming languages, where many
properties of interest are defined inductively. *)
(** The following exercises provide simple examples of this
technique, to help you familiarize yourself with it. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (ev_sum) *)
Theorem ev_sum : forall n m, even n -> even m -> even (n + m).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced, optional (even'_ev)
In general, there may be multiple ways of defining a
property inductively. For example, here's a (slightly contrived)
alternative definition for [even]: *)
Inductive even' : nat -> Prop :=
| even'_0 : even' 0
| even'_2 : even' 2
| even'_sum n m (Hn : even' n) (Hm : even' m) : even' (n + m).
(** Prove that this definition is logically equivalent to the old
one. (You may want to look at the previous theorem when you get
to the induction step.) *)
Theorem even'_ev : forall n, even' n <-> even n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced, recommended (ev_ev__ev)
Finding the appropriate thing to do induction on is a
bit tricky here: *)
Theorem ev_ev__ev : forall n m,
even (n+m) -> even n -> even m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (ev_plus_plus)
This exercise just requires applying existing lemmas. No
induction or even case analysis is needed, though some of the
rewriting may be tedious. *)
Theorem ev_plus_plus : forall n m p,
even (n+m) -> even (n+p) -> even (m+p).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Inductive Relations *)
(** A proposition parameterized by a number (such as [even])
can be thought of as a _property_ -- i.e., it defines
a subset of [nat], namely those numbers for which the proposition
is provable. In the same way, a two-argument proposition can be
thought of as a _relation_ -- i.e., it defines a set of pairs for
which the proposition is provable. *)
Module Playground.
(** One useful example is the "less than or equal to" relation on
numbers. *)
(** The following definition should be fairly intuitive. It
says that there are two ways to give evidence that one number is
less than or equal to another: either observe that they are the
same number, or give evidence that the first is less than or equal
to the predecessor of the second. *)
Inductive le : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| le_n n : le n n
| le_S n m (H : le n m) : le n (S m).
Notation "m <= n" := (le m n).
(** Proofs of facts about [<=] using the constructors [le_n] and
[le_S] follow the same patterns as proofs about properties, like
[even] above. We can [apply] the constructors to prove [<=]
goals (e.g., to show that [3<=3] or [3<=6]), and we can use
tactics like [inversion] to extract information from [<=]
hypotheses in the context (e.g., to prove that [(2 <= 1) ->
2+2=5].) *)
(** Here are some sanity checks on the definition. (Notice that,
although these are the same kind of simple "unit tests" as we gave
for the testing functions we wrote in the first few lectures, we
must construct their proofs explicitly -- [simpl] and
[reflexivity] don't do the job, because the proofs aren't just a
matter of simplifying computations.) *)
Theorem test_le1 :
3 <= 3.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
apply le_n. Qed.
Theorem test_le2 :
3 <= 6.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
apply le_S. apply le_S. apply le_S. apply le_n. Qed.
Theorem test_le3 :
(2 <= 1) -> 2 + 2 = 5.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros H. inversion H. inversion H2. Qed.
(** The "strictly less than" relation [n < m] can now be defined
in terms of [le]. *)
End Playground.
Definition lt (n m:nat) := le (S n) m.
Notation "m < n" := (lt m n).
(** Here are a few more simple relations on numbers: *)
Inductive square_of : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| sq n : square_of n (n * n).
Inductive next_nat : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| nn n : next_nat n (S n).
Inductive next_even : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| ne_1 n : even (S n) -> next_even n (S n)
| ne_2 n (H : even (S (S n))) : next_even n (S (S n)).
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (total_relation)
Define an inductive binary relation [total_relation] that holds
between every pair of natural numbers. *)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (empty_relation)
Define an inductive binary relation [empty_relation] (on numbers)
that never holds. *)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(** From the definition of [le], we can sketch the behaviors of
[destruct], [inversion], and [induction] on a hypothesis [H]
providing evidence of the form [le e1 e2]. Doing [destruct H]
will generate two cases. In the first case, [e1 = e2], and it
will replace instances of [e2] with [e1] in the goal and context.
In the second case, [e2 = S n'] for some [n'] for which [le e1 n']
holds, and it will replace instances of [e2] with [S n'].
Doing [inversion H] will remove impossible cases and add generated
equalities to the context for further use. Doing [induction H]
will, in the second case, add the induction hypothesis that the
goal holds when [e2] is replaced with [n']. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (le_exercises)
Here are a number of facts about the [<=] and [<] relations that
we are going to need later in the course. The proofs make good
practice exercises. *)
Lemma le_trans : forall m n o, m <= n -> n <= o -> m <= o.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem O_le_n : forall n,
0 <= n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem n_le_m__Sn_le_Sm : forall n m,
n <= m -> S n <= S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem Sn_le_Sm__n_le_m : forall n m,
S n <= S m -> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem le_plus_l : forall a b,
a <= a + b.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem plus_lt : forall n1 n2 m,
n1 + n2 < m ->
n1 < m /\ n2 < m.
Proof.
unfold lt.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem lt_S : forall n m,
n < m ->
n < S m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem leb_complete : forall n m,
n <=? m = true -> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Hint: The next one may be easiest to prove by induction on [m]. *)
Theorem leb_correct : forall n m,
n <= m ->
n <=? m = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Hint: This one can easily be proved without using [induction]. *)
Theorem leb_true_trans : forall n m o,
n <=? m = true -> m <=? o = true -> n <=? o = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (leb_iff) *)
Theorem leb_iff : forall n m,
n <=? m = true <-> n <= m.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
Module R.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, recommended (R_provability)
We can define three-place relations, four-place relations,
etc., in just the same way as binary relations. For example,
consider the following three-place relation on numbers: *)
Inductive R : nat -> nat -> nat -> Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 0 0
| c2 m n o (H : R m n o) : R (S m) n (S o)
| c3 m n o (H : R m n o) : R m (S n) (S o)
| c4 m n o (H : R (S m) (S n) (S (S o))) : R m n o
| c5 m n o (H : R m n o) : R n m o.
(** - Which of the following propositions are provable?
- [R 1 1 2]
- [R 2 2 6]
- If we dropped constructor [c5] from the definition of [R],
would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1
sentence) explain your answer.
- If we dropped constructor [c4] from the definition of [R],
would the set of provable propositions change? Briefly (1
sentence) explain your answer.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
*)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_R_provability : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (R_fact)
The relation [R] above actually encodes a familiar function.
Figure out which function; then state and prove this equivalence
in Coq? *)
Definition fR : nat -> nat -> nat
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Theorem R_equiv_fR : forall m n o, R m n o <-> fR m n = o.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
End R.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (subsequence)
A list is a _subsequence_ of another list if all of the elements
in the first list occur in the same order in the second list,
possibly with some extra elements in between. For example,
[1;2;3]
is a subsequence of each of the lists
[1;2;3]
[1;1;1;2;2;3]
[1;2;7;3]
[5;6;1;9;9;2;7;3;8]
but it is _not_ a subsequence of any of the lists
[1;2]
[1;3]
[5;6;2;1;7;3;8].
- Define an inductive proposition [subseq] on [list nat] that
captures what it means to be a subsequence. (Hint: You'll need
three cases.)
- Prove [subseq_refl] that subsequence is reflexive, that is,
any list is a subsequence of itself.
- Prove [subseq_app] that for any lists [l1], [l2], and [l3],
if [l1] is a subsequence of [l2], then [l1] is also a subsequence
of [l2 ++ l3].
- (Optional, harder) Prove [subseq_trans] that subsequence is
transitive -- that is, if [l1] is a subsequence of [l2] and [l2]
is a subsequence of [l3], then [l1] is a subsequence of [l3].
Hint: choose your induction carefully! *)
Inductive subseq : list nat -> list nat -> Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Theorem subseq_refl : forall (l : list nat), subseq l l.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem subseq_app : forall (l1 l2 l3 : list nat),
subseq l1 l2 ->
subseq l1 (l2 ++ l3).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem subseq_trans : forall (l1 l2 l3 : list nat),
subseq l1 l2 ->
subseq l2 l3 ->
subseq l1 l3.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (R_provability2)
Suppose we give Coq the following definition:
Inductive R : nat -> list nat -> Prop :=
| c1 : R 0 []
| c2 : forall n l, R n l -> R (S n) (n :: l)
| c3 : forall n l, R (S n) l -> R n l.
Which of the following propositions are provable?
- [R 2 [1;0]]
- [R 1 [1;2;1;0]]
- [R 6 [3;2;1;0]] *)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Case Study: Regular Expressions *)
(** The [even] property provides a simple example for
illustrating inductive definitions and the basic techniques for
reasoning about them, but it is not terribly exciting -- after
all, it is equivalent to the two non-inductive definitions of
evenness that we had already seen, and does not seem to offer any
concrete benefit over them.
To give a better sense of the power of inductive definitions, we
now show how to use them to model a classic concept in computer
science: _regular expressions_. *)
(** Regular expressions are a simple language for describing sets of
strings. Their syntax is defined as follows: *)
Inductive reg_exp {T : Type} : Type :=
| EmptySet
| EmptyStr
| Char (t : T)
| App (r1 r2 : reg_exp)
| Union (r1 r2 : reg_exp)
| Star (r : reg_exp).
(** Note that this definition is _polymorphic_: Regular
expressions in [reg_exp T] describe strings with characters drawn
from [T] -- that is, lists of elements of [T].
(We depart slightly from standard practice in that we do not
require the type [T] to be finite. This results in a somewhat
different theory of regular expressions, but the difference is not
significant for our purposes.) *)
(** We connect regular expressions and strings via the following
rules, which define when a regular expression _matches_ some
string:
- The expression [EmptySet] does not match any string.
- The expression [EmptyStr] matches the empty string [[]].
- The expression [Char x] matches the one-character string [[x]].
- If [re1] matches [s1], and [re2] matches [s2],
then [App re1 re2] matches [s1 ++ s2].
- If at least one of [re1] and [re2] matches [s],
then [Union re1 re2] matches [s].
- Finally, if we can write some string [s] as the concatenation
of a sequence of strings [s = s_1 ++ ... ++ s_k], and the
expression [re] matches each one of the strings [s_i],
then [Star re] matches [s].
As a special case, the sequence of strings may be empty, so
[Star re] always matches the empty string [[]] no matter what
[re] is. *)
(** We can easily translate this informal definition into an
[Inductive] one as follows: *)
Inductive exp_match {T} : list T -> reg_exp -> Prop :=
| MEmpty : exp_match [] EmptyStr
| MChar x : exp_match [x] (Char x)
| MApp s1 re1 s2 re2
(H1 : exp_match s1 re1)
(H2 : exp_match s2 re2) :
exp_match (s1 ++ s2) (App re1 re2)
| MUnionL s1 re1 re2
(H1 : exp_match s1 re1) :
exp_match s1 (Union re1 re2)
| MUnionR re1 s2 re2
(H2 : exp_match s2 re2) :
exp_match s2 (Union re1 re2)
| MStar0 re : exp_match [] (Star re)
| MStarApp s1 s2 re
(H1 : exp_match s1 re)
(H2 : exp_match s2 (Star re)) :
exp_match (s1 ++ s2) (Star re).
(** Again, for readability, we can also display this definition using
inference-rule notation. At the same time, let's introduce a more
readable infix notation. *)
Notation "s =~ re" := (exp_match s re) (at level 80).
(**
---------------- (MEmpty)
[] =~ EmptyStr
--------------- (MChar)
[x] =~ Char x
s1 =~ re1 s2 =~ re2
------------------------- (MApp)
s1 ++ s2 =~ App re1 re2
s1 =~ re1
--------------------- (MUnionL)
s1 =~ Union re1 re2
s2 =~ re2
--------------------- (MUnionR)
s2 =~ Union re1 re2
--------------- (MStar0)
[] =~ Star re
s1 =~ re s2 =~ Star re
--------------------------- (MStarApp)
s1 ++ s2 =~ Star re
*)
(** Notice that these rules are not _quite_ the same as the
informal ones that we gave at the beginning of the section.
First, we don't need to include a rule explicitly stating that no
string matches [EmptySet]; we just don't happen to include any
rule that would have the effect of some string matching
[EmptySet]. (Indeed, the syntax of inductive definitions doesn't
even _allow_ us to give such a "negative rule.")
Second, the informal rules for [Union] and [Star] correspond
to two constructors each: [MUnionL] / [MUnionR], and [MStar0] /
[MStarApp]. The result is logically equivalent to the original
rules but more convenient to use in Coq, since the recursive
occurrences of [exp_match] are given as direct arguments to the
constructors, making it easier to perform induction on evidence.
(The [exp_match_ex1] and [exp_match_ex2] exercises below ask you
to prove that the constructors given in the inductive declaration
and the ones that would arise from a more literal transcription of
the informal rules are indeed equivalent.)
Let's illustrate these rules with a few examples. *)
Example reg_exp_ex1 : [1] =~ Char 1.
Proof.
apply MChar.
Qed.
Example reg_exp_ex2 : [1; 2] =~ App (Char 1) (Char 2).
Proof.
apply (MApp [1] _ [2]).
- apply MChar.
- apply MChar.
Qed.
(** (Notice how the last example applies [MApp] to the strings
[[1]] and [[2]] directly. Since the goal mentions [[1; 2]]
instead of [[1] ++ [2]], Coq wouldn't be able to figure out how to
split the string on its own.)
Using [inversion], we can also show that certain strings do _not_
match a regular expression: *)
Example reg_exp_ex3 : ~ ([1; 2] =~ Char 1).
Proof.
intros H. inversion H.
Qed.
(** We can define helper functions for writing down regular
expressions. The [reg_exp_of_list] function constructs a regular
expression that matches exactly the list that it receives as an
argument: *)
Fixpoint reg_exp_of_list {T} (l : list T) :=
match l with
| [] => EmptyStr
| x :: l' => App (Char x) (reg_exp_of_list l')
end.
Example reg_exp_ex4 : [1; 2; 3] =~ reg_exp_of_list [1; 2; 3].
Proof.
simpl. apply (MApp [1]).
{ apply MChar. }
apply (MApp [2]).
{ apply MChar. }
apply (MApp [3]).
{ apply MChar. }
apply MEmpty.
Qed.
(** We can also prove general facts about [exp_match]. For instance,
the following lemma shows that every string [s] that matches [re]
also matches [Star re]. *)
Lemma MStar1 :
forall T s (re : @reg_exp T) ,
s =~ re ->
s =~ Star re.
Proof.
intros T s re H.
rewrite <- (app_nil_r _ s).
apply (MStarApp s [] re).
- apply H.
- apply MStar0.
Qed.
(** (Note the use of [app_nil_r] to change the goal of the theorem to
exactly the same shape expected by [MStarApp].) *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (exp_match_ex1)
The following lemmas show that the informal matching rules given
at the beginning of the chapter can be obtained from the formal
inductive definition. *)
Lemma empty_is_empty : forall T (s : list T),
~ (s =~ EmptySet).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Lemma MUnion' : forall T (s : list T) (re1 re2 : @reg_exp T),
s =~ re1 \/ s =~ re2 ->
s =~ Union re1 re2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** The next lemma is stated in terms of the [fold] function from the
[Poly] chapter: If [ss : list (list T)] represents a sequence of
strings [s1, ..., sn], then [fold app ss []] is the result of
concatenating them all together. *)
Lemma MStar' : forall T (ss : list (list T)) (re : reg_exp),
(forall s, In s ss -> s =~ re) ->
fold app ss [] =~ Star re.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard, optional (reg_exp_of_list_spec)
Prove that [reg_exp_of_list] satisfies the following
specification: *)
Lemma reg_exp_of_list_spec : forall T (s1 s2 : list T),
s1 =~ reg_exp_of_list s2 <-> s1 = s2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Since the definition of [exp_match] has a recursive
structure, we might expect that proofs involving regular
expressions will often require induction on evidence. *)
(** For example, suppose that we wanted to prove the following
intuitive result: If a regular expression [re] matches some string
[s], then all elements of [s] must occur as character literals
somewhere in [re].
To state this theorem, we first define a function [re_chars] that
lists all characters that occur in a regular expression: *)
Fixpoint re_chars {T} (re : reg_exp) : list T :=
match re with
| EmptySet => []
| EmptyStr => []
| Char x => [x]
| App re1 re2 => re_chars re1 ++ re_chars re2
| Union re1 re2 => re_chars re1 ++ re_chars re2
| Star re => re_chars re
end.
(** We can then phrase our theorem as follows: *)
Theorem in_re_match : forall T (s : list T) (re : reg_exp) (x : T),
s =~ re ->
In x s ->
In x (re_chars re).
Proof.
intros T s re x Hmatch Hin.
induction Hmatch
as [| x'
| s1 re1 s2 re2 Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2
| s1 re1 re2 Hmatch IH | re1 s2 re2 Hmatch IH
| re | s1 s2 re Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2].
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
- (* MEmpty *)
apply Hin.
- (* MChar *)
apply Hin.
- simpl. rewrite In_app_iff in *.
destruct Hin as [Hin | Hin].
+ (* In x s1 *)
left. apply (IH1 Hin).
+ (* In x s2 *)
right. apply (IH2 Hin).
- (* MUnionL *)
simpl. rewrite In_app_iff.
left. apply (IH Hin).
- (* MUnionR *)
simpl. rewrite In_app_iff.
right. apply (IH Hin).
- (* MStar0 *)
destruct Hin.
(** Something interesting happens in the [MStarApp] case. We obtain
_two_ induction hypotheses: One that applies when [x] occurs in
[s1] (which matches [re]), and a second one that applies when [x]
occurs in [s2] (which matches [Star re]). This is a good
illustration of why we need induction on evidence for [exp_match],
rather than induction on the regular expression [re]: The latter
would only provide an induction hypothesis for strings that match
[re], which would not allow us to reason about the case [In x
s2]. *)
- (* MStarApp *)
simpl. rewrite In_app_iff in Hin.
destruct Hin as [Hin | Hin].
+ (* In x s1 *)
apply (IH1 Hin).
+ (* In x s2 *)
apply (IH2 Hin).
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard (re_not_empty)
Write a recursive function [re_not_empty] that tests whether a
regular expression matches some string. Prove that your function
is correct. *)
Fixpoint re_not_empty {T : Type} (re : @reg_exp T) : bool
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Lemma re_not_empty_correct : forall T (re : @reg_exp T),
(exists s, s =~ re) <-> re_not_empty re = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** The [remember] Tactic *)
(** One potentially confusing feature of the [induction] tactic is
that it will let you try to perform an induction over a term that
isn't sufficiently general. The effect of this is to lose
information (much as [destruct] without an [eqn:] clause can do),
and leave you unable to complete the proof. Here's an example: *)
Lemma star_app: forall T (s1 s2 : list T) (re : @reg_exp T),
s1 =~ Star re ->
s2 =~ Star re ->
s1 ++ s2 =~ Star re.
Proof.
intros T s1 s2 re H1.
(** Just doing an [inversion] on [H1] won't get us very far in
the recursive cases. (Try it!). So we need induction (on
evidence!). Here is a naive first attempt: *)
induction H1
as [|x'|s1 re1 s2' re2 Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2
|s1 re1 re2 Hmatch IH|re1 s2' re2 Hmatch IH
|re''|s1 s2' re'' Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2].
(** But now, although we get seven cases (as we would expect from the
definition of [exp_match]), we have lost a very important bit of
information from [H1]: the fact that [s1] matched something of the
form [Star re]. This means that we have to give proofs for _all_
seven constructors of this definition, even though all but two of
them ([MStar0] and [MStarApp]) are contradictory. We can still
get the proof to go through for a few constructors, such as
[MEmpty]... *)
- (* MEmpty *)
simpl. intros H. apply H.
(** ... but most cases get stuck. For [MChar], for instance, we
must show that
s2 =~ Char x' -> x' :: s2 =~ Char x',
which is clearly impossible. *)
- (* MChar. Stuck... *)
Abort.
(** The problem is that [induction] over a Prop hypothesis only works
properly with hypotheses that are completely general, i.e., ones
in which all the arguments are variables, as opposed to more
complex expressions, such as [Star re].
(In this respect, [induction] on evidence behaves more like
[destruct]-without-[eqn:] than like [inversion].)
An awkward way to solve this problem is "manually generalizing"
over the problematic expressions by adding explicit equality
hypotheses to the lemma: *)
Lemma star_app: forall T (s1 s2 : list T) (re re' : reg_exp),
re' = Star re ->
s1 =~ re' ->
s2 =~ Star re ->
s1 ++ s2 =~ Star re.
(** We can now proceed by performing induction over evidence directly,
because the argument to the first hypothesis is sufficiently
general, which means that we can discharge most cases by inverting
the [re' = Star re] equality in the context.
This idiom is so common that Coq provides a tactic to
automatically generate such equations for us, avoiding thus the
need for changing the statements of our theorems. *)
Abort.
(** The tactic [remember e as x] causes Coq to (1) replace all
occurrences of the expression [e] by the variable [x], and (2) add
an equation [x = e] to the context. Here's how we can use it to
show the above result: *)
Lemma star_app: forall T (s1 s2 : list T) (re : reg_exp),
s1 =~ Star re ->
s2 =~ Star re ->
s1 ++ s2 =~ Star re.
Proof.
intros T s1 s2 re H1.
remember (Star re) as re'.
(** We now have [Heqre' : re' = Star re]. *)
generalize dependent s2.
induction H1
as [|x'|s1 re1 s2' re2 Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2
|s1 re1 re2 Hmatch IH|re1 s2' re2 Hmatch IH
|re''|s1 s2' re'' Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2].
(** The [Heqre'] is contradictory in most cases, allowing us to
conclude immediately. *)
- (* MEmpty *) discriminate.
- (* MChar *) discriminate.
- (* MApp *) discriminate.
- (* MUnionL *) discriminate.
- (* MUnionR *) discriminate.
(** The interesting cases are those that correspond to [Star]. Note
that the induction hypothesis [IH2] on the [MStarApp] case
mentions an additional premise [Star re'' = Star re'], which
results from the equality generated by [remember]. *)
- (* MStar0 *)
injection Heqre'. intros Heqre'' s H. apply H.
- (* MStarApp *)
injection Heqre'. intros H0.
intros s2 H1. rewrite <- app_assoc.
apply MStarApp.
+ apply Hmatch1.
+ apply IH2.
* rewrite H0. reflexivity.
* apply H1.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard, optional (exp_match_ex2) *)
(** The [MStar''] lemma below (combined with its converse, the
[MStar'] exercise above), shows that our definition of [exp_match]
for [Star] is equivalent to the informal one given previously. *)
Lemma MStar'' : forall T (s : list T) (re : reg_exp),
s =~ Star re ->
exists ss : list (list T),
s = fold app ss []
/\ forall s', In s' ss -> s' =~ re.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, advanced (pumping)
One of the first really interesting theorems in the theory of
regular expressions is the so-called _pumping lemma_, which
states, informally, that any sufficiently long string [s] matching
a regular expression [re] can be "pumped" by repeating some middle
section of [s] an arbitrary number of times to produce a new
string also matching [re].
To begin, we need to define "sufficiently long." Since we are
working in a constructive logic, we actually need to be able to
calculate, for each regular expression [re], the minimum length
for strings [s] to guarantee "pumpability." *)
Module Pumping.
Fixpoint pumping_constant {T} (re : @reg_exp T) : nat :=
match re with
| EmptySet => 0
| EmptyStr => 1
| Char _ => 2
| App re1 re2 =>
pumping_constant re1 + pumping_constant re2
| Union re1 re2 =>
pumping_constant re1 + pumping_constant re2
| Star _ => 1
end.
(** Next, it is useful to define an auxiliary function that repeats a
string (appends it to itself) some number of times. *)
Fixpoint napp {T} (n : nat) (l : list T) : list T :=
match n with
| 0 => []
| S n' => l ++ napp n' l
end.
Lemma napp_plus: forall T (n m : nat) (l : list T),
napp (n + m) l = napp n l ++ napp m l.
Proof.
intros T n m l.
induction n as [|n IHn].
- reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite IHn, app_assoc. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Now, the pumping lemma itself says that, if [s =~ re] and if the
length of [s] is at least the pumping constant of [re], then [s]
can be split into three substrings [s1 ++ s2 ++ s3] in such a way
that [s2] can be repeated any number of times and the result, when
combined with [s1] and [s3] will still match [re]. Since [s2] is
also guaranteed not to be the empty string, this gives us
a (constructive!) way to generate strings matching [re] that are
as long as we like. *)
Lemma pumping : forall T (re : @reg_exp T) s,
s =~ re ->
pumping_constant re <= length s ->
exists s1 s2 s3,
s = s1 ++ s2 ++ s3 /\
s2 <> [] /\
forall m, s1 ++ napp m s2 ++ s3 =~ re.
(** To streamline the proof (which you are to fill in), the [omega]
tactic, which is enabled by the following [Require], is helpful in
several places for automatically completing tedious low-level
arguments involving equalities or inequalities over natural
numbers. We'll return to [omega] in a later chapter, but feel
free to experiment with it now if you like. The first case of the
induction gives an example of how it is used. *)
Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Proof.
intros T re s Hmatch.
induction Hmatch
as [ | x | s1 re1 s2 re2 Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2
| s1 re1 re2 Hmatch IH | re1 s2 re2 Hmatch IH
| re | s1 s2 re Hmatch1 IH1 Hmatch2 IH2 ].
- (* MEmpty *)
simpl. omega.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
End Pumping.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Case Study: Improving Reflection *)
(** We've seen in the [Logic] chapter that we often need to
relate boolean computations to statements in [Prop]. But
performing this conversion as we did it there can result in
tedious proof scripts. Consider the proof of the following
theorem: *)
Theorem filter_not_empty_In : forall n l,
filter (fun x => n =? x) l <> [] ->
In n l.
Proof.
intros n l. induction l as [|m l' IHl'].
- (* l = [] *)
simpl. intros H. apply H. reflexivity.
- (* l = m :: l' *)
simpl. destruct (n =? m) eqn:H.
+ (* n =? m = true *)
intros _. rewrite eqb_eq in H. rewrite H.
left. reflexivity.
+ (* n =? m = false *)
intros H'. right. apply IHl'. apply H'.
Qed.
(** In the first branch after [destruct], we explicitly apply
the [eqb_eq] lemma to the equation generated by
destructing [n =? m], to convert the assumption [n =? m
= true] into the assumption [n = m]; then we had to [rewrite]
using this assumption to complete the case. *)
(** We can streamline this by defining an inductive proposition that
yields a better case-analysis principle for [n =? m].
Instead of generating an equation such as [(n =? m) = true],
which is generally not directly useful, this principle gives us
right away the assumption we really need: [n = m]. *)
Inductive reflect (P : Prop) : bool -> Prop :=
| ReflectT (H : P) : reflect P true
| ReflectF (H : ~ P) : reflect P false.
(** The [reflect] property takes two arguments: a proposition
[P] and a boolean [b]. Intuitively, it states that the property
[P] is _reflected_ in (i.e., equivalent to) the boolean [b]: that
is, [P] holds if and only if [b = true]. To see this, notice
that, by definition, the only way we can produce evidence for
[reflect P true] is by showing [P] and then using the [ReflectT]
constructor. If we invert this statement, this means that it
should be possible to extract evidence for [P] from a proof of
[reflect P true]. Similarly, the only way to show [reflect P
false] is by combining evidence for [~ P] with the [ReflectF]
constructor.
It is easy to formalize this intuition and show that the
statements [P <-> b = true] and [reflect P b] are indeed
equivalent. First, the left-to-right implication: *)
Theorem iff_reflect : forall P b, (P <-> b = true) -> reflect P b.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P b H. destruct b.
- apply ReflectT. rewrite H. reflexivity.
- apply ReflectF. rewrite H. intros H'. discriminate.
Qed.
(** Now you prove the right-to-left implication: *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, recommended (reflect_iff) *)
Theorem reflect_iff : forall P b, reflect P b -> (P <-> b = true).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** The advantage of [reflect] over the normal "if and only if"
connective is that, by destructing a hypothesis or lemma of the
form [reflect P b], we can perform case analysis on [b] while at
the same time generating appropriate hypothesis in the two
branches ([P] in the first subgoal and [~ P] in the second). *)
Lemma eqbP : forall n m, reflect (n = m) (n =? m).
Proof.
intros n m. apply iff_reflect. rewrite eqb_eq. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** A smoother proof of [filter_not_empty_In] now goes as follows.
Notice how the calls to [destruct] and [apply] are combined into a
single call to [destruct]. *)
(** (To see this clearly, look at the two proofs of
[filter_not_empty_In] with Coq and observe the differences in
proof state at the beginning of the first case of the
[destruct].) *)
Theorem filter_not_empty_In' : forall n l,
filter (fun x => n =? x) l <> [] ->
In n l.
Proof.
intros n l. induction l as [|m l' IHl'].
- (* l = [] *)
simpl. intros H. apply H. reflexivity.
- (* l = m :: l' *)
simpl. destruct (eqbP n m) as [H | H].
+ (* n = m *)
intros _. rewrite H. left. reflexivity.
+ (* n <> m *)
intros H'. right. apply IHl'. apply H'.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, recommended (eqbP_practice)
Use [eqbP] as above to prove the following: *)
Fixpoint count n l :=
match l with
| [] => 0
| m :: l' => (if n =? m then 1 else 0) + count n l'
end.
Theorem eqbP_practice : forall n l,
count n l = 0 -> ~(In n l).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** This small example shows how reflection gives us a small gain in
convenience; in larger developments, using [reflect] consistently
can often lead to noticeably shorter and clearer proof scripts.
We'll see many more examples in later chapters and in _Programming
Language Foundations_.
The use of the [reflect] property has been popularized by
_SSReflect_, a Coq library that has been used to formalize
important results in mathematics, including as the 4-color theorem
and the Feit-Thompson theorem. The name SSReflect stands for
_small-scale reflection_, i.e., the pervasive use of reflection to
simplify small proof steps with boolean computations. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Additional Exercises *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, recommended (nostutter_defn)
Formulating inductive definitions of properties is an important
skill you'll need in this course. Try to solve this exercise
without any help at all.
We say that a list "stutters" if it repeats the same element
consecutively. (This is different from not containing duplicates:
the sequence [[1;4;1]] repeats the element [1] but does not
stutter.) The property "[nostutter mylist]" means that [mylist]
does not stutter. Formulate an inductive definition for
[nostutter]. *)
Inductive nostutter {X:Type} : list X -> Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
(** Make sure each of these tests succeeds, but feel free to change
the suggested proof (in comments) if the given one doesn't work
for you. Your definition might be different from ours and still
be correct, in which case the examples might need a different
proof. (You'll notice that the suggested proofs use a number of
tactics we haven't talked about, to make them more robust to
different possible ways of defining [nostutter]. You can probably
just uncomment and use them as-is, but you can also prove each
example with more basic tactics.) *)
Example test_nostutter_1: nostutter [3;1;4;1;5;6].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(*
Proof. repeat constructor; apply eqb_neq; auto.
Qed.
*)
Example test_nostutter_2: nostutter (@nil nat).
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(*
Proof. repeat constructor; apply eqb_neq; auto.
Qed.
*)
Example test_nostutter_3: nostutter [5].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(*
Proof. repeat constructor; apply eqb_false; auto. Qed.
*)
Example test_nostutter_4: not (nostutter [3;1;1;4]).
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(*
Proof. intro.
repeat match goal with
h: nostutter _ |- _ => inversion h; clear h; subst
end.
contradiction Hneq0; auto. Qed.
*)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_nostutter : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced (filter_challenge)
Let's prove that our definition of [filter] from the [Poly]
chapter matches an abstract specification. Here is the
specification, written out informally in English:
A list [l] is an "in-order merge" of [l1] and [l2] if it contains
all the same elements as [l1] and [l2], in the same order as [l1]
and [l2], but possibly interleaved. For example,
[1;4;6;2;3]
is an in-order merge of
[1;6;2]
and
[4;3].
Now, suppose we have a set [X], a function [test: X->bool], and a
list [l] of type [list X]. Suppose further that [l] is an
in-order merge of two lists, [l1] and [l2], such that every item
in [l1] satisfies [test] and no item in [l2] satisfies test. Then
[filter test l = l1].
Translate this specification into a Coq theorem and prove
it. (You'll need to begin by defining what it means for one list
to be a merge of two others. Do this with an inductive relation,
not a [Fixpoint].) *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_filter_challenge : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, advanced, optional (filter_challenge_2)
A different way to characterize the behavior of [filter] goes like
this: Among all subsequences of [l] with the property that [test]
evaluates to [true] on all their members, [filter test l] is the
longest. Formalize this claim and prove it. *)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard, optional (palindromes)
A palindrome is a sequence that reads the same backwards as
forwards.
- Define an inductive proposition [pal] on [list X] that
captures what it means to be a palindrome. (Hint: You'll need
three cases. Your definition should be based on the structure
of the list; just having a single constructor like
c : forall l, l = rev l -> pal l
may seem obvious, but will not work very well.)
- Prove ([pal_app_rev]) that
forall l, pal (l ++ rev l).
- Prove ([pal_rev] that)
forall l, pal l -> l = rev l.
*)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_pal_pal_app_rev_pal_rev : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, standard, optional (palindrome_converse)
Again, the converse direction is significantly more difficult, due
to the lack of evidence. Using your definition of [pal] from the
previous exercise, prove that
forall l, l = rev l -> pal l.
*)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced, optional (NoDup)
Recall the definition of the [In] property from the [Logic]
chapter, which asserts that a value [x] appears at least once in a
list [l]: *)
(* Fixpoint In (A : Type) (x : A) (l : list A) : Prop :=
match l with
| [] => False
| x' :: l' => x' = x \/ In A x l'
end *)
(** Your first task is to use [In] to define a proposition [disjoint X
l1 l2], which should be provable exactly when [l1] and [l2] are
lists (with elements of type X) that have no elements in
common. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** Next, use [In] to define an inductive proposition [NoDup X
l], which should be provable exactly when [l] is a list (with
elements of type [X]) where every member is different from every
other. For example, [NoDup nat [1;2;3;4]] and [NoDup
bool []] should be provable, while [NoDup nat [1;2;1]] and
[NoDup bool [true;true]] should not be. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** Finally, state and prove one or more interesting theorems relating
[disjoint], [NoDup] and [++] (list append). *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_NoDup_disjoint_etc : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, advanced, optional (pigeonhole_principle)
The _pigeonhole principle_ states a basic fact about counting: if
we distribute more than [n] items into [n] pigeonholes, some
pigeonhole must contain at least two items. As often happens, this
apparently trivial fact about numbers requires non-trivial
machinery to prove, but we now have enough... *)
(** First prove an easy useful lemma. *)
Lemma in_split : forall (X:Type) (x:X) (l:list X),
In x l ->
exists l1 l2, l = l1 ++ x :: l2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Now define a property [repeats] such that [repeats X l] asserts
that [l] contains at least one repeated element (of type [X]). *)
Inductive repeats {X:Type} : list X -> Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
(** Now, here's a way to formalize the pigeonhole principle. Suppose
list [l2] represents a list of pigeonhole labels, and list [l1]
represents the labels assigned to a list of items. If there are
more items than labels, at least two items must have the same
label -- i.e., list [l1] must contain repeats.
This proof is much easier if you use the [excluded_middle]
hypothesis to show that [In] is decidable, i.e., [forall x l, (In x
l) \/ ~ (In x l)]. However, it is also possible to make the proof
go through _without_ assuming that [In] is decidable; if you
manage to do this, you will not need the [excluded_middle]
hypothesis. *)
Theorem pigeonhole_principle: forall (X:Type) (l1 l2:list X),
excluded_middle ->
(forall x, In x l1 -> In x l2) ->
length l2 < length l1 ->
repeats l1.
Proof.
intros X l1. induction l1 as [|x l1' IHl1'].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_check_repeats : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Extended Exercise: A Verified Regular-Expression Matcher *)
(** We have now defined a match relation over regular expressions and
polymorphic lists. We can use such a definition to manually prove that
a given regex matches a given string, but it does not give us a
program that we can run to determine a match autmatically.
It would be reasonable to hope that we can translate the definitions
of the inductive rules for constructing evidence of the match relation
into cases of a recursive function reflects the relation by recursing
on a given regex. However, it does not seem straightforward to define
such a function in which the given regex is a recursion variable
recognized by Coq. As a result, Coq will not accept that the function
always terminates.
Heavily-optimized regex matchers match a regex by translating a given
regex into a state machine and determining if the state machine
accepts a given string. However, regex matching can also be
implemented using an algorithm that operates purely on strings and
regexes without defining and maintaining additional datatypes, such as
state machines. We'll implemement such an algorithm, and verify that
its value reflects the match relation. *)
(** We will implement a regex matcher that matches strings represented
as lists of ASCII characters: *)
Require Export Coq.Strings.Ascii.
Definition string := list ascii.
(** The Coq standard library contains a distinct inductive definition
of strings of ASCII characters. However, we will use the above
definition of strings as lists as ASCII characters in order to apply
the existing definition of the match relation.
We could also define a regex matcher over polymorphic lists, not lists
of ASCII characters specifically. The matching algorithm that we will
implement needs to be able to test equality of elements in a given
list, and thus needs to be given an equality-testing
function. Generalizing the definitions, theorems, and proofs that we
define for such a setting is a bit tedious, but workable. *)
(** The proof of correctness of the regex matcher will combine
properties of the regex-matching function with properties of the
[match] relation that do not depend on the matching function. We'll go
ahead and prove the latter class of properties now. Most of them have
straightforward proofs, which have been given to you, although there
are a few key lemmas that are left for you to prove. *)
(** Each provable [Prop] is equivalent to [True]. *)
Lemma provable_equiv_true : forall (P : Prop), P -> (P <-> True).
Proof.
intros.
split.
- intros. constructor.
- intros _. apply H.
Qed.
(** Each [Prop] whose negation is provable is equivalent to [False]. *)
Lemma not_equiv_false : forall (P : Prop), ~P -> (P <-> False).
Proof.
intros.
split.
- apply H.
- intros. destruct H0.
Qed.
(** [EmptySet] matches no string. *)
Lemma null_matches_none : forall (s : string), (s =~ EmptySet) <-> False.
Proof.
intros.
apply not_equiv_false.
unfold not. intros. inversion H.
Qed.
(** [EmptyStr] only matches the empty string. *)
Lemma empty_matches_eps : forall (s : string), s =~ EmptyStr <-> s = [ ].
Proof.
split.
- intros. inversion H. reflexivity.
- intros. rewrite H. apply MEmpty.
Qed.
(** [EmptyStr] matches no non-empty string. *)
Lemma empty_nomatch_ne : forall (a : ascii) s, (a :: s =~ EmptyStr) <-> False.
Proof.
intros.
apply not_equiv_false.
unfold not. intros. inversion H.
Qed.
(** [Char a] matches no string that starts with a non-[a] character. *)
Lemma char_nomatch_char :
forall (a b : ascii) s, b <> a -> (b :: s =~ Char a <-> False).
Proof.
intros.
apply not_equiv_false.
unfold not.
intros.
apply H.
inversion H0.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** If [Char a] matches a non-empty string, then the string's tail is empty. *)
Lemma char_eps_suffix : forall (a : ascii) s, a :: s =~ Char a <-> s = [ ].
Proof.
split.
- intros. inversion H. reflexivity.
- intros. rewrite H. apply MChar.
Qed.
(** [App re0 re1] matches string [s] iff [s = s0 ++ s1], where [s0]
matches [re0] and [s1] matches [re1]. *)
Lemma app_exists : forall (s : string) re0 re1,
s =~ App re0 re1 <->
exists s0 s1, s = s0 ++ s1 /\ s0 =~ re0 /\ s1 =~ re1.
Proof.
intros.
split.
- intros. inversion H. exists s1, s2. split.
* reflexivity.
* split. apply H3. apply H4.
- intros [ s0 [ s1 [ Happ [ Hmat0 Hmat1 ] ] ] ].
rewrite Happ. apply (MApp s0 _ s1 _ Hmat0 Hmat1).
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (app_ne)
[App re0 re1] matches [a::s] iff [re0] matches the empty string
and [a::s] matches [re1] or [s=s0++s1], where [a::s0] matches [re0]
and [s1] matches [re1].
Even though this is a property of purely the match relation, it is a
critical observation behind the design of our regex matcher. So (1)
take time to understand it, (2) prove it, and (3) look for how you'll
use it later. *)
Lemma app_ne : forall (a : ascii) s re0 re1,
a :: s =~ (App re0 re1) <->
([ ] =~ re0 /\ a :: s =~ re1) \/
exists s0 s1, s = s0 ++ s1 /\ a :: s0 =~ re0 /\ s1 =~ re1.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** [s] matches [Union re0 re1] iff [s] matches [re0] or [s] matches [re1]. *)
Lemma union_disj : forall (s : string) re0 re1,
s =~ Union re0 re1 <-> s =~ re0 \/ s =~ re1.
Proof.
intros. split.
- intros. inversion H.
+ left. apply H2.
+ right. apply H1.
- intros [ H | H ].
+ apply MUnionL. apply H.
+ apply MUnionR. apply H.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (star_ne)
[a::s] matches [Star re] iff [s = s0 ++ s1], where [a::s0] matches
[re] and [s1] matches [Star re]. Like [app_ne], this observation is
critical, so understand it, prove it, and keep it in mind.
Hint: you'll need to perform induction. There are quite a few
reasonable candidates for [Prop]'s to prove by induction. The only one
that will work is splitting the [iff] into two implications and
proving one by induction on the evidence for [a :: s =~ Star re]. The
other implication can be proved without induction.
In order to prove the right property by induction, you'll need to
rephrase [a :: s =~ Star re] to be a [Prop] over general variables,
using the [remember] tactic. *)
Lemma star_ne : forall (a : ascii) s re,
a :: s =~ Star re <->
exists s0 s1, s = s0 ++ s1 /\ a :: s0 =~ re /\ s1 =~ Star re.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** The definition of our regex matcher will include two fixpoint
functions. The first function, given regex [re], will evaluate to a
value that reflects whether [re] matches the empty string. The
function will satisfy the following property: *)
Definition refl_matches_eps m :=
forall re : @reg_exp ascii, reflect ([ ] =~ re) (m re).
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (match_eps)
Complete the definition of [match_eps] so that it tests if a given
regex matches the empty string: *)
Fixpoint match_eps (re: @reg_exp ascii) : bool
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (match_eps_refl)
Now, prove that [match_eps] indeed tests if a given regex matches
the empty string. (Hint: You'll want to use the reflection lemmas
[ReflectT] and [ReflectF].) *)
Lemma match_eps_refl : refl_matches_eps match_eps.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** We'll define other functions that use [match_eps]. However, the
only property of [match_eps] that you'll need to use in all proofs
over these functions is [match_eps_refl]. *)
(** The key operation that will be performed by our regex matcher will
be to iteratively construct a sequence of regex derivatives. For each
character [a] and regex [re], the derivative of [re] on [a] is a regex
that matches all suffixes of strings matched by [re] that start with
[a]. I.e., [re'] is a derivative of [re] on [a] if they satisfy the
following relation: *)
Definition is_der re (a : ascii) re' :=
forall s, a :: s =~ re <-> s =~ re'.
(** A function [d] derives strings if, given character [a] and regex
[re], it evaluates to the derivative of [re] on [a]. I.e., [d]
satisfies the following property: *)
Definition derives d := forall a re, is_der re a (d a re).
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (derive)
Define [derive] so that it derives strings. One natural
implementation uses [match_eps] in some cases to determine if key
regex's match the empty string. *)
Fixpoint derive (a : ascii) (re : @reg_exp ascii) : @reg_exp ascii
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** The [derive] function should pass the following tests. Each test
establishes an equality between an expression that will be
evaluated by our regex matcher and the final value that must be
returned by the regex matcher. Each test is annotated with the
match fact that it reflects. *)
Example c := ascii_of_nat 99.
Example d := ascii_of_nat 100.
(** "c" =~ EmptySet: *)
Example test_der0 : match_eps (derive c (EmptySet)) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "c" =~ Char c: *)
Example test_der1 : match_eps (derive c (Char c)) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "c" =~ Char d: *)
Example test_der2 : match_eps (derive c (Char d)) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "c" =~ App (Char c) EmptyStr: *)
Example test_der3 : match_eps (derive c (App (Char c) EmptyStr)) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "c" =~ App EmptyStr (Char c): *)
Example test_der4 : match_eps (derive c (App EmptyStr (Char c))) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "c" =~ Star c: *)
Example test_der5 : match_eps (derive c (Star (Char c))) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "cd" =~ App (Char c) (Char d): *)
Example test_der6 :
match_eps (derive d (derive c (App (Char c) (Char d)))) = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** "cd" =~ App (Char d) (Char c): *)
Example test_der7 :
match_eps (derive d (derive c (App (Char d) (Char c)))) = false.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard, optional (derive_corr)
Prove that [derive] in fact always derives strings.
Hint: one proof performs induction on [re], although you'll need
to carefully choose the property that you prove by induction by
generalizing the appropriate terms.
Hint: if your definition of [derive] applies [match_eps] to a
particular regex [re], then a natural proof will apply
[match_eps_refl] to [re] and destruct the result to generate cases
with assumptions that the [re] does or does not match the empty
string.
Hint: You can save quite a bit of work by using lemmas proved
above. In particular, to prove many cases of the induction, you
can rewrite a [Prop] over a complicated regex (e.g., [s =~ Union
re0 re1]) to a Boolean combination of [Prop]'s over simple
regex's (e.g., [s =~ re0 \/ s =~ re1]) using lemmas given above
that are logical equivalences. You can then reason about these
[Prop]'s naturally using [intro] and [destruct]. *)
Lemma derive_corr : derives derive.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** We'll define the regex matcher using [derive]. However, the only
property of [derive] that you'll need to use in all proofs of
properties of the matcher is [derive_corr]. *)
(** A function [m] matches regexes if, given string [s] and regex [re],
it evaluates to a value that reflects whether [s] is matched by
[re]. I.e., [m] holds the following property: *)
Definition matches_regex m : Prop :=
forall (s : string) re, reflect (s =~ re) (m s re).
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (regex_match)
Complete the definition of [regex_match] so that it matches
regexes. *)
Fixpoint regex_match (s : string) (re : @reg_exp ascii) : bool
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (regex_refl)
Finally, prove that [regex_match] in fact matches regexes.
Hint: if your definition of [regex_match] applies [match_eps] to
regex [re], then a natural proof applies [match_eps_refl] to [re]
and destructs the result to generate cases in which you may assume
that [re] does or does not match the empty string.
Hint: if your definition of [regex_match] applies [derive] to
character [x] and regex [re], then a natural proof applies
[derive_corr] to [x] and [re] to prove that [x :: s =~ re] given
[s =~ derive x re], and vice versa. *)
Theorem regex_refl : matches_regex regex_match.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* Wed Jan 9 12:02:45 EST 2019 *)