logical-foundations/Logic.v
2020-06-03 21:46:06 -05:00

1603 lines
53 KiB
Coq

(** * Logic: Logic in Coq *)
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing".
From LF Require Export Tactics.
(** In previous chapters, we have seen many examples of factual
claims (_propositions_) and ways of presenting evidence of their
truth (_proofs_). In particular, we have worked extensively with
_equality propositions_ of the form [e1 = e2], with
implications ([P -> Q]), and with quantified propositions ([forall
x, P]). In this chapter, we will see how Coq can be used to carry
out other familiar forms of logical reasoning.
Before diving into details, let's talk a bit about the status of
mathematical statements in Coq. Recall that Coq is a _typed_
language, which means that every sensible expression in its world
has an associated type. Logical claims are no exception: any
statement we might try to prove in Coq has a type, namely [Prop],
the type of _propositions_. We can see this with the [Check]
command: *)
Check 3 = 3.
(* ===> Prop *)
Check forall n m : nat, n + m = m + n.
(* ===> Prop *)
(** Note that _all_ syntactically well-formed propositions have type
[Prop] in Coq, regardless of whether they are true. *)
(** Simply _being_ a proposition is one thing; being _provable_ is
something else! *)
Check 2 = 2.
(* ===> Prop *)
Check forall n : nat, n = 2.
(* ===> Prop *)
Check 3 = 4.
(* ===> Prop *)
(** Indeed, propositions don't just have types: they are
_first-class objects_ that can be manipulated in the same ways as
the other entities in Coq's world. *)
(** So far, we've seen one primary place that propositions can appear:
in [Theorem] (and [Lemma] and [Example]) declarations. *)
Theorem plus_2_2_is_4 :
2 + 2 = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** But propositions can be used in many other ways. For example, we
can give a name to a proposition using a [Definition], just as we
have given names to expressions of other sorts. *)
Definition plus_fact : Prop := 2 + 2 = 4.
Check plus_fact.
(* ===> plus_fact : Prop *)
(** We can later use this name in any situation where a proposition is
expected -- for example, as the claim in a [Theorem] declaration. *)
Theorem plus_fact_is_true :
plus_fact.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** We can also write _parameterized_ propositions -- that is,
functions that take arguments of some type and return a
proposition. *)
(** For instance, the following function takes a number
and returns a proposition asserting that this number is equal to
three: *)
Definition is_three (n : nat) : Prop :=
n = 3.
Check is_three.
(* ===> nat -> Prop *)
(** In Coq, functions that return propositions are said to define
_properties_ of their arguments.
For instance, here's a (polymorphic) property defining the
familiar notion of an _injective function_. *)
Definition injective {A B} (f : A -> B) :=
forall x y : A, f x = f y -> x = y.
Lemma succ_inj : injective S.
Proof.
intros n m H. injection H as H1. apply H1.
Qed.
(** The equality operator [=] is also a function that returns a
[Prop].
The expression [n = m] is syntactic sugar for [eq n m] (defined
using Coq's [Notation] mechanism). Because [eq] can be used with
elements of any type, it is also polymorphic: *)
Check @eq.
(* ===> forall A : Type, A -> A -> Prop *)
(** (Notice that we wrote [@eq] instead of [eq]: The type
argument [A] to [eq] is declared as implicit, so we need to turn
off implicit arguments to see the full type of [eq].) *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Logical Connectives *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Conjunction *)
(** The _conjunction_, or _logical and_, of propositions [A] and [B]
is written [A /\ B], representing the claim that both [A] and [B]
are true. *)
Example and_example : 3 + 4 = 7 /\ 2 * 2 = 4.
(** To prove a conjunction, use the [split] tactic. It will generate
two subgoals, one for each part of the statement: *)
Proof.
split.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 + 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(** For any propositions [A] and [B], if we assume that [A] is true
and we assume that [B] is true, we can conclude that [A /\ B] is
also true. *)
Lemma and_intro : forall A B : Prop, A -> B -> A /\ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA HB. split.
- apply HA.
- apply HB.
Qed.
(** Since applying a theorem with hypotheses to some goal has the
effect of generating as many subgoals as there are hypotheses for
that theorem, we can apply [and_intro] to achieve the same effect
as [split]. *)
Example and_example' : 3 + 4 = 7 /\ 2 * 2 = 4.
Proof.
apply and_intro.
- (* 3 + 4 = 7 *) reflexivity.
- (* 2 + 2 = 4 *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (and_exercise) *)
Example and_exercise :
forall n m : nat, n + m = 0 -> n = 0 /\ m = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** So much for proving conjunctive statements. To go in the other
direction -- i.e., to _use_ a conjunctive hypothesis to help prove
something else -- we employ the [destruct] tactic.
If the proof context contains a hypothesis [H] of the form
[A /\ B], writing [destruct H as [HA HB]] will remove [H] from the
context and add two new hypotheses: [HA], stating that [A] is
true, and [HB], stating that [B] is true. *)
Lemma and_example2 :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 /\ m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n m H.
destruct H as [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** As usual, we can also destruct [H] right when we introduce it,
instead of introducing and then destructing it: *)
Lemma and_example2' :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 /\ m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** You may wonder why we bothered packing the two hypotheses [n = 0]
and [m = 0] into a single conjunction, since we could have also
stated the theorem with two separate premises: *)
Lemma and_example2'' :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 -> m = 0 -> n + m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m Hn Hm.
rewrite Hn. rewrite Hm.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** For this theorem, both formulations are fine. But it's important
to understand how to work with conjunctive hypotheses because
conjunctions often arise from intermediate steps in proofs,
especially in bigger developments. Here's a simple example: *)
Lemma and_example3 :
forall n m : nat, n + m = 0 -> n * m = 0.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n m H.
assert (H' : n = 0 /\ m = 0).
{ apply and_exercise. apply H. }
destruct H' as [Hn Hm].
rewrite Hn. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Another common situation with conjunctions is that we know
[A /\ B] but in some context we need just [A] (or just [B]).
The following lemmas are useful in such cases: *)
Lemma proj1 : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> P.
Proof.
intros P Q [HP HQ].
apply HP. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (proj2) *)
Lemma proj2 : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> Q.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Finally, we sometimes need to rearrange the order of conjunctions
and/or the grouping of multi-way conjunctions. The following
commutativity and associativity theorems are handy in such
cases. *)
Theorem and_commut : forall P Q : Prop,
P /\ Q -> Q /\ P.
Proof.
intros P Q [HP HQ].
split.
- (* left *) apply HQ.
- (* right *) apply HP. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (and_assoc)
(In the following proof of associativity, notice how the _nested_
[intros] pattern breaks the hypothesis [H : P /\ (Q /\ R)] down into
[HP : P], [HQ : Q], and [HR : R]. Finish the proof from
there.) *)
Theorem and_assoc : forall P Q R : Prop,
P /\ (Q /\ R) -> (P /\ Q) /\ R.
Proof.
intros P Q R [HP [HQ HR]].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** By the way, the infix notation [/\] is actually just syntactic
sugar for [and A B]. That is, [and] is a Coq operator that takes
two propositions as arguments and yields a proposition. *)
Check and.
(* ===> and : Prop -> Prop -> Prop *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Disjunction *)
(** Another important connective is the _disjunction_, or _logical or_,
of two propositions: [A \/ B] is true when either [A] or [B]
is. (This infix notation stands for [or A B], where [or : Prop ->
Prop -> Prop].) *)
(** To use a disjunctive hypothesis in a proof, we proceed by case
analysis, which, as for [nat] or other data types, can be done
explicitly with [destruct] or implicitly with an [intros] pattern: *)
Lemma or_example :
forall n m : nat, n = 0 \/ m = 0 -> n * m = 0.
Proof.
(* This pattern implicitly does case analysis on
[n = 0 \/ m = 0] *)
intros n m [Hn | Hm].
- (* Here, [n = 0] *)
rewrite Hn. reflexivity.
- (* Here, [m = 0] *)
rewrite Hm. rewrite <- mult_n_O.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Conversely, to show that a disjunction holds, we need to show that
one of its sides does. This is done via two tactics, [left] and
[right]. As their names imply, the first one requires
proving the left side of the disjunction, while the second
requires proving its right side. Here is a trivial use... *)
Lemma or_intro : forall A B : Prop, A -> A \/ B.
Proof.
intros A B HA.
left.
apply HA.
Qed.
(** ... and here is a slightly more interesting example requiring both
[left] and [right]: *)
Lemma zero_or_succ :
forall n : nat, n = 0 \/ n = S (pred n).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros [|n].
- left. reflexivity.
- right. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (mult_eq_0) *)
Lemma mult_eq_0 :
forall n m, n * m = 0 -> n = 0 \/ m = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (or_commut) *)
Theorem or_commut : forall P Q : Prop,
P \/ Q -> Q \/ P.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Falsehood and Negation
So far, we have mostly been concerned with proving that certain
things are _true_ -- addition is commutative, appending lists is
associative, etc. Of course, we may also be interested in
negative results, showing that some given proposition is _not_
true. In Coq, such statements are expressed with the negation
operator [~]. *)
(** To see how negation works, recall the _principle of explosion_
from the [Tactics] chapter; it asserts that, if we assume a
contradiction, then any other proposition can be derived.
Following this intuition, we could define [~ P] ("not [P]") as
[forall Q, P -> Q].
Coq actually makes a slightly different (but equivalent) choice,
defining [~ P] as [P -> False], where [False] is a specific
contradictory proposition defined in the standard library. *)
Module MyNot.
Definition not (P:Prop) := P -> False.
Notation "~ x" := (not x) : type_scope.
Check not.
(* ===> Prop -> Prop *)
End MyNot.
(** Since [False] is a contradictory proposition, the principle of
explosion also applies to it. If we get [False] into the proof
context, we can use [destruct] on it to complete any goal: *)
Theorem ex_falso_quodlibet : forall (P:Prop),
False -> P.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P contra.
destruct contra. Qed.
(** The Latin _ex falso quodlibet_ means, literally, "from falsehood
follows whatever you like"; this is another common name for the
principle of explosion. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (not_implies_our_not)
Show that Coq's definition of negation implies the intuitive one
mentioned above: *)
Fact not_implies_our_not : forall (P:Prop),
~ P -> (forall (Q:Prop), P -> Q).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Inequality is a frequent enough example of negated statement
that there is a special notation for it, [x <> y]:
Notation "x <> y" := (~(x = y)).
*)
(** We can use [not] to state that [0] and [1] are different elements
of [nat]: *)
Theorem zero_not_one : 0 <> 1.
Proof.
(** The proposition [0 <> 1] is exactly the same as
[~(0 = 1)], that is [not (0 = 1)], which unfolds to
[(0 = 1) -> False]. (We use [unfold not] explicitly here
to illustrate that point, but generally it can be omitted.) *)
unfold not.
(** To prove an inequality, we may assume the opposite
equality... *)
intros contra.
(** ... and deduce a contradiction from it. Here, the
equality [O = S O] contradicts the disjointness of
constructors [O] and [S], so [discriminate] takes care
of it. *)
discriminate contra.
Qed.
(** It takes a little practice to get used to working with negation in
Coq. Even though you can see perfectly well why a statement
involving negation is true, it can be a little tricky at first to
get things into the right configuration so that Coq can understand
it! Here are proofs of a few familiar facts to get you warmed
up. *)
Theorem not_False :
~ False.
Proof.
unfold not. intros H. destruct H. Qed.
Theorem contradiction_implies_anything : forall P Q : Prop,
(P /\ ~P) -> Q.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P Q [HP HNA]. unfold not in HNA.
apply HNA in HP. destruct HP. Qed.
Theorem double_neg : forall P : Prop,
P -> ~~P.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P H. unfold not. intros G. apply G. apply H. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (double_neg_inf)
Write an informal proof of [double_neg]:
_Theorem_: [P] implies [~~P], for any proposition [P]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_double_neg_inf : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, recommended (contrapositive) *)
Theorem contrapositive : forall (P Q : Prop),
(P -> Q) -> (~Q -> ~P).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (not_both_true_and_false) *)
Theorem not_both_true_and_false : forall P : Prop,
~ (P /\ ~P).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, advanced (informal_not_PNP)
Write an informal proof (in English) of the proposition [forall P
: Prop, ~(P /\ ~P)]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(* Do not modify the following line: *)
Definition manual_grade_for_informal_not_PNP : option (nat*string) := None.
(** [] *)
(** Similarly, since inequality involves a negation, it requires a
little practice to be able to work with it fluently. Here is one
useful trick. If you are trying to prove a goal that is
nonsensical (e.g., the goal state is [false = true]), apply
[ex_falso_quodlibet] to change the goal to [False]. This makes it
easier to use assumptions of the form [~P] that may be available
in the context -- in particular, assumptions of the form
[x<>y]. *)
Theorem not_true_is_false : forall b : bool,
b <> true -> b = false.
Proof.
intros [] H.
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet.
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Since reasoning with [ex_falso_quodlibet] is quite common, Coq
provides a built-in tactic, [exfalso], for applying it. *)
Theorem not_true_is_false' : forall b : bool,
b <> true -> b = false.
Proof.
intros [] H.
- (* b = true *)
unfold not in H.
exfalso. (* <=== *)
apply H. reflexivity.
- (* b = false *) reflexivity.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Truth *)
(** Besides [False], Coq's standard library also defines [True], a
proposition that is trivially true. To prove it, we use the
predefined constant [I : True]: *)
Lemma True_is_true : True.
Proof. apply I. Qed.
(** Unlike [False], which is used extensively, [True] is used quite
rarely, since it is trivial (and therefore uninteresting) to prove
as a goal, and it carries no useful information as a hypothesis.
But it can be quite useful when defining complex [Prop]s using
conditionals or as a parameter to higher-order [Prop]s.
We will see examples of such uses of [True] later on. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Logical Equivalence *)
(** The handy "if and only if" connective, which asserts that two
propositions have the same truth value, is just the conjunction of
two implications. *)
Module MyIff.
Definition iff (P Q : Prop) := (P -> Q) /\ (Q -> P).
Notation "P <-> Q" := (iff P Q)
(at level 95, no associativity)
: type_scope.
End MyIff.
Theorem iff_sym : forall P Q : Prop,
(P <-> Q) -> (Q <-> P).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros P Q [HAB HBA].
split.
- (* -> *) apply HBA.
- (* <- *) apply HAB. Qed.
Lemma not_true_iff_false : forall b,
b <> true <-> b = false.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros b. split.
- (* -> *) apply not_true_is_false.
- (* <- *)
intros H. rewrite H. intros H'. discriminate H'.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (iff_properties)
Using the above proof that [<->] is symmetric ([iff_sym]) as
a guide, prove that it is also reflexive and transitive. *)
Theorem iff_refl : forall P : Prop,
P <-> P.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem iff_trans : forall P Q R : Prop,
(P <-> Q) -> (Q <-> R) -> (P <-> R).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (or_distributes_over_and) *)
Theorem or_distributes_over_and : forall P Q R : Prop,
P \/ (Q /\ R) <-> (P \/ Q) /\ (P \/ R).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** Some of Coq's tactics treat [iff] statements specially, avoiding
the need for some low-level proof-state manipulation. In
particular, [rewrite] and [reflexivity] can be used with [iff]
statements, not just equalities. To enable this behavior, we need
to import a Coq library that supports it: *)
From Coq Require Import Setoids.Setoid.
(** Here is a simple example demonstrating how these tactics work with
[iff]. First, let's prove a couple of basic iff equivalences... *)
Lemma mult_0 : forall n m, n * m = 0 <-> n = 0 \/ m = 0.
Proof.
split.
- apply mult_eq_0.
- apply or_example.
Qed.
Lemma or_assoc :
forall P Q R : Prop, P \/ (Q \/ R) <-> (P \/ Q) \/ R.
Proof.
intros P Q R. split.
- intros [H | [H | H]].
+ left. left. apply H.
+ left. right. apply H.
+ right. apply H.
- intros [[H | H] | H].
+ left. apply H.
+ right. left. apply H.
+ right. right. apply H.
Qed.
(** We can now use these facts with [rewrite] and [reflexivity] to
give smooth proofs of statements involving equivalences. Here is
a ternary version of the previous [mult_0] result: *)
Lemma mult_0_3 :
forall n m p, n * m * p = 0 <-> n = 0 \/ m = 0 \/ p = 0.
Proof.
intros n m p.
rewrite mult_0. rewrite mult_0. rewrite or_assoc.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** The [apply] tactic can also be used with [<->]. When given an
equivalence as its argument, [apply] tries to guess which side of
the equivalence to use. *)
Lemma apply_iff_example :
forall n m : nat, n * m = 0 -> n = 0 \/ m = 0.
Proof.
intros n m H. apply mult_0. apply H.
Qed.
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Existential Quantification *)
(** Another important logical connective is _existential
quantification_. To say that there is some [x] of type [T] such
that some property [P] holds of [x], we write [exists x : T,
P]. As with [forall], the type annotation [: T] can be omitted if
Coq is able to infer from the context what the type of [x] should
be. *)
(** To prove a statement of the form [exists x, P], we must show that
[P] holds for some specific choice of value for [x], known as the
_witness_ of the existential. This is done in two steps: First,
we explicitly tell Coq which witness [t] we have in mind by
invoking the tactic [exists t]. Then we prove that [P] holds after
all occurrences of [x] are replaced by [t]. *)
Lemma four_is_even : exists n : nat, 4 = n + n.
Proof.
exists 2. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Conversely, if we have an existential hypothesis [exists x, P] in
the context, we can destruct it to obtain a witness [x] and a
hypothesis stating that [P] holds of [x]. *)
Theorem exists_example_2 : forall n,
(exists m, n = 4 + m) ->
(exists o, n = 2 + o).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n [m Hm]. (* note implicit [destruct] here *)
exists (2 + m).
apply Hm. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard, recommended (dist_not_exists)
Prove that "[P] holds for all [x]" implies "there is no [x] for
which [P] does not hold." (Hint: [destruct H as [x E]] works on
existential assumptions!) *)
Theorem dist_not_exists : forall (X:Type) (P : X -> Prop),
(forall x, P x) -> ~ (exists x, ~ P x).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (dist_exists_or)
Prove that existential quantification distributes over
disjunction. *)
Theorem dist_exists_or : forall (X:Type) (P Q : X -> Prop),
(exists x, P x \/ Q x) <-> (exists x, P x) \/ (exists x, Q x).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Programming with Propositions *)
(** The logical connectives that we have seen provide a rich
vocabulary for defining complex propositions from simpler ones.
To illustrate, let's look at how to express the claim that an
element [x] occurs in a list [l]. Notice that this property has a
simple recursive structure:
- If [l] is the empty list, then [x] cannot occur on it, so the
property "[x] appears in [l]" is simply false.
- Otherwise, [l] has the form [x' :: l']. In this case, [x]
occurs in [l] if either it is equal to [x'] or it occurs in
[l']. *)
(** We can translate this directly into a straightforward recursive
function taking an element and a list and returning a proposition: *)
Fixpoint In {A : Type} (x : A) (l : list A) : Prop :=
match l with
| [] => False
| x' :: l' => x' = x \/ In x l'
end.
(** When [In] is applied to a concrete list, it expands into a
concrete sequence of nested disjunctions. *)
Example In_example_1 : In 4 [1; 2; 3; 4; 5].
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
simpl. right. right. right. left. reflexivity.
Qed.
Example In_example_2 :
forall n, In n [2; 4] ->
exists n', n = 2 * n'.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
simpl.
intros n [H | [H | []]].
- exists 1. rewrite <- H. reflexivity.
- exists 2. rewrite <- H. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** (Notice the use of the empty pattern to discharge the last case
_en passant_.) *)
(** We can also prove more generic, higher-level lemmas about [In].
Note, in the next, how [In] starts out applied to a variable and
only gets expanded when we do case analysis on this variable: *)
Lemma In_map :
forall (A B : Type) (f : A -> B) (l : list A) (x : A),
In x l ->
In (f x) (map f l).
Proof.
intros A B f l x.
induction l as [|x' l' IHl'].
- (* l = nil, contradiction *)
simpl. intros [].
- (* l = x' :: l' *)
simpl. intros [H | H].
+ rewrite H. left. reflexivity.
+ right. apply IHl'. apply H.
Qed.
(** This way of defining propositions recursively, though convenient
in some cases, also has some drawbacks. In particular, it is
subject to Coq's usual restrictions regarding the definition of
recursive functions, e.g., the requirement that they be "obviously
terminating." In the next chapter, we will see how to define
propositions _inductively_, a different technique with its own set
of strengths and limitations. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (In_map_iff) *)
Lemma In_map_iff :
forall (A B : Type) (f : A -> B) (l : list A) (y : B),
In y (map f l) <->
exists x, f x = y /\ In x l.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (In_app_iff) *)
Lemma In_app_iff : forall A l l' (a:A),
In a (l++l') <-> In a l \/ In a l'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard, recommended (All)
Recall that functions returning propositions can be seen as
_properties_ of their arguments. For instance, if [P] has type
[nat -> Prop], then [P n] states that property [P] holds of [n].
Drawing inspiration from [In], write a recursive function [All]
stating that some property [P] holds of all elements of a list
[l]. To make sure your definition is correct, prove the [All_In]
lemma below. (Of course, your definition should _not_ just
restate the left-hand side of [All_In].) *)
Fixpoint All {T : Type} (P : T -> Prop) (l : list T) : Prop
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Lemma All_In :
forall T (P : T -> Prop) (l : list T),
(forall x, In x l -> P x) <->
All P l.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (combine_odd_even)
Complete the definition of the [combine_odd_even] function below.
It takes as arguments two properties of numbers, [Podd] and
[Peven], and it should return a property [P] such that [P n] is
equivalent to [Podd n] when [n] is odd and equivalent to [Peven n]
otherwise. *)
Definition combine_odd_even (Podd Peven : nat -> Prop) : nat -> Prop
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
(** To test your definition, prove the following facts: *)
Theorem combine_odd_even_intro :
forall (Podd Peven : nat -> Prop) (n : nat),
(oddb n = true -> Podd n) ->
(oddb n = false -> Peven n) ->
combine_odd_even Podd Peven n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem combine_odd_even_elim_odd :
forall (Podd Peven : nat -> Prop) (n : nat),
combine_odd_even Podd Peven n ->
oddb n = true ->
Podd n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem combine_odd_even_elim_even :
forall (Podd Peven : nat -> Prop) (n : nat),
combine_odd_even Podd Peven n ->
oddb n = false ->
Peven n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Applying Theorems to Arguments *)
(** One feature of Coq that distinguishes it from some other
popular proof assistants (e.g., ACL2 and Isabelle) is that it
treats _proofs_ as first-class objects.
There is a great deal to be said about this, but it is not
necessary to understand it all in detail in order to use Coq. This
section gives just a taste, while a deeper exploration can be
found in the optional chapters [ProofObjects] and
[IndPrinciples]. *)
(** We have seen that we can use the [Check] command to ask Coq to
print the type of an expression. We can also use [Check] to ask
what theorem a particular identifier refers to. *)
Check plus_comm.
(* ===> forall n m : nat, n + m = m + n *)
(** Coq prints the _statement_ of the [plus_comm] theorem in the same
way that it prints the _type_ of any term that we ask it to
[Check]. Why? *)
(** The reason is that the identifier [plus_comm] actually refers to a
_proof object_ -- a data structure that represents a logical
derivation establishing of the truth of the statement [forall n m
: nat, n + m = m + n]. The type of this object _is_ the statement
of the theorem that it is a proof of. *)
(** Intuitively, this makes sense because the statement of a theorem
tells us what we can use that theorem for, just as the type of a
computational object tells us what we can do with that object --
e.g., if we have a term of type [nat -> nat -> nat], we can give
it two [nat]s as arguments and get a [nat] back. Similarly, if we
have an object of type [n = m -> n + n = m + m] and we provide it
an "argument" of type [n = m], we can derive [n + n = m + m]. *)
(** Operationally, this analogy goes even further: by applying a
theorem, as if it were a function, to hypotheses with matching
types, we can specialize its result without having to resort to
intermediate assertions. For example, suppose we wanted to prove
the following result: *)
Lemma plus_comm3 :
forall x y z, x + (y + z) = (z + y) + x.
(** It appears at first sight that we ought to be able to prove this
by rewriting with [plus_comm] twice to make the two sides match.
The problem, however, is that the second [rewrite] will undo the
effect of the first. *)
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros x y z.
rewrite plus_comm.
rewrite plus_comm.
(* We are back where we started... *)
Abort.
(** One simple way of fixing this problem, using only tools that we
already know, is to use [assert] to derive a specialized version
of [plus_comm] that can be used to rewrite exactly where we
want. *)
Lemma plus_comm3_take2 :
forall x y z, x + (y + z) = (z + y) + x.
Proof.
intros x y z.
rewrite plus_comm.
assert (H : y + z = z + y).
{ rewrite plus_comm. reflexivity. }
rewrite H.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** A more elegant alternative is to apply [plus_comm] directly to the
arguments we want to instantiate it with, in much the same way as
we apply a polymorphic function to a type argument. *)
Lemma plus_comm3_take3 :
forall x y z, x + (y + z) = (z + y) + x.
Proof.
intros x y z.
rewrite plus_comm.
rewrite (plus_comm y z).
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** Let us show another example of using a theorem or lemma
like a function. The following theorem says: any list [l]
containing some element must be nonempty. *)
Lemma in_not_nil :
forall A (x : A) (l : list A), In x l -> l <> [].
Proof.
intros A x l H. unfold not. intro Hl. destruct l.
- simpl in H. destruct H.
- discriminate Hl.
Qed.
(** What makes this interesting is that one quantified variable
([x]) does not appear in the conclusion ([l <> []]). *)
(** We can use this lemma to prove the special case where [x]
is [42]. Naively, the tactic [apply in_not_nil] will fail because
it cannot infer the value of [x]. There are several ways to work
around that... *)
Lemma in_not_nil_42 :
forall l : list nat, In 42 l -> l <> [].
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros l H.
Fail apply in_not_nil.
Abort.
(* [apply ... with ...] *)
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take2 :
forall l : list nat, In 42 l -> l <> [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil with (x := 42).
apply H.
Qed.
(* [apply ... in ...] *)
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take3 :
forall l : list nat, In 42 l -> l <> [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply in_not_nil in H.
apply H.
Qed.
(* Explicitly apply the lemma to the value for [x]. *)
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take4 :
forall l : list nat, In 42 l -> l <> [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil nat 42).
apply H.
Qed.
(* Explicitly apply the lemma to a hypothesis. *)
Lemma in_not_nil_42_take5 :
forall l : list nat, In 42 l -> l <> [].
Proof.
intros l H.
apply (in_not_nil _ _ _ H).
Qed.
(** You can "use theorems as functions" in this way with almost all
tactics that take a theorem name as an argument. Note also that
theorem application uses the same inference mechanisms as function
application; thus, it is possible, for example, to supply
wildcards as arguments to be inferred, or to declare some
hypotheses to a theorem as implicit by default. These features
are illustrated in the proof below. (The details of how this proof
works are not critical -- the goal here is just to illustrate what
can be done.) *)
Example lemma_application_ex :
forall {n : nat} {ns : list nat},
In n (map (fun m => m * 0) ns) ->
n = 0.
Proof.
intros n ns H.
destruct (proj1 _ _ (In_map_iff _ _ _ _ _) H)
as [m [Hm _]].
rewrite mult_0_r in Hm. rewrite <- Hm. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** We will see many more examples in later chapters. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Coq vs. Set Theory *)
(** Coq's logical core, the _Calculus of Inductive
Constructions_, differs in some important ways from other formal
systems that are used by mathematicians to write down precise and
rigorous proofs. For example, in the most popular foundation for
paper-and-pencil mathematics, Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZFC), a
mathematical object can potentially be a member of many different
sets; a term in Coq's logic, on the other hand, is a member of at
most one type. This difference often leads to slightly different
ways of capturing informal mathematical concepts, but these are,
by and large, about equally natural and easy to work with. For
example, instead of saying that a natural number [n] belongs to
the set of even numbers, we would say in Coq that [even n] holds,
where [even : nat -> Prop] is a property describing even numbers.
However, there are some cases where translating standard
mathematical reasoning into Coq can be cumbersome or sometimes
even impossible, unless we enrich the core logic with additional
axioms.
We conclude this chapter with a brief discussion of some of the
most significant differences between the two worlds. *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Functional Extensionality *)
(** The equality assertions that we have seen so far mostly have
concerned elements of inductive types ([nat], [bool], etc.). But
since Coq's equality operator is polymorphic, these are not the
only possibilities -- in particular, we can write propositions
claiming that two _functions_ are equal to each other: *)
Example function_equality_ex1 :
(fun x => 3 + x) = (fun x => (pred 4) + x).
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** In common mathematical practice, two functions [f] and [g] are
considered equal if they produce the same outputs:
(forall x, f x = g x) -> f = g
This is known as the principle of _functional extensionality_. *)
(** Informally speaking, an "extensional property" is one that
pertains to an object's observable behavior. Thus, functional
extensionality simply means that a function's identity is
completely determined by what we can observe from it -- i.e., in
Coq terms, the results we obtain after applying it. *)
(** Functional extensionality is not part of Coq's built-in logic.
This means that some "reasonable" propositions are not provable. *)
Example function_equality_ex2 :
(fun x => plus x 1) = (fun x => plus 1 x).
Proof.
(* Stuck *)
Abort.
(** However, we can add functional extensionality to Coq's core using
the [Axiom] command. *)
Axiom functional_extensionality : forall {X Y: Type}
{f g : X -> Y},
(forall (x:X), f x = g x) -> f = g.
(** Using [Axiom] has the same effect as stating a theorem and
skipping its proof using [Admitted], but it alerts the reader that
this isn't just something we're going to come back and fill in
later! *)
(** We can now invoke functional extensionality in proofs: *)
Example function_equality_ex2 :
(fun x => plus x 1) = (fun x => plus 1 x).
Proof.
apply functional_extensionality. intros x.
apply plus_comm.
Qed.
(** Naturally, we must be careful when adding new axioms into Coq's
logic, as they may render it _inconsistent_ -- that is, they may
make it possible to prove every proposition, including [False],
[2+2=5], etc.!
Unfortunately, there is no simple way of telling whether an axiom
is safe to add: hard work by highly-trained trained experts is
generally required to establish the consistency of any particular
combination of axioms.
Fortunately, it is known that adding functional extensionality, in
particular, _is_ consistent. *)
(** To check whether a particular proof relies on any additional
axioms, use the [Print Assumptions] command. *)
Print Assumptions function_equality_ex2.
(* ===>
Axioms:
functional_extensionality :
forall (X Y : Type) (f g : X -> Y),
(forall x : X, f x = g x) -> f = g *)
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, standard (tr_rev_correct)
One problem with the definition of the list-reversing function
[rev] that we have is that it performs a call to [app] on each
step; running [app] takes time asymptotically linear in the size
of the list, which means that [rev] has quadratic running time.
We can improve this with the following definition: *)
Fixpoint rev_append {X} (l1 l2 : list X) : list X :=
match l1 with
| [] => l2
| x :: l1' => rev_append l1' (x :: l2)
end.
Definition tr_rev {X} (l : list X) : list X :=
rev_append l [].
(** This version is said to be _tail-recursive_, because the recursive
call to the function is the last operation that needs to be
performed (i.e., we don't have to execute [++] after the recursive
call); a decent compiler will generate very efficient code in this
case. Prove that the two definitions are indeed equivalent. *)
Lemma tr_rev_correct : forall X, @tr_rev X = @rev X.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Propositions and Booleans *)
(** We've seen two different ways of expressing logical claims in Coq:
with _booleans_ (of type [bool]), and with _propositions_ (of type
[Prop]).
For instance, to claim that a number [n] is even, we can say
either... *)
(** ... that [evenb n] evaluates to [true]... *)
Example even_42_bool : evenb 42 = true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** ... or that there exists some [k] such that [n = double k]. *)
Example even_42_prop : exists k, 42 = double k.
Proof. exists 21. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Of course, it would be pretty strange if these two
characterizations of evenness did not describe the same set of
natural numbers! Fortunately, we can prove that they do... *)
(** We first need two helper lemmas. *)
Theorem evenb_double : forall k, evenb (double k) = true.
Proof.
intros k. induction k as [|k' IHk'].
- reflexivity.
- simpl. apply IHk'.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (evenb_double_conv) *)
Theorem evenb_double_conv : forall n,
exists k, n = if evenb n then double k
else S (double k).
Proof.
(* Hint: Use the [evenb_S] lemma from [Induction.v]. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
Theorem even_bool_prop : forall n,
evenb n = true <-> exists k, n = double k.
Proof.
intros n. split.
- intros H. destruct (evenb_double_conv n) as [k Hk].
rewrite Hk. rewrite H. exists k. reflexivity.
- intros [k Hk]. rewrite Hk. apply evenb_double.
Qed.
(** In view of this theorem, we say that the boolean computation
[evenb n] is reflected in the truth of the proposition [exists k,
n = double k]. *)
(** Similarly, to state that two numbers [n] and [m] are equal, we can
say either
- (1) that [n =? m] returns [true], or
- (2) that [n = m].
Again, these two notions are equivalent. *)
Theorem eqb_eq : forall n1 n2 : nat,
n1 =? n2 = true <-> n1 = n2.
Proof.
intros n1 n2. split.
- apply eqb_true.
- intros H. rewrite H. rewrite <- eqb_refl. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** However, even when the boolean and propositional formulations of a
claim are equivalent from a purely logical perspective, they may
not be equivalent _operationally_. *)
(** In the case of even numbers above, when proving the
backwards direction of [even_bool_prop] (i.e., [evenb_double],
going from the propositional to the boolean claim), we used a
simple induction on [k]. On the other hand, the converse (the
[evenb_double_conv] exercise) required a clever generalization,
since we can't directly prove
[(evenb n = true) -> (exists k, n = double k)]. *)
(** For these examples, the propositional claims are more useful than
their boolean counterparts, but this is not always the case. For
instance, we cannot test whether a general proposition is true or
not in a function definition; as a consequence, the following code
fragment is rejected: *)
Fail Definition is_even_prime n :=
if n = 2 then true
else false.
(** Coq complains that [n = 2] has type [Prop], while it expects
an element of [bool] (or some other inductive type with two
elements). The reason for this error message has to do with the
_computational_ nature of Coq's core language, which is designed
so that every function that it can express is computable and
total. One reason for this is to allow the extraction of
executable programs from Coq developments. As a consequence,
[Prop] in Coq does _not_ have a universal case analysis operation
telling whether any given proposition is true or false, since such
an operation would allow us to write non-computable functions.
Although general non-computable properties cannot be phrased as
boolean computations, it is worth noting that even many
_computable_ properties are easier to express using [Prop] than
[bool], since recursive function definitions are subject to
significant restrictions in Coq. For instance, the next chapter
shows how to define the property that a regular expression matches
a given string using [Prop]. Doing the same with [bool] would
amount to writing a regular expression matcher, which would be
more complicated, harder to understand, and harder to reason
about.
Conversely, an important side benefit of stating facts using
booleans is enabling some proof automation through computation
with Coq terms, a technique known as _proof by
reflection_. Consider the following statement: *)
Example even_1000 : exists k, 1000 = double k.
(** The most direct proof of this fact is to give the value of [k]
explicitly. *)
Proof. exists 500. reflexivity. Qed.
(** On the other hand, the proof of the corresponding boolean
statement is even simpler: *)
Example even_1000' : evenb 1000 = true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
(** What is interesting is that, since the two notions are equivalent,
we can use the boolean formulation to prove the other one without
mentioning the value 500 explicitly: *)
Example even_1000'' : exists k, 1000 = double k.
Proof. apply even_bool_prop. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Although we haven't gained much in terms of proof-script
size in this case, larger proofs can often be made considerably
simpler by the use of reflection. As an extreme example, the Coq
proof of the famous _4-color theorem_ uses reflection to reduce
the analysis of hundreds of different cases to a boolean
computation. *)
(** Another notable difference is that the negation of a "boolean
fact" is straightforward to state and prove: simply flip the
expected boolean result. *)
Example not_even_1001 : evenb 1001 = false.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** In contrast, propositional negation may be more difficult
to grasp. *)
Example not_even_1001' : ~(exists k, 1001 = double k).
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
rewrite <- even_bool_prop.
unfold not.
simpl.
intro H.
discriminate H.
Qed.
(** Equality provides a complementary example: knowing that
[n =? m = true] is generally of little direct help in the middle
of a proof involving [n] and [m]; however, if we convert the
statement to the equivalent form [n = m], we can rewrite with it.
*)
Lemma plus_eqb_example : forall n m p : nat,
n =? m = true -> n + p =? m + p = true.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
intros n m p H.
rewrite eqb_eq in H.
rewrite H.
rewrite eqb_eq.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** We won't cover reflection in much detail, but it serves as a good
example showing the complementary strengths of booleans and
general propositions. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard (logical_connectives)
The following lemmas relate the propositional connectives studied
in this chapter to the corresponding boolean operations. *)
Lemma andb_true_iff : forall b1 b2:bool,
b1 && b2 = true <-> b1 = true /\ b2 = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Lemma orb_true_iff : forall b1 b2,
b1 || b2 = true <-> b1 = true \/ b2 = true.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, standard (eqb_neq)
The following theorem is an alternate "negative" formulation of
[eqb_eq] that is more convenient in certain
situations (we'll see examples in later chapters). *)
Theorem eqb_neq : forall x y : nat,
x =? y = false <-> x <> y.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (eqb_list)
Given a boolean operator [eqb] for testing equality of elements of
some type [A], we can define a function [eqb_list] for testing
equality of lists with elements in [A]. Complete the definition
of the [eqb_list] function below. To make sure that your
definition is correct, prove the lemma [eqb_list_true_iff]. *)
Fixpoint eqb_list {A : Type} (eqb : A -> A -> bool)
(l1 l2 : list A) : bool
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Lemma eqb_list_true_iff :
forall A (eqb : A -> A -> bool),
(forall a1 a2, eqb a1 a2 = true <-> a1 = a2) ->
forall l1 l2, eqb_list eqb l1 l2 = true <-> l1 = l2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, standard, recommended (All_forallb)
Recall the function [forallb], from the exercise
[forall_exists_challenge] in chapter [Tactics]: *)
Fixpoint forallb {X : Type} (test : X -> bool) (l : list X) : bool :=
match l with
| [] => true
| x :: l' => andb (test x) (forallb test l')
end.
(** Prove the theorem below, which relates [forallb] to the [All]
property of the above exercise. *)
Theorem forallb_true_iff : forall X test (l : list X),
forallb test l = true <-> All (fun x => test x = true) l.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** Are there any important properties of the function [forallb] which
are not captured by this specification? *)
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(* ================================================================= *)
(** ** Classical vs. Constructive Logic *)
(** We have seen that it is not possible to test whether or not a
proposition [P] holds while defining a Coq function. You may be
surprised to learn that a similar restriction applies to _proofs_!
In other words, the following intuitive reasoning principle is not
derivable in Coq: *)
Definition excluded_middle := forall P : Prop,
P \/ ~ P.
(** To understand operationally why this is the case, recall
that, to prove a statement of the form [P \/ Q], we use the [left]
and [right] tactics, which effectively require knowing which side
of the disjunction holds. But the universally quantified [P] in
[excluded_middle] is an _arbitrary_ proposition, which we know
nothing about. We don't have enough information to choose which
of [left] or [right] to apply, just as Coq doesn't have enough
information to mechanically decide whether [P] holds or not inside
a function. *)
(** However, if we happen to know that [P] is reflected in some
boolean term [b], then knowing whether it holds or not is trivial:
we just have to check the value of [b]. *)
Theorem restricted_excluded_middle : forall P b,
(P <-> b = true) -> P \/ ~ P.
Proof.
intros P [] H.
- left. rewrite H. reflexivity.
- right. rewrite H. intros contra. discriminate contra.
Qed.
(** In particular, the excluded middle is valid for equations [n = m],
between natural numbers [n] and [m]. *)
Theorem restricted_excluded_middle_eq : forall (n m : nat),
n = m \/ n <> m.
Proof.
intros n m.
apply (restricted_excluded_middle (n = m) (n =? m)).
symmetry.
apply eqb_eq.
Qed.
(** It may seem strange that the general excluded middle is not
available by default in Coq; after all, any given claim must be
either true or false. Nonetheless, there is an advantage in not
assuming the excluded middle: statements in Coq can make stronger
claims than the analogous statements in standard mathematics.
Notably, if there is a Coq proof of [exists x, P x], it is
possible to explicitly exhibit a value of [x] for which we can
prove [P x] -- in other words, every proof of existence is
necessarily _constructive_. *)
(** Logics like Coq's, which do not assume the excluded middle, are
referred to as _constructive logics_.
More conventional logical systems such as ZFC, in which the
excluded middle does hold for arbitrary propositions, are referred
to as _classical_. *)
(** The following example illustrates why assuming the excluded middle
may lead to non-constructive proofs:
_Claim_: There exist irrational numbers [a] and [b] such that [a ^
b] is rational.
_Proof_: It is not difficult to show that [sqrt 2] is irrational.
If [sqrt 2 ^ sqrt 2] is rational, it suffices to take [a = b =
sqrt 2] and we are done. Otherwise, [sqrt 2 ^ sqrt 2] is
irrational. In this case, we can take [a = sqrt 2 ^ sqrt 2] and
[b = sqrt 2], since [a ^ b = sqrt 2 ^ (sqrt 2 * sqrt 2) = sqrt 2 ^
2 = 2]. []
Do you see what happened here? We used the excluded middle to
consider separately the cases where [sqrt 2 ^ sqrt 2] is rational
and where it is not, without knowing which one actually holds!
Because of that, we wind up knowing that such [a] and [b] exist
but we cannot determine what their actual values are (at least,
using this line of argument).
As useful as constructive logic is, it does have its limitations:
There are many statements that can easily be proven in classical
logic but that have much more complicated constructive proofs, and
there are some that are known to have no constructive proof at
all! Fortunately, like functional extensionality, the excluded
middle is known to be compatible with Coq's logic, allowing us to
add it safely as an axiom. However, we will not need to do so in
this book: the results that we cover can be developed entirely
within constructive logic at negligible extra cost.
It takes some practice to understand which proof techniques must
be avoided in constructive reasoning, but arguments by
contradiction, in particular, are infamous for leading to
non-constructive proofs. Here's a typical example: suppose that
we want to show that there exists [x] with some property [P],
i.e., such that [P x]. We start by assuming that our conclusion
is false; that is, [~ exists x, P x]. From this premise, it is not
hard to derive [forall x, ~ P x]. If we manage to show that this
intermediate fact results in a contradiction, we arrive at an
existence proof without ever exhibiting a value of [x] for which
[P x] holds!
The technical flaw here, from a constructive standpoint, is that
we claimed to prove [exists x, P x] using a proof of
[~ ~ (exists x, P x)]. Allowing ourselves to remove double
negations from arbitrary statements is equivalent to assuming the
excluded middle, as shown in one of the exercises below. Thus,
this line of reasoning cannot be encoded in Coq without assuming
additional axioms. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, standard (excluded_middle_irrefutable)
Proving the consistency of Coq with the general excluded middle
axiom requires complicated reasoning that cannot be carried out
within Coq itself. However, the following theorem implies that it
is always safe to assume a decidability axiom (i.e., an instance
of excluded middle) for any _particular_ Prop [P]. Why? Because
we cannot prove the negation of such an axiom. If we could, we
would have both [~ (P \/ ~P)] and [~ ~ (P \/ ~P)] (since [P]
implies [~ ~ P], by the exercise below), which would be a
contradiction. But since we can't, it is safe to add [P \/ ~P] as
an axiom. *)
Theorem excluded_middle_irrefutable: forall (P:Prop),
~ ~ (P \/ ~ P).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (not_exists_dist)
It is a theorem of classical logic that the following two
assertions are equivalent:
~ (exists x, ~ P x)
forall x, P x
The [dist_not_exists] theorem above proves one side of this
equivalence. Interestingly, the other direction cannot be proved
in constructive logic. Your job is to show that it is implied by
the excluded middle. *)
Theorem not_exists_dist :
excluded_middle ->
forall (X:Type) (P : X -> Prop),
~ (exists x, ~ P x) -> (forall x, P x).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(** [] *)
(** **** Exercise: 5 stars, standard, optional (classical_axioms)
For those who like a challenge, here is an exercise taken from the
Coq'Art book by Bertot and Casteran (p. 123). Each of the
following four statements, together with [excluded_middle], can be
considered as characterizing classical logic. We can't prove any
of them in Coq, but we can consistently add any one of them as an
axiom if we wish to work in classical logic.
Prove that all five propositions (these four plus
[excluded_middle]) are equivalent. *)
Definition peirce := forall P Q: Prop,
((P->Q)->P)->P.
Definition double_negation_elimination := forall P:Prop,
~~P -> P.
Definition de_morgan_not_and_not := forall P Q:Prop,
~(~P /\ ~Q) -> P\/Q.
Definition implies_to_or := forall P Q:Prop,
(P->Q) -> (~P\/Q).
(* FILL IN HERE
[] *)
(* Wed Jan 9 12:02:45 EST 2019 *)