This commit is contained in:
parent
531b33442d
commit
043b3ebe74
5 changed files with 357 additions and 60 deletions
|
@ -8,6 +8,7 @@ import {
|
||||||
mkdirSync,
|
mkdirSync,
|
||||||
mkdtempSync,
|
mkdtempSync,
|
||||||
readFileSync,
|
readFileSync,
|
||||||
|
existsSync,
|
||||||
readdirSync,
|
readdirSync,
|
||||||
copyFileSync,
|
copyFileSync,
|
||||||
writeFileSync,
|
writeFileSync,
|
||||||
|
@ -35,6 +36,8 @@ const remarkAgda: RemarkPlugin = ({ base, publicDir }: Options) => {
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
const tempDir = mkdtempSync(join(tmpdir(), "agdaRender."));
|
const tempDir = mkdtempSync(join(tmpdir(), "agdaRender."));
|
||||||
const agdaOutDir = join(tempDir, "output");
|
const agdaOutDir = join(tempDir, "output");
|
||||||
|
const agdaOutFilename = parse(path).base.replace(/\.lagda.md/, ".md");
|
||||||
|
const agdaOutFile = join(agdaOutDir, agdaOutFilename);
|
||||||
mkdirSync(agdaOutDir, { recursive: true });
|
mkdirSync(agdaOutDir, { recursive: true });
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
const childOutput = spawnSync(
|
const childOutput = spawnSync(
|
||||||
|
@ -44,18 +47,32 @@ const remarkAgda: RemarkPlugin = ({ base, publicDir }: Options) => {
|
||||||
`--html-dir=${agdaOutDir}`,
|
`--html-dir=${agdaOutDir}`,
|
||||||
"--highlight-occurrences",
|
"--highlight-occurrences",
|
||||||
"--html-highlight=code",
|
"--html-highlight=code",
|
||||||
"--allow-unsolved-metas",
|
|
||||||
path,
|
path,
|
||||||
],
|
],
|
||||||
{},
|
{},
|
||||||
);
|
);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
// TODO: Handle child output
|
if (childOutput.error || !existsSync(agdaOutFile)) {
|
||||||
console.error("--AGDA OUTPUT--");
|
throw new Error(
|
||||||
console.error(childOutput);
|
`Agda error:
|
||||||
console.error(childOutput.stdout?.toString());
|
|
||||||
console.error(childOutput.stderr?.toString());
|
Stdout:
|
||||||
console.error("--AGDA OUTPUT--");
|
${childOutput.stdout}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Stderr:
|
||||||
|
${childOutput.stderr}`,
|
||||||
|
{
|
||||||
|
cause: childOutput.error,
|
||||||
|
},
|
||||||
|
);
|
||||||
|
}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
// // TODO: Handle child output
|
||||||
|
// console.error("--AGDA OUTPUT--");
|
||||||
|
// console.error(childOutput);
|
||||||
|
// console.error(childOutput.stdout?.toString());
|
||||||
|
// console.error(childOutput.stderr?.toString());
|
||||||
|
// console.error("--AGDA OUTPUT--");
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
const referencedFiles = new Set();
|
const referencedFiles = new Set();
|
||||||
for (const file of readdirSync(agdaOutDir)) {
|
for (const file of readdirSync(agdaOutDir)) {
|
||||||
|
@ -87,11 +104,9 @@ const remarkAgda: RemarkPlugin = ({ base, publicDir }: Options) => {
|
||||||
}
|
}
|
||||||
}
|
}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
const filename = parse(path).base.replace(/\.lagda.md/, ".md");
|
|
||||||
const htmlname = parse(path).base.replace(/\.lagda.md/, ".html");
|
const htmlname = parse(path).base.replace(/\.lagda.md/, ".html");
|
||||||
const fullOutputPath = join(agdaOutDir, filename);
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
const doc = readFileSync(fullOutputPath);
|
const doc = readFileSync(agdaOutFile);
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
// This is the post-processed markdown with HTML code blocks replacing the Agda code blocks
|
// This is the post-processed markdown with HTML code blocks replacing the Agda code blocks
|
||||||
const tree2 = fromMarkdown(doc);
|
const tree2 = fromMarkdown(doc);
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -4,22 +4,24 @@ module Prelude where
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
open import Agda.Primitive
|
open import Agda.Primitive
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
module 𝟘 where
|
private
|
||||||
data ⊥ : Set where
|
variable
|
||||||
¬_ : Set → Set
|
l : Level
|
||||||
¬ A = A → ⊥
|
|
||||||
open 𝟘 public
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
module 𝟙 where
|
data ⊥ : Set where
|
||||||
data ⊤ : Set where
|
|
||||||
tt : ⊤
|
|
||||||
open 𝟙 public
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
module 𝟚 where
|
rec-⊥ : {A : Set} → ⊥ → A
|
||||||
data Bool : Set where
|
rec-⊥ ()
|
||||||
true : Bool
|
|
||||||
false : Bool
|
¬_ : Set → Set
|
||||||
open 𝟚 public
|
¬ A = A → ⊥
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
data ⊤ : Set where
|
||||||
|
tt : ⊤
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
data Bool : Set where
|
||||||
|
true : Bool
|
||||||
|
false : Bool
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
id : {l : Level} {A : Set l} → A → A
|
id : {l : Level} {A : Set l} → A → A
|
||||||
id x = x
|
id x = x
|
||||||
|
@ -39,6 +41,19 @@ open Nat public
|
||||||
infix 4 _≡_
|
infix 4 _≡_
|
||||||
data _≡_ {l} {A : Set l} : (a b : A) → Set l where
|
data _≡_ {l} {A : Set l} : (a b : A) → Set l where
|
||||||
instance refl : {x : A} → x ≡ x
|
instance refl : {x : A} → x ≡ x
|
||||||
|
{-# BUILTIN EQUALITY _≡_ #-}
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
ap : {A B : Set l} → (f : A → B) → {x y : A} → x ≡ y → f x ≡ f y
|
||||||
|
ap f refl = refl
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
sym : {A : Set l} {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x
|
||||||
|
sym refl = refl
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
trans : {A : Set l} {x y z : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ z → x ≡ z
|
||||||
|
trans refl refl = refl
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
infixl 10 _∙_
|
||||||
|
_∙_ = trans
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
transport : {l₁ l₂ : Level} {A : Set l₁} {x y : A}
|
transport : {l₁ l₂ : Level} {A : Set l₁} {x y : A}
|
||||||
→ (P : A → Set l₂)
|
→ (P : A → Set l₂)
|
||||||
|
@ -72,3 +87,9 @@ _∘_ : {A B C : Set} (g : B → C) → (f : A → B) → A → C
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
_∼_ : {A B : Set} (f g : A → B) → Set
|
_∼_ : {A B : Set} (f g : A → B) → Set
|
||||||
_∼_ {A} f g = (x : A) → f x ≡ g x
|
_∼_ {A} f g = (x : A) → f x ≡ g x
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
postulate
|
||||||
|
funExt : {l : Level} {A B : Set l}
|
||||||
|
→ {f g : A → B}
|
||||||
|
→ ((x : A) → f x ≡ g x)
|
||||||
|
→ f ≡ g
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,5 +1,5 @@
|
||||||
---
|
---
|
||||||
title: "Formally proving true ≢ false in cubical Agda"
|
title: "Formally proving true ≢ false in Homotopy Type Theory with Agda"
|
||||||
slug: "proving-true-from-false"
|
slug: "proving-true-from-false"
|
||||||
date: 2023-04-21
|
date: 2023-04-21
|
||||||
tags: ["type-theory", "agda"]
|
tags: ["type-theory", "agda"]
|
||||||
|
@ -12,12 +12,7 @@ math: true
|
||||||
These are some imports that are required for code on this page to work properly.
|
These are some imports that are required for code on this page to work properly.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```agda
|
```agda
|
||||||
{-# OPTIONS --cubical #-}
|
open import Prelude
|
||||||
open import Cubical.Foundations.Prelude
|
|
||||||
open import Prelude hiding (_≢_; _≡_; refl; transport)
|
|
||||||
infix 4 _≢_
|
|
||||||
_≢_ : ∀ {A : Set} → A → A → Set
|
|
||||||
x ≢ y = ¬ (x ≡ y)
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
</details>
|
</details>
|
||||||
|
@ -53,9 +48,8 @@ left side so it becomes judgmentally equal to the right:
|
||||||
- suc (suc (suc zero))
|
- suc (suc (suc zero))
|
||||||
- 3
|
- 3
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
However, in cubical Agda, naively using `refl` with the inverse statement
|
However, in Agda, naively using `refl` with the inverse statement doesn't work.
|
||||||
doesn't work. I've commented it out so the code on this page can continue to
|
I've commented it out so the code on this page can continue to compile.
|
||||||
compile.
|
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
-- true≢false = refl
|
-- true≢false = refl
|
||||||
|
@ -88,7 +82,7 @@ The strategy here is we define some kind of "type-map". Every time we see
|
||||||
`false`, we'll map it to empty.
|
`false`, we'll map it to empty.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
bool-map : Bool → Type
|
bool-map : Bool → Set
|
||||||
bool-map true = ⊤
|
bool-map true = ⊤
|
||||||
bool-map false = ⊥
|
bool-map false = ⊥
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
@ -98,26 +92,29 @@ over a path (the path supposedly given to us as the witness that true ≢ false)
|
||||||
will produce a function from the inhabited type we chose to the empty type!
|
will produce a function from the inhabited type we chose to the empty type!
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
true≢false p = transport (λ i → bool-map (p i)) tt
|
true≢false p = transport bool-map p tt
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
I used `true` here, but I could equally have just used anything else:
|
I used `true` here, but I could equally have just used anything else:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
bool-map2 : Bool → Type
|
bool-map2 : Bool → Set
|
||||||
bool-map2 true = 1 ≡ 1
|
bool-map2 true = 1 ≡ 1
|
||||||
bool-map2 false = ⊥
|
bool-map2 false = ⊥
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
true≢false2 : true ≢ false
|
true≢false2 : true ≢ false
|
||||||
true≢false2 p = transport (λ i → bool-map2 (p i)) refl
|
true≢false2 p = transport bool-map2 p refl
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
## Note on proving divergence on equivalent values
|
## Note on proving divergence on equivalent values
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
Let's make sure this isn't broken by trying to apply this to something that's
|
> [!NOTE]
|
||||||
actually true:
|
> Update: some of these have been commented out since regular Agda doesn't support higher inductive types
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
Let's make sure this isn't broken by trying to apply this to something that's
|
||||||
|
actually true, like this higher inductive type:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```text
|
||||||
data NotBool : Type where
|
data NotBool : Type where
|
||||||
true1 : NotBool
|
true1 : NotBool
|
||||||
true2 : NotBool
|
true2 : NotBool
|
||||||
|
@ -128,8 +125,7 @@ In this data type, we have a path over `true1` and `true2` that is a part of the
|
||||||
definition of the `NotBool` type. Since this is an intrinsic equality, we can't
|
definition of the `NotBool` type. Since this is an intrinsic equality, we can't
|
||||||
map `true1` and `true2` to divergent types. Let's see what happens:
|
map `true1` and `true2` to divergent types. Let's see what happens:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```text
|
||||||
{-# NON_COVERING #-}
|
|
||||||
notbool-map : NotBool → Type
|
notbool-map : NotBool → Type
|
||||||
notbool-map true1 = ⊤
|
notbool-map true1 = ⊤
|
||||||
notbool-map true2 = ⊥
|
notbool-map true2 = ⊥
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -12,7 +12,7 @@ First off, a demonstration. Here's the code for function application over a path
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
open import Agda.Primitive
|
open import Agda.Primitive
|
||||||
open import Prelude
|
open import Prelude hiding (ap)
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
ap : {l1 l2 : Level} {A : Set l1} {B : Set l2} {x y : A}
|
ap : {l1 l2 : Level} {A : Set l1} {B : Set l2} {x y : A}
|
||||||
→ (f : A → B)
|
→ (f : A → B)
|
||||||
|
|
|
@ -1,5 +1,5 @@
|
||||||
---
|
---
|
||||||
title: "Boolean equivalences"
|
title: "Boolean equivalences in HoTT"
|
||||||
slug: 2024-06-28-boolean-equivalences
|
slug: 2024-06-28-boolean-equivalences
|
||||||
date: 2024-06-28T21:37:04.299Z
|
date: 2024-06-28T21:37:04.299Z
|
||||||
tags: ["agda", "type-theory", "hott"]
|
tags: ["agda", "type-theory", "hott"]
|
||||||
|
@ -15,25 +15,41 @@ $$
|
||||||
(2 \simeq 2) \simeq 2
|
(2 \simeq 2) \simeq 2
|
||||||
$$
|
$$
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
This problem is exercise 2.13 of the [Homotopy Type Theory book][book]. If you
|
> [!NOTE]
|
||||||
are planning to attempt this problem, spoilers ahead!
|
> This problem is exercise 2.13 of the [Homotopy Type Theory book][book]. If you
|
||||||
|
> are planning to attempt this problem, spoilers ahead!
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
[book]: https://homotopytypetheory.org/book/
|
[book]: https://homotopytypetheory.org/book/
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
<small>The following line imports some of the definitions used in this post.</small>
|
<small>The following line imports some of the definitions used in this post.</small>
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
{-# OPTIONS --allow-unsolved-metas #-}
|
||||||
open import Prelude
|
open import Prelude
|
||||||
|
open Σ
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
## The problem explained
|
## The problem explained
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
With just the notation, the problem may not be clear.
|
With just that notation, the problem may not be clear.
|
||||||
$2$ represents the set with only 2 elements in it, which is the booleans. The
|
$2$ represents the set with only two elements in it, which is the booleans. The
|
||||||
elements of $2$ are $\textrm{true}$ and $\textrm{false}$.
|
elements of $2$ are $\textrm{true}$ and $\textrm{false}$.
|
||||||
In this expression, $\simeq$ denotes [_homotopy equivalence_][1] between sets,
|
|
||||||
which you can think of as an isomorphism.
|
```
|
||||||
For some function $f : A \rightarrow B$, we say that $f$ is an equivalence if:
|
data 𝟚 : Set where
|
||||||
|
true : 𝟚
|
||||||
|
false : 𝟚
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
In the problem statement, $\simeq$ denotes [_homotopy equivalence_][1] between
|
||||||
|
sets, which you can think of as basically a fancy isomorphism. For some
|
||||||
|
function $f : A \rightarrow B$, we say that $f$ is an equivalence[^equivalence]
|
||||||
|
if:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
[^equivalence]: There are other ways to define equivalences. As we'll show, an important
|
||||||
|
property that is missed by this definition is that equivalences should be _mere
|
||||||
|
propositions_. The reason why this definition falls short of that requirement is
|
||||||
|
shown by Theorem 4.1.3 in the [HoTT book][book].
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
[1]: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Homotopy#Homotopy_equivalence
|
[1]: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Homotopy#Homotopy_equivalence
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -56,7 +72,7 @@ Then, the expression $2 \simeq 2$ simply expresses an equivalence between the
|
||||||
boolean set to itself. Here's an example of a function that satisfies this equivalence:
|
boolean set to itself. Here's an example of a function that satisfies this equivalence:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
bool-id : Bool → Bool
|
bool-id : 𝟚 → 𝟚
|
||||||
bool-id b = b
|
bool-id b = b
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -74,9 +90,9 @@ bool-id-eqv = mkEquiv bool-id id-homotopy id-homotopy
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
We can package these together into a single definition that combines the
|
We can package these together into a single definition that combines the
|
||||||
function along with proof of its equivalence properties using a dependent
|
function along with proof of its equivalence properties using a dependent
|
||||||
pair[^1]:
|
pair[^dependent-pair]:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
[^1]: A dependent pair (or $\Sigma$-type) is like a regular pair $\langle x, y\rangle$, but where $y$ can depend on $x$.
|
[^dependent-pair]: A dependent pair (or $\Sigma$-type) is like a regular pair $\langle x, y\rangle$, but where $y$ can depend on $x$.
|
||||||
For example, $\langle x , \textrm{isPrime}(x) \rangle$.
|
For example, $\langle x , \textrm{isPrime}(x) \rangle$.
|
||||||
In this case it's useful since we can carry the equivalence information along with the function itself.
|
In this case it's useful since we can carry the equivalence information along with the function itself.
|
||||||
This type is rather core to Martin-Löf Type Theory, you can read more about it [here][dependent-pair].
|
This type is rather core to Martin-Löf Type Theory, you can read more about it [here][dependent-pair].
|
||||||
|
@ -93,7 +109,7 @@ A ≃ B = Σ (A → B) (λ f → isEquiv f)
|
||||||
This gives us an equivalence:
|
This gives us an equivalence:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
bool-eqv : Bool ≃ Bool
|
bool-eqv : 𝟚 ≃ 𝟚
|
||||||
bool-eqv = bool-id , bool-id-eqv
|
bool-eqv = bool-id , bool-id-eqv
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -106,7 +122,7 @@ equivalences between the boolean type and itself. Here is another possible
|
||||||
definition:
|
definition:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
bool-neg : Bool → Bool
|
bool-neg : 𝟚 → 𝟚
|
||||||
bool-neg true = false
|
bool-neg true = false
|
||||||
bool-neg false = true
|
bool-neg false = true
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
@ -127,7 +143,7 @@ bool-neg-eqv = mkEquiv bool-neg neg-homotopy neg-homotopy
|
||||||
neg-homotopy true = refl
|
neg-homotopy true = refl
|
||||||
neg-homotopy false = refl
|
neg-homotopy false = refl
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
bool-eqv2 : Bool ≃ Bool
|
bool-eqv2 : 𝟚 ≃ 𝟚
|
||||||
bool-eqv2 = bool-neg , bool-neg-eqv
|
bool-eqv2 = bool-neg , bool-neg-eqv
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
@ -147,6 +163,255 @@ That's where the main exercise statement comes in: "show that" $(2 \simeq 2)
|
||||||
\simeq 2$, or in other words, find an inhabitant of this type.
|
\simeq 2$, or in other words, find an inhabitant of this type.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
_ : (Bool ≃ Bool) ≃ Bool
|
main-theorem : (𝟚 ≃ 𝟚) ≃ 𝟚
|
||||||
_ = {! !}
|
|
||||||
```
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
How do we do this? Well, remember what it means to define an equivalence: first
|
||||||
|
define a function, then show that it is an equivalence. Since equivalences are
|
||||||
|
symmetrical, it doesn't matter which way we start first. I'll choose to first
|
||||||
|
define a function $2 \rightarrow 2 \simeq 2$. This is fairly easy to do by
|
||||||
|
case-splitting:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
f : 𝟚 → (𝟚 ≃ 𝟚)
|
||||||
|
f true = bool-eqv
|
||||||
|
f false = bool-eqv2
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
This maps `true` to the equivalence derived from the identity function, and
|
||||||
|
`false` to the function derived from the negation function.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Now we need another function in the other direction. We can't case-split on
|
||||||
|
functions, but we can certainly case-split on their output. Specifically, we can
|
||||||
|
differentiate `id` from `neg` by their behavior when being called on `true`:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
- $\textrm{id}(\textrm{true}) :\equiv \textrm{true}$
|
||||||
|
- $\textrm{neg}(\textrm{true}) :\equiv \textrm{false}$
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
g : (𝟚 ≃ 𝟚) → 𝟚
|
||||||
|
g eqv = (fst eqv) true
|
||||||
|
-- same as this:
|
||||||
|
-- let (f , f-is-equiv) = eqv in f true
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Hold on. If you know about the cardinality of functions, you'll observe that in
|
||||||
|
the space of functions $f : 2 \rightarrow 2$, there are $2^2 = 4$ equivalence
|
||||||
|
classes of functions. So if we mapped 4 functions into 2, how could this be
|
||||||
|
considered an equivalence?
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
A **key observation** here is that we're not mapping from all possible functions
|
||||||
|
$f : 2 \rightarrow 2$. We're mapping functions $f : 2 \simeq 2$ that have
|
||||||
|
already been proven to be equivalences. This means we can count on them to be
|
||||||
|
structure-preserving, and can rule out cases like the function that maps
|
||||||
|
everything to true, since it can't possibly have an inverse.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
We'll come back to this later.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
First, let's show that $g \circ f \sim \textrm{id}$. This one is easy, we can
|
||||||
|
just case-split. Each of the cases reduces to something that is definitionally
|
||||||
|
equal, so we can use `refl`.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
g∘f : (g ∘ f) ∼ id
|
||||||
|
g∘f true = refl
|
||||||
|
g∘f false = refl
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Now comes the complicated case: proving $f \circ g \sim \textrm{id}$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
> [!NOTE]
|
||||||
|
> Since Agda's comment syntax is `--`, the horizontal lines in the code below
|
||||||
|
> are simply a visual way of separating out our proof premises from our proof
|
||||||
|
> goals.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
module f∘g-case where
|
||||||
|
goal :
|
||||||
|
(eqv : 𝟚 ≃ 𝟚)
|
||||||
|
--------------------
|
||||||
|
→ f (g eqv) ≡ id eqv
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
f∘g : (f ∘ g) ∼ id
|
||||||
|
f∘g eqv = goal eqv
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Now our goal is to show that for any equivalence $\textrm{eqv} : 2 \simeq 2$,
|
||||||
|
applying $f ∘ g$ to it is the same as not doing anything. We can evaluate the
|
||||||
|
$g(\textrm{eqv})$ a little bit to give us a more detailed goal:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
goal2 :
|
||||||
|
(eqv : 𝟚 ≃ 𝟚)
|
||||||
|
--------------------------
|
||||||
|
→ f ((fst eqv) true) ≡ eqv
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
-- Solving goal with goal2, leaving us to prove goal2
|
||||||
|
goal eqv = goal2 eqv
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
The problem is if you think about equivalences as encoding some rich data about
|
||||||
|
a function, converting it to a boolean and back is sort of like shoving it into
|
||||||
|
a lower-resolution domain and then bringing it back. How can we prove that the
|
||||||
|
equivalence is still the same equivalence, and as a result proving that there
|
||||||
|
are only 2 possible equivalences?
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Note that the function $f$ ultimately still only produces 2 values. That means
|
||||||
|
if we want to prove this, we can case-split on $f$'s output. In Agda, this uses
|
||||||
|
a syntax known as [with-abstraction]:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
[with-abstraction]: https://agda.readthedocs.io/en/v2.6.4.3-r1/language/with-abstraction.html
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
goal3 :
|
||||||
|
(eqv : 𝟚 ≃ 𝟚) → (b : 𝟚) → (p : fst eqv true ≡ b)
|
||||||
|
------------------------------------------------
|
||||||
|
→ f b ≡ eqv
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
-- Solving goal2 with goal3, leaving us to prove goal3
|
||||||
|
goal2 eqv with b ← (fst eqv) true in p = goal3 eqv b p
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
We can now case-split on $b$, which is the output of calling $f$ on the
|
||||||
|
equivalence returned by $g$. This means that for the `true` case, we need to
|
||||||
|
show that $f(b) = \textrm{bool-eqv}$ (which is based on `id`) is equivalent to
|
||||||
|
the equivalence that generated the `true`.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Let's start with the `id` case; we just need to show that for every equivalence
|
||||||
|
$e$ where running the equivalence function on `true` also returned `true`, $e
|
||||||
|
\equiv f(\textrm{true})$.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Unfortunately, we don't know if this is true unless our equivalences are _mere
|
||||||
|
propositions_, meaning if two functions are identical, then so are their
|
||||||
|
equivalences.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
$$
|
||||||
|
\textrm{isProp}(P) :\equiv \prod_{x, y: P}(x \equiv y)
|
||||||
|
$$
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
<small>Definition 3.3.1 from the [HoTT book][book]</small>
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Applying this to $\textrm{isEquiv}(f)$, we get the property:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
$$
|
||||||
|
\sum_{f : A → B} \left( \prod_{e_1, e_2 : \textrm{isEquiv}(f)} e_1 \equiv e_2 \right)
|
||||||
|
$$
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
This proof is shown later in the book, so I will use it here directly without proof[^equiv-isProp]:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
[^equiv-isProp]: I haven't worked that far in the book yet, but this is shown in Theorem 4.2.13 in the [HoTT book][book].
|
||||||
|
I might write a separate post about that when I get there, it seems like an interesting proof as well!
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
postulate
|
||||||
|
equiv-isProp : {A B : Set}
|
||||||
|
→ (e1 e2 : A ≃ B) → (Σ.fst e1 ≡ Σ.fst e2)
|
||||||
|
-----------------------------------------
|
||||||
|
→ e1 ≡ e2
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Now we're going to need our **key observation** that we made earlier, that
|
||||||
|
equivalences must not map both values to a single one.
|
||||||
|
This way, we can pin the behavior of the function on all inputs by just using
|
||||||
|
its behavior on `true`, since its output on `false` must be _different_.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
We can use a proof that [$\textrm{true} \not\equiv \textrm{false}$][true-not-false] that I've shown previously.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
[true-not-false]: https://mzhang.io/posts/proving-true-from-false/
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
true≢false : true ≢ false
|
||||||
|
-- read: true ≡ false → ⊥
|
||||||
|
true≢false p = bottom-generator p
|
||||||
|
where
|
||||||
|
map : 𝟚 → Set
|
||||||
|
map true = ⊤
|
||||||
|
map false = ⊥
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
bottom-generator : true ≡ false → ⊥
|
||||||
|
bottom-generator p = transport map p tt
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Let's transform this into information about $f$'s output on different inputs:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
observation : (f : 𝟚 → 𝟚) → isEquiv f → f true ≢ f false
|
||||||
|
-- read: f true ≡ f false → ⊥
|
||||||
|
observation f (mkEquiv g f∘g g∘f) p =
|
||||||
|
let
|
||||||
|
-- Given p : f true ≡ f false
|
||||||
|
-- Proof strategy is to call g on it to get (g ∘ f) true ≡ (g ∘ f) false
|
||||||
|
-- Then, use our equivalence properties to reduce it to true ≡ false
|
||||||
|
-- Then, apply the lemma true≢false we just proved
|
||||||
|
step1 = ap g p
|
||||||
|
step2 = sym (g∘f true) ∙ step1 ∙ (g∘f false)
|
||||||
|
step3 = true≢false step2
|
||||||
|
in step3
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
For convenience, let's rewrite this so that it takes in an arbitrary $b$ and
|
||||||
|
returns the version of the inequality we want:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
observation' : (f : 𝟚 → 𝟚) → isEquiv f → (b : 𝟚) → f b ≢ f (bool-neg b)
|
||||||
|
-- ^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^
|
||||||
|
observation' f eqv true p = observation f eqv p
|
||||||
|
observation' f eqv false p = observation f eqv (sym p)
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Then, solving the `true` case is simply a matter of using function
|
||||||
|
extensionality (functions are equal if they are point-wise equal) to show that
|
||||||
|
just the function part of the equivalences are identical, and then using this
|
||||||
|
property to prove that the equivalences must be identical as well.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
goal3 eqv true p = equiv-isProp bool-eqv eqv functions-equal
|
||||||
|
where
|
||||||
|
e = fst eqv
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal : (x : 𝟚) → e x ≡ x
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal true = p
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal false with ef ← e false in eq = helper ef eq
|
||||||
|
where
|
||||||
|
helper : (ef : 𝟚) → e false ≡ ef → ef ≡ false
|
||||||
|
helper true eq = rec-⊥ (observation' e (snd eqv) false (eq ∙ sym p))
|
||||||
|
helper false eq = refl
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
-- NOTE: fst bool-eqv = id, definitionally
|
||||||
|
functions-equal : id ≡ e
|
||||||
|
functions-equal = sym (funExt pointwise-equal)
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
The `false` case is proved similarly.
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
goal3 eqv false p = equiv-isProp bool-eqv2 eqv functions-equal
|
||||||
|
where
|
||||||
|
e = fst eqv
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal : (x : 𝟚) → e x ≡ bool-neg x
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal true = p
|
||||||
|
pointwise-equal false with ef ← e false in eq = helper ef eq
|
||||||
|
where
|
||||||
|
helper : (ef : 𝟚) → e false ≡ ef → ef ≡ true
|
||||||
|
helper true eq = refl
|
||||||
|
helper false eq = rec-⊥ (observation' e (snd eqv) true (p ∙ sym eq))
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
functions-equal : bool-neg ≡ e
|
||||||
|
functions-equal = sym (funExt pointwise-equal)
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Putting this all together, we get the property we want to prove:
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
open f∘g-case
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
-- main-theorem : (𝟚 ≃ 𝟚) ≃ 𝟚
|
||||||
|
main-theorem = g , mkEquiv f g∘f f∘g
|
||||||
|
```
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Now that Agda's all happy, our work here is done!
|
||||||
|
|
||||||
|
Going through all this taught me a lot about how the basics of equivalences and
|
||||||
|
how to express a lot of different ideas into the type system. Thanks for
|
||||||
|
reading!
|
||||||
|
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue