Michael Zhang
7f8137b9f6
All checks were successful
ci/woodpecker/push/woodpecker Pipeline was successful
170 lines
4.5 KiB
Markdown
170 lines
4.5 KiB
Markdown
+++
|
||
title = "Proving true ≢ false"
|
||
slug = "proving-true-from-false"
|
||
date = 2023-04-21
|
||
tags = ["type-theory", "agda"]
|
||
math = true
|
||
+++
|
||
|
||
<details>
|
||
<summary>Imports</summary>
|
||
|
||
These are some imports that are required for code on this page to work properly.
|
||
|
||
```agda
|
||
{-# OPTIONS --cubical #-}
|
||
|
||
open import Cubical.Foundations.Prelude
|
||
open import Data.Bool
|
||
open import Data.Unit
|
||
open import Data.Empty
|
||
|
||
¬_ : Set → Set
|
||
¬ A = A → ⊥
|
||
|
||
infix 4 _≢_
|
||
_≢_ : ∀ {A : Set} → A → A → Set
|
||
x ≢ y = ¬ (x ≡ y)
|
||
```
|
||
</details>
|
||
|
||
The other day, I was trying to prove `true ≢ false` in Agda. I would write the
|
||
statement like this:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
true≢false : true ≢ false
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
For many "obvious" statements, it suffices to just write `refl` since the two
|
||
sides are trivially true via rewriting. For example:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
open import Data.Nat
|
||
1+2≡3 : 1 + 2 ≡ 3
|
||
1+2≡3 = refl
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
This is saying that using the way addition is defined, we can just rewrite the
|
||
left side so it becomes judgmentally equal to the right:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
-- For convenience, here's the definition of addition:
|
||
-- _+_ : Nat → Nat → Nat
|
||
-- zero + m = m
|
||
-- suc n + m = suc (n + m)
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
- 1 + 2
|
||
- suc zero + suc (suc zero)
|
||
- suc (zero + suc (suc zero))
|
||
- suc (suc (suc zero))
|
||
- 3
|
||
|
||
However, in cubical Agda, naively using `refl` with the inverse statement
|
||
doesn't work. I've commented it out so the code on this page can continue to
|
||
compile.
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
-- true≢false = refl
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
It looks like it's not obvious to the interpreter that this statement is
|
||
actually true. Why is that
|
||
|
||
## Intuition
|
||
|
||
Well, in constructive logic / constructive type theory, proving something is
|
||
false is actually a bit different. You see, the definition of the `not`
|
||
operator, or $\neg$, was:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
-- ¬_ : Set → Set
|
||
-- ¬ A = A → ⊥
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
> The code is commented out because it was already defined at the top of the
|
||
> page in order for the code to compile.
|
||
|
||
This roughly translates to, "give me any proof of A, and I'll produce a value of
|
||
the bottom type." Since the bottom type $\bot$ is a type without values, being
|
||
able to produce a value represents logical falsehood. So we're looking for a way
|
||
to ensure that any proof of `true ≢ false` must lead to $\bot$.
|
||
|
||
The strategy here is we define some kind of "type-map". Every time we see
|
||
`true`, we'll map it to some arbitrary inhabited type, and every time we see
|
||
`false`, we'll map it to empty.
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
bool-map : Bool → Type
|
||
bool-map true = ⊤
|
||
bool-map false = ⊥
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
This way, we can use the fact that transporting
|
||
over a path (the path supposedly given to us as the witness that true ≢ false)
|
||
will produce a function from the inhabited type we chose to the empty type!
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
true≢false p = transport (λ i → bool-map (p i)) tt
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
I used `true` here, but I could equally have just used anything else:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
bool-map2 : Bool → Type
|
||
bool-map2 true = 1 ≡ 1
|
||
bool-map2 false = ⊥
|
||
|
||
true≢false2 : true ≢ false
|
||
true≢false2 p = transport (λ i → bool-map2 (p i)) refl
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
## Note on proving divergence on equivalent values
|
||
|
||
Let's make sure this isn't broken by trying to apply this to something that's
|
||
actually true:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
data NotBool : Type where
|
||
true1 : NotBool
|
||
true2 : NotBool
|
||
same : true1 ≡ true2
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
In this data type, we have a path over `true1` and `true2` that is a part of the
|
||
definition of the `NotBool` type. Since this is an intrinsic equality, we can't
|
||
map `true1` and `true2` to divergent types. Let's see what happens:
|
||
|
||
```
|
||
notbool-map : NotBool → Type
|
||
notbool-map true1 = ⊤
|
||
notbool-map true2 = ⊥
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Ok, we've defined the same thing that we did before, but Agda gives us this
|
||
message:
|
||
|
||
```text
|
||
Errors:
|
||
Incomplete pattern matching for notbool-map. Missing cases:
|
||
notbool-map (same i)
|
||
when checking the definition of notbool-map
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
Agda helpfully notes that we still have another case in the inductive type to
|
||
pattern match on. Let's just go ahead and give it some value:
|
||
|
||
```text
|
||
notbool-map (same i) = ⊤
|
||
```
|
||
|
||
If you give it `⊤`, it will complain that `⊥ != ⊤ of type Type`, but if you give
|
||
it `⊥`, it will also complain! Because pattern matching on higher inductive
|
||
types requires a functor over the path, we must provide a function that
|
||
satisfies the equality `notbool-map true1 ≡ notbool-map true2`, which unless we
|
||
have provided the same type to both, will not be possible.
|
||
|
||
So in the end, this type `NotBool → Type` is only possible to write if the two
|
||
types we mapped `true1` and `true2` can be proven equivalent. But this also
|
||
means we can't use it to prove `true1 ≢ true2`, which is exactly the property we
|
||
wanted to begin with.
|