halfway through Quantifiers

This commit is contained in:
wadler 2018-03-15 19:08:31 -03:00
parent 77ebd9b67f
commit 29ed7cdbeb
5 changed files with 133 additions and 126 deletions

View file

@ -26,7 +26,7 @@ material in a different way; see the [Preface](Preface).
- [Equality: Equality and equational reasoning](Equality) - [Equality: Equality and equational reasoning](Equality)
- [Isomorphism: Isomorphism and embedding](Isomorphism) - [Isomorphism: Isomorphism and embedding](Isomorphism)
- [Connectives: Conjunction, Disjunction, and Implication](Connectives) - [Connectives: Conjunction, Disjunction, and Implication](Connectives)
- [Negation: Negation, with Classical and Intuitionistic Logic](Negation) - [Negation: Negation, with Intuitionistic and Classical Logic](Negation)
- [Quantiers: Universals and Existentials](Quantifiers) - [Quantiers: Universals and Existentials](Quantifiers)
- [Lists: Lists and other data types](Lists) - [Lists: Lists and other data types](Lists)
- [Decidable: Booleans and decision procedures](Decidable) - [Decidable: Booleans and decision procedures](Decidable)

View file

@ -534,7 +534,6 @@ Right identity follows from commutativity of sum and left identity.
≃-∎ ≃-∎
\end{code} \end{code}
## Implication is function ## Implication is function
Given two propositions `A` and `B`, the implication `A → B` holds if Given two propositions `A` and `B`, the implication `A → B` holds if
@ -543,9 +542,9 @@ the function type, which has appeared throughout this book.
Evidence that `A → B` holds is of the form Evidence that `A → B` holds is of the form
λ{ x → N } λ (x : A) → N x
where `N` is a term of type `B` containing as a free variable `x` of type `A`. where `N x` is a term of type `B` containing as a free variable `x` of type `A`.
Given a term `L` providing evidence that `A → B` holds, and a term `M` Given a term `L` providing evidence that `A → B` holds, and a term `M`
providing evidence that `A` holds, the term `L M` provides evidence that providing evidence that `A` holds, the term `L M` provides evidence that
`B` holds. In other words, evidence that `A → B` holds is a function that `B` holds. In other words, evidence that `A → B` holds is a function that
@ -555,7 +554,7 @@ Put another way, if we know that `A → B` and `A` both hold,
then we may conclude that `B` holds. then we may conclude that `B` holds.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
→-elim : ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → A → B →-elim : ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → A → B
→-elim f x = f x →-elim L M = L M
\end{code} \end{code}
In medieval times, this rule was known by the name *modus ponens*. In medieval times, this rule was known by the name *modus ponens*.
It corresponds to function application. It corresponds to function application.
@ -566,10 +565,10 @@ while applying a function is referred to as *eliminating* the function.
Elimination followed by introduction is the identity. Elimination followed by introduction is the identity.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
η-→ : ∀ {A B : Set} (f : A → B) → (λ{x → f x}) ≡ f η-→ : ∀ {A B : Set} (f : A → B) → (λ (x : A) → f x) ≡ f
η-→ {A} {B} f = extensionality η-helper η-→ {A} {B} f = extensionality η-helper
where where
η-helper : (x : A) → (λ (x : A) → f x) x ≡ f x η-helper : (x : A) → (λ (x : A) → f x) x ≡ f x
η-helper x = refl η-helper x = refl
\end{code} \end{code}
The proof depends on extensionality. The proof depends on extensionality.
@ -672,8 +671,8 @@ That is, the assertion that if either `A` holds or `B` holds then `C` holds
is the same as the assertion that if `A` holds then `C` holds and if is the same as the assertion that if `A` holds then `C` holds and if
`B` holds then `C` holds. The proof of the left inverse requires extensionality. `B` holds then `C` holds. The proof of the left inverse requires extensionality.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
→-distributes-⊎ : ∀ {A B C : Set} → (A ⊎ B → C) ≃ ((A → C) × (B → C)) →-distrib-⊎ : ∀ {A B C : Set} → (A ⊎ B → C) ≃ ((A → C) × (B → C))
→-distributes-⊎ = →-distrib-⊎ =
record record
{ to = λ{ f → ( (λ{ x → f (inj₁ x) }) , (λ{ y → f (inj₂ y) }) ) } { to = λ{ f → ( (λ{ x → f (inj₁ x) }) , (λ{ y → f (inj₂ y) }) ) }
; from = λ{ (g , h) → λ{ (inj₁ x) → g x ; (inj₂ y) → h y } } ; from = λ{ (g , h) → λ{ (inj₁ x) → g x ; (inj₂ y) → h y } }
@ -695,8 +694,8 @@ is the same as the assertion that if `A` holds then `B` holds and if
`A` holds then `C` holds. The proof of left inverse requires both extensionality `A` holds then `C` holds. The proof of left inverse requires both extensionality
and the rule `η-×` for products. and the rule `η-×` for products.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
→-distributes-× : ∀ {A B C : Set} → (A → B × C) ≃ ((A → B) × (A → C)) →-distrib-× : ∀ {A B C : Set} → (A → B × C) ≃ ((A → B) × (A → C))
→-distributes-× = →-distrib-× =
record record
{ to = λ{ f → ( (λ{ x → proj₁ (f x) }) , (λ{ y → proj₂ (f y)}) ) } { to = λ{ f → ( (λ{ x → proj₁ (f x) }) , (λ{ y → proj₂ (f y)}) ) }
; from = λ{ (g , h) → λ{ x → (g x , h x) } } ; from = λ{ (g , h) → λ{ x → (g x , h x) } }
@ -711,8 +710,8 @@ and the rule `η-×` for products.
Products distributes over sum, up to isomorphism. The code to validate Products distributes over sum, up to isomorphism. The code to validate
this fact is similar in structure to our previous results. this fact is similar in structure to our previous results.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
×-distributes-⊎ : ∀ {A B C : Set} → ((A ⊎ B) × C) ≃ ((A × C) ⊎ (B × C)) ×-distrib-⊎ : ∀ {A B C : Set} → ((A ⊎ B) × C) ≃ ((A × C) ⊎ (B × C))
×-distributes-⊎ = ×-distrib-⊎ =
record record
{ to = λ { ((inj₁ x) , z) → (inj₁ (x , z)) { to = λ { ((inj₁ x) , z) → (inj₁ (x , z))
; ((inj₂ y) , z) → (inj₂ (y , z)) ; ((inj₂ y) , z) → (inj₂ (y , z))
@ -731,8 +730,8 @@ this fact is similar in structure to our previous results.
Sums do not distribute over products up to isomorphism, but it is an embedding. Sums do not distribute over products up to isomorphism, but it is an embedding.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
⊎-distributes-× : ∀ {A B C : Set} → ((A × B) ⊎ C) ≲ ((A ⊎ C) × (B ⊎ C)) ⊎-distrib-× : ∀ {A B C : Set} → ((A × B) ⊎ C) ≲ ((A ⊎ C) × (B ⊎ C))
⊎-distributes-× = ⊎-distrib-× =
record record
{ to = λ { (inj₁ (x , y)) → (inj₁ x , inj₁ y) { to = λ { (inj₁ (x , y)) → (inj₁ x , inj₁ y)
; (inj₂ z) → (inj₂ z , inj₂ z) ; (inj₂ z) → (inj₂ z , inj₂ z)
@ -800,6 +799,7 @@ This chapter uses the following unicode.
⊎ U+228E MULTISET UNION (\u+) ⊎ U+228E MULTISET UNION (\u+)
U+22A4 DOWN TACK (\top) U+22A4 DOWN TACK (\top)
⊥ U+22A5 UP TACK (\bot) ⊥ U+22A5 UP TACK (\bot)
η U+03B7 GREEK SMALL LETTER ETA (\eta)
₁ U+2081 SUBSCRIPT ONE (\_1) ₁ U+2081 SUBSCRIPT ONE (\_1)
₂ U+2082 SUBSCRIPT TWO (\_2) ₂ U+2082 SUBSCRIPT TWO (\_2)
⇔ U+21D4 LEFT RIGHT DOUBLE ARROW (\<=>) ⇔ U+21D4 LEFT RIGHT DOUBLE ARROW (\<=>)

View file

@ -59,8 +59,9 @@ but on the left-hand side of the equation the argument has been instantiated to
which requires that `x` and `y` are the same. Hence, for the right-hand side of the equation which requires that `x` and `y` are the same. Hence, for the right-hand side of the equation
we need a term of type `x ≡ x`, and `refl` will do. we need a term of type `x ≡ x`, and `refl` will do.
It is instructive to develop `sym` interactively. It is instructive to develop `sym` interactively. To start, we supply
To start, we supply a variable for the argument on the left, and a hole for the body on the right: a variable for the argument on the left, and a hole for the body on
the right:
sym : ∀ {} {A : Set } {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x sym : ∀ {} {A : Set } {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x
sym e = {! !} sym e = {! !}
@ -75,8 +76,9 @@ If we go into the hole and type `C-C C-,` then Agda reports:
.A : Set . .A : Set .
. : .Agda.Primitive.Level . : .Agda.Primitive.Level
If in the hole we type `C-C C-C e` then Agda will instantiate `e` to all possible constructors, If in the hole we type `C-C C-C e` then Agda will instantiate `e` to
with one equation for each. There is only one possible constructor: all possible constructors, with one equation for each. There is only
one possible constructor:
sym : ∀ {} {A : Set } {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x sym : ∀ {} {A : Set } {x y : A} → x ≡ y → y ≡ x
sym refl = {! !} sym refl = {! !}

View file

@ -1,19 +1,16 @@
--- ---
title : "Negation: Negation, with Classical and Intuitionistic Logic" title : "Negation: Negation, with Intuitionistic and Classical Logic"
layout : page layout : page
permalink : /Negation permalink : /Negation
--- ---
This chapter introduces negation, and discusses intuitionistic
and classical logic.
## Imports ## Imports
\begin{code} \begin{code}
import Relation.Binary.PropositionalEquality as Eq
open Eq using (_≡_; refl; sym; trans; cong)
open Eq.≡-Reasoning
open import Isomorphism using (_≃_; ≃-sym; ≃-trans; _≲_) open import Isomorphism using (_≃_; ≃-sym; ≃-trans; _≲_)
open Isomorphism.≃-Reasoning
open import Data.Nat using (; zero; suc; _+_; _*_)
open import Data.Nat.Properties.Simple using (+-suc)
open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim) open import Data.Empty using (⊥; ⊥-elim)
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂) open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂) open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂)
@ -84,11 +81,11 @@ can conclude `¬ ¬ A` (evidenced by `¬¬-intro x`). Then from
`¬ ¬ ¬ A` and `¬ ¬ A` we have a contradiction (evidenced by `¬ ¬ ¬ A` and `¬ ¬ A` we have a contradiction (evidenced by
`¬¬¬x (¬¬-intro x)`. Hence we have shown `¬ A`. `¬¬¬x (¬¬-intro x)`. Hence we have shown `¬ A`.
Another law of logic is the *contrapositive*, Another law of logic is *contraposition*,
stating that if `A` implies `B`, then `¬ B` implies `¬ A`. stating that if `A` implies `B`, then `¬ B` implies `¬ A`.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
contrapositive : ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → (¬ B → ¬ A) contraposition : ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → (¬ B → ¬ A)
contrapositive f ¬y x = ¬y (f x) contraposition f ¬y x = ¬y (f x)
\end{code} \end{code}
Let `f` be evidence of `A → B` and let `¬y` be evidence of `¬ B`. We Let `f` be evidence of `A → B` and let `¬y` be evidence of `¬ B`. We
will show that assuming `A` leads to a contradiction, and hence will show that assuming `A` leads to a contradiction, and hence
@ -268,7 +265,7 @@ Philip Wadler, *International Conference on Functional Programming*, 2003.)
### Exercise ### Exercise
Prove the following four formulas are equivalent to each other, Prove the following three formulas are equivalent to each other,
and to the formulas `EM` and `⊎-Dual-+` given earlier. and to the formulas `EM` and `⊎-Dual-+` given earlier.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
¬¬-Elim Peirce Implication : Set₁ ¬¬-Elim Peirce Implication : Set₁
@ -277,61 +274,34 @@ Peirce = ∀ {A B : Set} → (((A → B) → A) → A)
Implication = ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → ¬ A ⊎ B Implication = ∀ {A B : Set} → (A → B) → ¬ A ⊎ B
\end{code} \end{code}
<!--
It turns out that an assertion such as `Set : Set` is paradoxical.
Therefore, there are an infinite number of different levels of sets,
where `Set lzero : Set lone` and `Set lone : Set ltwo`, and so on,
where `lone` is `lsuc lzero`, and `ltwo` is `lsuc lone`, analogous to
the way we represent the natural nuambers. So far, we have only used
the type `Set`, which is equivalent to `Set lzero`. Here, since each
of `double-negation` and the others defines a type, we need to use
`Set₁` as the "type of types".
-->
[NOTES]
Two halves of de Morgan's laws hold intuitionistically. The other two
halves are each equivalent to the law of double negation.
\begin{code}
dem1 : ∀ {A B : Set} → A × B → ¬ (¬ A ⊎ ¬ B)
dem1 (a , b) (inj₁ ¬a) = ¬a a
dem1 (a , b) (inj₂ ¬b) = ¬b b
dem2 : ∀ {A B : Set} → A ⊎ B → ¬ (¬ A × ¬ B)
dem2 (inj₁ a) (¬a , ¬b) = ¬a a
dem2 (inj₂ b) (¬a , ¬b) = ¬b b
\end{code}
For the other variant of De Morgan's law, one way is an isomorphism.
\begin{code}
-- dem-≃ : ∀ {A B : Set} → (¬ (A ⊎ B)) ≃ (¬ A × ¬ B)
-- dem-≃ = →-distributes-⊎
\end{code}
The other holds in only one direction.
\begin{code}
dem-half : ∀ {A B : Set} → ¬ A ⊎ ¬ B → ¬ (A × B)
dem-half (inj₁ ¬a) (a , b) = ¬a a
dem-half (inj₂ ¬b) (a , b) = ¬b b
\end{code}
The other variant does not appear to be equivalent to classical logic.
So that undermines my idea that basic propositions are either true
intuitionistically or equivalent to classical logic.
For several of the laws equivalent to classical logic, the reverse
direction holds in intuitionistic long.
\begin{code}
implication-inv : ∀ {A B : Set} → (¬ A ⊎ B) → A → B
implication-inv (inj₁ ¬a) a = ⊥-elim (¬a a)
implication-inv (inj₂ b) a = b
demorgan-inv : ∀ {A B : Set} → A ⊎ B → ¬ (¬ A × ¬ B)
demorgan-inv (inj₁ a) (¬a , ¬b) = ¬a a
demorgan-inv (inj₂ b) (¬a , ¬b) = ¬b b
\end{code}
### Exercise (`¬-stable`, `×-stable`)
Say that a formula is *stable* if double negation elimination holds for it.
\begin{code}
Stable : Set → Set
Stable A = ¬ ¬ A → A
\end{code}
Show that any negated formula is stable, and that the conjunction
of two stable formulas is stable.
\begin{code}
¬-Stable : Set₁
¬-Stable = ∀ {A : Set} → Stable (¬ A)
×-Stable : Set₁
×-Stable = ∀ {A B : Set} → Stable A → Stable B → Stable (A × B)
\end{code}
## Standard Prelude
Definitions similar to those in this chapter can be found in the standard library.
\begin{code}
import Relation.Nullary using (¬_)
import Relation.Nullary.Negation using (contraposition)
\end{code}
## Unicode
This chapter uses the following unicode.
¬ U+00AC NOT SIGN (\neg)

View file

@ -4,6 +4,8 @@ layout : page
permalink : /Quantifiers permalink : /Quantifiers
--- ---
This chapter introduces universal and existential quatification.
## Imports ## Imports
\begin{code} \begin{code}
@ -16,6 +18,8 @@ open import Data.Nat using (; zero; suc; _+_; _*_)
open import Data.Nat.Properties.Simple using (+-suc) open import Data.Nat.Properties.Simple using (+-suc)
open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_) open import Relation.Nullary using (¬_)
open import Function using (_∘_) open import Function using (_∘_)
open import Data.Product using (_×_; _,_; proj₁; proj₂)
open import Data.Sum using (_⊎_; inj₁; inj₂)
\end{code} \end{code}
In what follows, we will occasionally require [extensionality][extensionality]. In what follows, we will occasionally require [extensionality][extensionality].
@ -29,52 +33,73 @@ postulate
## Universals ## Universals
Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B[x]` which Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B x` which
contains `x` as a free variable, the universally quantified contains `x` as a free variable, the universally quantified
proposition `∀ (x : A) → B[x]` holds if for every term `M` of type proposition `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds if for every term `M` of type
`A` the proposition `B[M]` holds. Here `B[M]` stands for `A` the proposition `B M` holds. Here `B M` stands for
the proposition `B[x]` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by the proposition `B x` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by
`M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B[x]` but bound in `M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B x` but bound in
`∀ (x : A) → B[x]`. We formalise universal quantification using the `∀ (x : A) → B x`. We formalise universal quantification using the
dependent function type, which has appeared throughout this book. dependent function type, which has appeared throughout this book.
Evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B[x]` holds is of the form Evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds is of the form
λ (x : A) → N[x] λ (x : A) → N x
where `N[x]` is a term of type `B[x]`; here `N[x]` is a term and `B[x]` where `N x` is a term of type `B x`, and `N x` and `B x` both contain
is a proposition (or type) both containing as a free variable `x` of a free variable `x` of type `A`. Given a term `L` providing evidence
type `A`. Given a term `L` providing evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B[x]` that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds, and a term `M` of type `A`, the term `L
holds and a term `M` of type `A`, the term `L M` provides evidence M` provides evidence that `B M` holds. In other words, evidence that
that `B[M]` holds. In other words, evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B[x]` `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds is a function that converts a term `M` of type
holds is a function that converts a term `M` of type `A` into evidence `A` into evidence that `B M` holds.
that `B[M]` holds.
Put another way, if we know that `∀ (x : A) → B[x]` holds and that `M` Put another way, if we know that `∀ (x : A) → B x` holds and that `M`
is a term of type `A` then we may conclude that `B[M]` holds. In is a term of type `A` then we may conclude that `B M` holds.
medieval times, this rule was known by the name *dictum de omni*. \begin{code}
∀-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (∀ (x : A) → B x) → (M : A) → B M
∀-elim L M = L M
\end{code}
In medieval times, this rule was known by the name *dictum de omni*.
If we introduce a universal and the immediately eliminate it, we can Ordinary function types arise as the special case of dependent
always simplify the resulting term. Thus function types where the range does not depend on a variable drawn
from the domain. When an ordinary function is viewed as evidence of
(λ (x : A) → N[x]) M implication, both its domain and range are viewed as types of
evidence, whereas when a dependent function is viewed as evidence of a
simplifies to `N[M]` of type `B[M]`, where `N[M]` stands for the term universal, its domain is viewed as a data type and its range is viewed
`N[x]` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by `M` of type `A`. as a type of evidence. This is just a matter of interpretation, since
in Agda data types and types of evidence are indistinguishable.
Unlike with conjunction, disjunction, and implication, there is no simple Unlike with conjunction, disjunction, and implication, there is no simple
analogy between universals and arithmetic. analogy between universals and arithmetic.
### Exercise (`∀-distrib-×`)
Show that universals distribute over conjunction.
\begin{code}
∀-Distrib-× = ∀ {A : Set} {B C : A → Set} →
(∀ (x : A) → B x × C x) ≃ (∀ (x : A) → B x) × (∀ (x : A) → C x)
\end{code}
Compare this with the result (`→-distrib-×`) in Chapter [Connectives](Connectives).
### Exercise (`⊎∀-implies-∀⊎`)
Show that a disjunction of universals implies a universal of disjunctions.
\begin{code}
⊎∀-Implies-∀⊎ = ∀ {A : Set} { B C : A → Set } →
(∀ (x : A) → B x) ⊎ (∀ (x : A) → C x) → ∀ (x : A) → B x ⊎ C x
\end{code}
Does the converse also hold? If so, prove; if not, explain why.
## Existentials ## Existentials
Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B[x]` which Given a variable `x` of type `A` and a proposition `B x` which
contains `x` as a free variable, the existentially quantified contains `x` as a free variable, the existentially quantified
proposition `∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])` holds if for some term `M` of type proposition `∃[ x ] → B x` holds if for some term `M` of type
`A` the proposition `B[M]` holds. Here `B[M]` stands for `A` the proposition `B M` holds. Here `B M` stands for
the proposition `B[x]` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by the proposition `B x` with each free occurrence of `x` replaced by
`M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B[x]` but bound in `M`. The variable `x` appears free in `B x` but bound in
`∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])`. `∃[ x ] → B x`.
It is common to adopt a notation such as `∃[ x : A ]→ B[x]`, It is common to adopt a notation such as `∃[ x : A ]→ B[x]`,
which introduces `x` as a bound variable of type `A` that appears which introduces `x` as a bound variable of type `A` that appears
@ -85,18 +110,23 @@ to introduce `x` as a bound variable.
We formalise existential quantification by declaring a suitable We formalise existential quantification by declaring a suitable
inductive type. inductive type.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
data ∃ {A : Set} (B : A → Set) : Set where data ∃ (A : Set) (B : A → Set) : Set where
_,_ : (x : A) → B x → ∃ B _,_ : (x : A) → B x → ∃ A B
\end{code} \end{code}
Evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])` holds is of the form Evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])` holds is of the form
`(M , N)` where `M` is a term of type `A`, and `N` is evidence `(M , N)` where `M` is a term of type `A`, and `N` is evidence
that `B[M]` holds. that `B[M]` holds.
\begin{code}
syntax ∃ A (λ x → B) = ∃[ x ∈ A ] B
\end{code}
Given evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])` holds, and Given evidence that `∃ (λ (x : A) → B[x])` holds, and
given evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B[x] → C` holds, where `C` does given evidence that `∀ (x : A) → B[x] → C` holds, where `C` does
not contain `x` as a free variable, we may conclude that `C` holds. not contain `x` as a free variable, we may conclude that `C` holds.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
∃-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} → ∃ B → (∀ (x : A) → B x → C) → C ∃-elim : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} {C : Set} →
(∃[ x ∈ A ] B x) → (∀ (x : A) → B x → C) → C
∃-elim (M , N) P = P M N ∃-elim (M , N) P = P M N
\end{code} \end{code}
In other words, if we know for every `x` of type `A` that `B[x]` In other words, if we know for every `x` of type `A` that `B[x]`
@ -148,7 +178,7 @@ allows us to simplify `m + suc n` to `suc (m + n)`.
Here is the proof in the forward direction. Here is the proof in the forward direction.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
ev-ex : ∀ {n : } → even n → ∃(λ (m : ) → 2 * m ≡ n) ev-ex : ∀ {n : } → even n → ∃[ m ∈ ] (2 * m ≡ n)
ev-ex ev0 = (zero , refl) ev-ex ev0 = (zero , refl)
ev-ex (ev+2 ev) with ev-ex ev ev-ex (ev+2 ev) with ev-ex ev
... | (m , refl) = (suc m , lemma m) ... | (m , refl) = (suc m , lemma m)
@ -171,7 +201,7 @@ return a pair consisting of `suc m` and a proof that `2 * suc m ≡ suc
Here is the proof in the reverse direction. Here is the proof in the reverse direction.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
ex-ev : ∀ {n : } → ∃(λ (m : ) → 2 * m ≡ n) → even n ex-ev : ∀ {n : } → ∃[ m ∈ ] (2 * m ≡ n) → even n
ex-ev (zero , refl) = ev0 ex-ev (zero , refl) = ev0
ex-ev (suc m , refl) rewrite lemma m = ev+2 (ex-ev (m , refl)) ex-ev (suc m , refl) rewrite lemma m = ev+2 (ex-ev (m , refl))
\end{code} \end{code}
@ -196,11 +226,11 @@ disjuntion and universals are generalised conjunction, this
result is analogous to the one which tells us that negation result is analogous to the one which tells us that negation
of a disjuntion is isomorphic to a conjunction of negations. of a disjuntion is isomorphic to a conjunction of negations.
\begin{code} \begin{code}
¬∃∀ : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (¬ ∃ (λ (x : A) → B x)) ≃ ∀ (x : A) → ¬ B x ¬∃∀ : ∀ {A : Set} {B : A → Set} → (¬ ∃[ x ∈ A ] B x) ≃ ∀ (x : A) → ¬ B x
¬∃∀ = ¬∃∀ =
record record
{ to = λ { ¬∃bx x bx → ¬∃bx (x , bx) } { to = λ { ¬∃bx x bx → ¬∃bx (x , bx) }
; from = λ { ∀¬bx (x , bx) → ∀¬bx x bx } ; from = λ { ∀¬bx (x , bx) → ∀¬bx x bx }
; from∘to = λ { ¬∃bx → extensionality (λ { (x , bx) → refl }) } ; from∘to = λ { ¬∃bx → extensionality (λ { (x , bx) → refl }) }
; to∘from = λ { ∀¬bx → refl } ; to∘from = λ { ∀¬bx → refl }
} }
@ -223,7 +253,12 @@ requires extensionality.
*Exercise* Show `∃ (λ (x : A) → ¬ B x) → ¬ (∀ (x : A) → B x)`. *Exercise* Show `∃ (λ (x : A) → ¬ B x) → ¬ (∀ (x : A) → B x)`.
## Standard Prelude
Definitions similar to those in this chapter can be found in the standard library.
\begin{code}
import Data.Product using (∃)
\end{code}
## Unicode ## Unicode