5cf8064269
and exists.intro
784 lines
27 KiB
Org Mode
784 lines
27 KiB
Org Mode
* Lean Tutorial
|
||
|
||
** Introduction
|
||
|
||
Lean is an automatic and interactive theorem prover. It can be used to
|
||
create specifications, build mathematical libraries, and solve
|
||
constraints. In this tutorial, we introduce basic concepts, the logic
|
||
used in Lean, and the main commands.
|
||
|
||
** Getting started
|
||
|
||
We can use Lean in interactive or batch mode.
|
||
The following example just displays the message `hello world`.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
print "hello world"
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
All we have to do to run your first example is to call the =lean= executable
|
||
with the name of the text file that contains the command above.
|
||
If you saved the above command in the file =hello.lean=, then you just have
|
||
to execute
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC shell
|
||
lean hello.lean
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
As a more complex example, the next example defines a function that doubles
|
||
the input value.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
-- defines the double function
|
||
definition double (x : nat) := x + x
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
** Basics
|
||
|
||
We can also view Lean as a suite of tools for evaluating and processing
|
||
expressions representing terms, definitions, and theorems.
|
||
|
||
Every expression has a unique type in Lean. The command =check= returns the
|
||
type of a given expression.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
check true
|
||
check and
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The last command returns =Prop → Prop → Prop=. That is, the type of
|
||
=and= is a function that takes two _propositions_ and return a
|
||
proposition, =Prop= is the type of propositions.
|
||
|
||
The command =import= loads existing libraries and extensions.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
check nat.ge
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
We say =nat.ge= is a hierarchical name comprised of two parts: =nat= and =ge=.
|
||
|
||
The command =open= creates aliases based on a given prefix. The
|
||
command also imports notation, hints, and other features. We will
|
||
discuss its other applications later. Regarding aliases,
|
||
the following command creates aliases for all objects starting with
|
||
=nat=, and imports all notations defined in this namespace.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
check ge -- display the type of nat.ge
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The command =constant= assigns a type to an identifier. The following command postulates/assumes
|
||
that =n=, =m= and =o= have type =nat=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
constant n : nat
|
||
constant m : nat
|
||
constant o : nat
|
||
-- The command 'open nat' also imported the notation defined at the namespace 'nat'
|
||
check n + m
|
||
check n ≤ m
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The command =constants n m o : nat= can be used as a shorthand for the three commands above.
|
||
|
||
In Lean, proofs are also expressions, and all functionality provided for manipulating
|
||
expressions is also available for manipulating proofs. For example, =eq.refl n= is a proof
|
||
for =n = n=. In Lean, =eq.refl= is the reflexivity theorem.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
constant n : nat
|
||
check eq.refl n
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The command =axiom= postulates that a given proposition holds.
|
||
The following commands postulate two axioms =Ax1= and =Ax2= that state that =n = m= and
|
||
=m = o=. =Ax1= and =Ax2= are not just names. For example, =eq.trans Ax1 Ax2= is a proof that
|
||
=n = o=, where =eq.trans= is the transitivity theorem.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
constants m n o : nat
|
||
axiom Ax1 : n = m
|
||
axiom Ax2 : m = o
|
||
check eq.trans Ax1 Ax2
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The expression =eq.trans Ax1 Ax2= is just a function application like any other.
|
||
Moreover, in Lean, _propositions are types_. Any proposition =P= can be used
|
||
as a type. The elements of type =P= can be viewed as the proofs of =P=.
|
||
Moreover, in Lean, _proof checking is type checking_. For example, the Lean type checker
|
||
will reject the type incorrect term =eq.trans Ax2 Ax1=.
|
||
|
||
Because we use _proposition as types_, we must support _empty types_. For example,
|
||
the type =false= must be empty, since we don't have a proof for =false=.
|
||
|
||
Most systems based on the _propositions as types_ paradigm are based on constructive logic.
|
||
In Lean, we support classical and constructive logic. We can load
|
||
_classical axiom_ by using =import classical=. When the classical
|
||
extensions are loaded, the _excluded middle_ is a theorem,
|
||
and =em p= is a proof for =p ∨ ¬ p=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic.axioms.classical
|
||
constant p : Prop
|
||
check em p
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The commands =axiom= and =constant= are essentially the same command. We provide both
|
||
just to make Lean files more readable. We encourage users to use =axiom= only for
|
||
propositions, and =constant= for everything else.
|
||
|
||
Similarly, a theorem is just a definition. The following command defines a new theorem
|
||
called =nat_trans3=, and then use it to prove something else. In this
|
||
example, =eq.symm= is the symmetry theorem.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
theorem nat_trans3 (a b c d : nat) (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d :=
|
||
eq.trans (eq.trans H1 (eq.symm H2)) H3
|
||
|
||
-- Example using nat_trans3
|
||
constants x y z w : nat
|
||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||
check nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The theorem =nat_trans3= has 7 parameters, it takes for natural numbers =a=, =b=, =c= and =d=,
|
||
and three proofs showing that =a = b=, =c = b= and =c = d=, and returns a proof that =a = d=.
|
||
|
||
The theorem =nat_trans3= is somewhat inconvenient to use because it has 7 parameters.
|
||
However, the first four parameters can be inferred from the last 3. We can use =_= as a placeholder
|
||
that instructs Lean to synthesize this expression. The synthesis process is based on type inference, and it is
|
||
the most basic form of automation provided by Lean.
|
||
In the example above, we can use =check nat_trans3 _ _ _ _ Hxy Hzy Hzw=.
|
||
|
||
Lean also supports _implicit arguments_.
|
||
We mark implicit arguments using curly braces instead of parenthesis.
|
||
In the following example, we define the theorem =nat_trans3i= using
|
||
implicit arguments.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
theorem nat_trans3i {a b c d : nat} (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d :=
|
||
eq.trans (eq.trans H1 (eq.symm H2)) H3
|
||
|
||
-- Example using nat_trans3
|
||
constants x y z w : nat
|
||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||
check nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
It is identical to =nat_trans3=, the only difference is the use of curly braces.
|
||
Lean will (try to) infer the implicit arguments. The idea behind implicit arguments
|
||
is quite simple, we are just instructing Lean to automatically insert the placeholders
|
||
=_= for us.
|
||
|
||
Sometimes, Lean will not be able to infer the parameters automatically.
|
||
The annotation =@f= instructs Lean that we want to provide the
|
||
implicit arguments for =f= explicitly.
|
||
The theorems =eq.refl=, =eq.trans= and =eq.symm= all have implicit arguments.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
check @eq.refl
|
||
check @eq.symm
|
||
check @eq.trans
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
We can also instruct Lean to display all implicit arguments when it prints expressions.
|
||
This is useful when debugging non-trivial problems.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
constants a b c : nat
|
||
axiom H1 : a = b
|
||
axiom H2 : b = c
|
||
check eq.trans H1 H2
|
||
|
||
set_option pp.implicit true
|
||
-- Now, Lean will display all implicit arguments
|
||
check eq.trans H1 H2
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In the previous example, the =check= command stated that =eq.trans H1 H2=
|
||
has type =@eq ℕ a c=. The expression =a = c= is just notational convenience.
|
||
|
||
We have seen many occurrences of =Type=.
|
||
In Lean, the type of =nat= and =Prop= is =Type=.
|
||
What is the type of =Type=?
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
check Type
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Lean reports =Type : Type=, is it Lean inconsistent? Now, it is not.
|
||
Internally, Lean maintains a hierarchy of Types. We say each one of
|
||
them _lives_ in a universe. Lean is universe polymorphic, and by
|
||
default all universes are hidden from the user. Like implicit
|
||
arguments, we can instruct Lean to display the universe levels
|
||
explicitly.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
set_option pp.universes true
|
||
check Type
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In the command above, Lean reports that =Type.{l_1}= that lives in
|
||
universe =l_1= has type =Type.{succ l_1}=. That is, its type lives in
|
||
the universe =l_1 + 1=.
|
||
|
||
Definitions such as =eq.refl=, =eq.symm= and =eq.trans= are all universe
|
||
polymorphic.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
set_option pp.universes true
|
||
check @eq.refl
|
||
check @eq.symm
|
||
check @eq.trans
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Whenever we declare a new constant, Lean automatically infers the
|
||
universe parameters. We can also provide the universe levels
|
||
explicitly.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
|
||
definition id.{l} {A : Type.{l}} (a : A) : A := a
|
||
|
||
check id true
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The universes can be explicitly provided for each constant and =Type=
|
||
by using the notation =.{ ... }=. Unlike other systems, Lean does not
|
||
have _universe cumulativity_. That is, the type =Type.{i}= is *not* an
|
||
element of =Type.{j}= for =j > i=.
|
||
|
||
** Propositional logic
|
||
|
||
To manipulate formulas with a richer logical structure, it is important to master the notation Lean uses for building
|
||
composite logical expressions out of basic formulas using _logical connectives_. The logical connectives (=and=, =or=, =not=, etc)
|
||
are defined in the file [[../../library/standard/logic.lean][logic.lean]]. This file also defines notational convention for writing formulas
|
||
in a natural way. Here is a table showing the notation for the so called propositional (or Boolean) connectives.
|
||
|
||
|
||
| Ascii | Unicode | Definition |
|
||
|-------|-----------------------|--------------|
|
||
| true | | true |
|
||
| false | | false |
|
||
| not | ¬ | not |
|
||
| /\ | ∧ | and |
|
||
| \/ | ∨ | or |
|
||
| -> | → | |
|
||
| <-> | ↔ | iff |
|
||
|
||
=true= and =false= are logical constants to denote the true and false propositions. Logical negation is a unary operator just like
|
||
arithmetical negation on numbers. The other connectives are all binary operators. The meaning of the operators is the usual one.
|
||
The table above makes clear that Lean supports unicode characters. We can use Ascii or/and unicode versions.
|
||
Here is a simple example using the connectives above.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||
check ¬p → p ↔ false
|
||
check p ∨ q → q ∨ p
|
||
-- Ascii version
|
||
check p -> q -> p /\ q
|
||
check not p -> p <-> false
|
||
check p \/ q -> q \/ p
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Depending on the platform, Lean uses unicode characters by default when printing expressions. The following commands can be used to
|
||
change this behavior.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
set_option pp.unicode false
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||
set_option pp.unicode true
|
||
check p → q → p ∧ q
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Note that, it may seem that the symbols =->= and =→= are overloaded, and Lean uses them to represent implication and the type
|
||
of functions. Actually, they are not overloaded, they are the same symbols. In Lean, the Proposition =p → q= expression is also the type
|
||
of the functions that given a proof for =p=, returns a proof for =q=. This is very convenient for writing proofs.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
-- Hpq is a function that takes a proof for p and returns a proof for q
|
||
axiom Hpq : p → q
|
||
-- Hq is a proof/certificate for p
|
||
axiom Hp : p
|
||
-- The expression Hpq Hp is a proof/certificate for q
|
||
check Hpq Hp
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In composite expressions, the precedences of the various binary
|
||
connectives are in order of the above table, with =and= being the
|
||
strongest and =iff= the weakest. For example, =a ∧ b → c ∨ d ∧ e=
|
||
means =(a ∧ b) → (c ∨ (d ∧ e))=. All of them are right-associative.
|
||
So, =p ∧ q ∧ r= means =p ∧ (q ∧ r)=. The actual precedence and fixity of all
|
||
logical connectives is defined in the Lean
|
||
[[../../library/standard/logic.lean][logic definition file]].
|
||
Finally, =not=, =and=, =or= and =iff= are the actual names used when
|
||
defining the Boolean connectives. They can be used as any other function.
|
||
Lean supports _currying_ =and true= is a function from =Prop= to =Prop=.
|
||
|
||
** Functions
|
||
|
||
There are many variable-binding constructs in mathematics. Lean expresses
|
||
all of them using just one _abstraction_, which is a converse operation to
|
||
function application. Given a variable =x=, a type =A=, and a term =t= that
|
||
may or may not contain =x=, one can construct the so-called _lambda abstraction_
|
||
=fun x : A, t=, or using unicode notation =λ x : A, t=. Here is some simple
|
||
examples.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
check fun x : nat, x + 1
|
||
check fun x y : nat, x + 2 * y
|
||
check fun x y : Prop, not (x ∧ y)
|
||
check λ x : nat, x + 1
|
||
check λ (x : nat) (p : Prop), x = 0 ∨ p
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In many cases, Lean can automatically infer the type of the variable. Actually,
|
||
In all examples above, the type can be inferred automatically.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
check fun x, x + 1
|
||
check fun x y, x + 2 * y
|
||
check fun x y, not (x ∧ y)
|
||
check λ x, x + 1
|
||
check λ x p, x = 0 ∨ p
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
However, Lean will complain that it cannot infer the type of the
|
||
variable =x= in =fun x, x= because any type would work in this example.
|
||
|
||
The following example shows how to use lambda abstractions in
|
||
function applications
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1
|
||
check (fun x y, x + 2 * y) 1 2
|
||
check (fun x y, not (x ∧ y)) true false
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Lambda abstractions are also used to create proofs for propositions of the form =A → B=.
|
||
This should be natural since we can "view" =A → B= as the type of functions that given
|
||
a proof for =A= returns a proof for =B=.
|
||
For example, a proof for =p → p= is just =fun H : p, H= (the identity function).
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constant p : Prop
|
||
check fun H : p, H
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
** Definitional equality
|
||
|
||
The command =eval t= computes a normal form for the term =t=.
|
||
In Lean, we say two terms are _definitionally equal_ if the have the same
|
||
normal form. For example, the terms =(λ x : nat, x + 1) a= and =a + 1=
|
||
are definitionally equal. The Lean type/proof checker uses the normalizer when
|
||
checking types/proofs. So, we can prove that two definitionally equal terms
|
||
are equal using just =eq.refl=. Here is a simple example.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
theorem def_eq_th (a : nat) : ((λ x : nat, x + 1) a) = a + 1 := eq.refl (a+1)
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
** Provable equality
|
||
|
||
In the previous examples, we have used =nat_trans3 x y z w Hxy Hzy Hzw=
|
||
to show that =x = w=. In this case, =x= and =w= are not definitionally equal,
|
||
but they are provably equal in the environment that contains =nat_trans3= and
|
||
axioms =Hxy=, =Hzy= and =Hzw=.
|
||
|
||
** Proving
|
||
|
||
The Lean standard library contains basic theorems for creating proof terms. The
|
||
basic theorems are useful for creating manual proofs. The are also the
|
||
basic building blocks used by all automated proof engines available in
|
||
Lean. The theorems can be broken into three different categories:
|
||
introduction, elimination, and rewriting. First, we cover the introduction
|
||
and elimination theorems for the basic Boolean connectives.
|
||
|
||
*** And (conjunction)
|
||
|
||
The expression =and.intro H1 H2= creates a proof for =a ∧ b= using proofs
|
||
=H1 : a= and =H2 : b=. We say =and.intro= is the _and-introduction_ operation.
|
||
In the following example we use =and.intro= for creating a proof for
|
||
=p → q → p ∧ q=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check fun (Hp : p) (Hq : q), and.intro Hp Hq
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The expression =and.elim_left H= creates a proof =a= from a proof =H : a ∧ b=.
|
||
Similarly =and.elim_right H= is a proof for =b=. We say they are the _left/right and-eliminators_.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → p
|
||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and.elim_left H
|
||
-- Proof for p ∧ q → q
|
||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and.elim_right H
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Now, we prove =p ∧ q → q ∧ p= with the following simple proof term.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check fun H : p ∧ q, and.intro (and.elim_right H) (and.elim_left H)
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Note that the proof term is very similar to a function that just swaps the
|
||
elements of a pair.
|
||
|
||
*** (disjunction)
|
||
|
||
The expression =or.intro_left b H1= creates a proof for =a ∨ b= using a proof =H1 : a=.
|
||
Similarly, =or.intro_right a H2= creates a proof for =a ∨ b= using a proof =H2 : b=.
|
||
We say they are the _left/right or-introduction_.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
-- Proof for p → p ∨ q
|
||
check fun H : p, or.intro_left q H
|
||
-- Proof for q → p ∨ q
|
||
check fun H : q, or.intro_right p H
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The or-elimination rule is slightly more complicated. The basic idea is the
|
||
following, we can prove =c= from =a ∨ b=, by showing we can prove =c=
|
||
by assuming =a= or by assuming =b=. It is essentially a proof by cases.
|
||
=or.elim Hab Hac Hbc= takes three arguments =Hab : a ∨ b=, =Hac : a → c= and =Hbc : b → c= and produces a proof for =c=.
|
||
In the following example, we use =or.elim= to prove that =p v q → q ∨ p=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check fun H : p ∨ q,
|
||
or.elim H
|
||
(fun Hp : p, or.intro_right q Hp)
|
||
(fun Hq : q, or.intro_left p Hq)
|
||
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In most cases, the first argument of =or.intro_right= and
|
||
=or.intro_left= can be inferred automatically by Lean. Moreover, Lean
|
||
provides =or.inr= and =or.inl= as shorthands for =or.intro_right _=
|
||
and =or.intro_left _=. These two shorthands are extensively used in
|
||
the Lean standard library.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants p q : Prop
|
||
check fun H : p ∨ q,
|
||
or.elim H
|
||
(fun Hp : p, or.inr Hp)
|
||
(fun Hq : q, or.inl Hq)
|
||
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
*** Not (negation)
|
||
|
||
=not_intro H= produces a proof for =¬ a= from =H : a → false=. That is,
|
||
we obtain =¬ a= if we can derive =false= from =a=. The expression
|
||
=absurd Ha Hna= produces a proof for some =b= from =Ha : a= and =Hna : ¬ a=.
|
||
That is, we can deduce anything if we have =a= and =¬ a=.
|
||
We now use =not_intro= and =absurd= to produce a proof term for
|
||
=(a → b) → ¬b → ¬a=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants a b : Prop
|
||
check fun (Hab : a → b) (Hnb : ¬ b),
|
||
not.intro (fun Ha : a, absurd (Hab Ha) Hnb)
|
||
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In the standard library, =not a= is actually just an _abbreviation_
|
||
for =a → false=. Thus, we don't really need to use =not_intro=
|
||
explicitly.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants a b : Prop
|
||
check fun (Hab : a → b) (Hnb : ¬ b),
|
||
(fun Ha : a, Hnb (Hab Ha))
|
||
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Now, here is the proof term for =¬a → b → (b → a) → c=
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants a b c : Prop
|
||
check fun (Hna : ¬ a) (Hb : b) (Hba : b → a),
|
||
absurd (Hba Hb) Hna
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
*** Iff (if-and-only-if)
|
||
|
||
The expression =iff.intro H1 H2= produces a proof for =a ↔ b= from =H1 : a → b= and =H2 : b → a=.
|
||
=iff.elim_left H= produces a proof for =a → b= from =H : a ↔ b=. Similarly,
|
||
=iff.elim_right H= produces a proof for =b → a= from =H : a ↔ b=.
|
||
Here is the proof term for =a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a=
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants a b : Prop
|
||
check iff.intro
|
||
(fun H : a ∧ b, and.intro (and.elim_right H) (and.elim_left H))
|
||
(fun H : b ∧ a, and.intro (and.elim_right H) (and.elim_left H))
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In Lean, we can use =assume= instead of =fun= to make proof terms look
|
||
more like proofs found in text books.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
constants a b : Prop
|
||
check iff.intro
|
||
(assume H : a ∧ b, and.intro (and.elim_right H) (and.elim_left H))
|
||
(assume H : b ∧ a, and.intro (and.elim_right H) (and.elim_left H))
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
*** True and False
|
||
|
||
The expression =trivial= is a proof term for =true=, and =false_elim a H=
|
||
produces a proof for =a= from =H : false=.
|
||
|
||
*** Rewrite rules
|
||
|
||
*WARNING: We did not port this section to Lean 0.2 yet*
|
||
|
||
The Lean kernel also contains many theorems that are meant to be used as rewriting/simplification rules.
|
||
The conclusion of these theorems is of the form =t = s= or =t ↔ s=. For example, =and_id a= is proof term for
|
||
=a ∧ a ↔ a=. The Lean simplifier can use these theorems to automatically create proof terms for us.
|
||
The expression =(by simp [rule-set])= is similar to =_=, but it tells Lean to synthesize the proof term using the simplifier
|
||
using the rewrite rule set named =[rule-set]=. In the following example, we create a simple rewrite rule set
|
||
and use it to prove a theorem that would be quite tedious to prove by hand.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC
|
||
-- import module that defines several tactics/strategies including "simp"
|
||
import tactic
|
||
-- create a rewrite rule set with name 'simple'
|
||
rewrite_set simple
|
||
-- add some theorems to the rewrite rule set 'simple'
|
||
add_rewrite and_id and_truer and_truel and_comm and.assoc and_left_comm iff_id : simple
|
||
theorem th1 (a b : Bool) : a ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ∧ true ∧ b ↔ a ∧ b
|
||
:= (by simp simple)
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In Lean, we can combine manual and automated proofs in a natural way. We can manually write the proof
|
||
skeleton and use the =by= construct to invoke automated proof engines like the simplifier for filling the
|
||
tedious steps. Here is a very simple example.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC
|
||
theorem th2 (a b : Prop) : a ∧ b ↔ b ∧ a
|
||
:= iff.intro
|
||
(fun H : a ∧ b, (by simp simple))
|
||
(fun H : b ∧ a, (by simp simple))
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
** Dependent functions and quantifiers
|
||
|
||
Lean supports _dependent functions_. In type theory, they are also called dependent product types or Pi-types.
|
||
The idea is quite simple, suppose we have a type =A : Type=, and a family of types =B : A → Type= which assigns to each =a : A= a type =B a=. So a dependent function is a function whose range varies depending on its arguments.
|
||
In Lean, the dependent functions is written as =forall a : A, B a=,
|
||
=Pi a : A, B a=, =∀ x : A, B a=, or =Π x : A, B a=. We usually use
|
||
=forall= and =∀= for propositions, and =Pi= and =Π= for everything
|
||
else. In the previous examples, we have seen many examples of
|
||
dependent functions. The theorems =eq.refl=, =eq.trans= and =eq.symm=, and the
|
||
equality are all dependent functions.
|
||
|
||
The universal quantifier is just a dependent function.
|
||
In Lean, if we have a family of types =B : A → Prop=,
|
||
then =∀ x : A, B a= has type =Prop=.
|
||
This features complicates the Lean set-theoretic model, but it
|
||
improves usability.
|
||
Several theorem provers have a =forall elimination= (aka
|
||
instantiation) proof rule.
|
||
In Lean (and other systems based on proposition as types), this rule
|
||
is just function application.
|
||
In the following example we add an axiom stating that =f x= is =0=
|
||
forall =x=.
|
||
Then we instantiate the axiom using function application.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
constant f : nat → nat
|
||
axiom fzero : ∀ x, f x = 0
|
||
check fzero 1
|
||
constant a : nat
|
||
check fzero a
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
Since we instantiate quantifiers using function application, it is
|
||
natural to create proof terms for universal quantifiers using lambda
|
||
abstraction. In the following example, we create a proof term showing that for all
|
||
=x= and =y=, =f x = f y=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
constant f : nat → nat
|
||
axiom fzero : ∀ x, f x = 0
|
||
check λ x y, eq.trans (fzero x) (eq.symm (fzero y))
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
We can view the proof term above as a simple function or "recipe" for showing that
|
||
=f x = f y= for any =x= and =y=. The function "invokes" =fzero= for creating
|
||
proof terms for =f x = 0= and =f y = 0=. Then, it uses symmetry =eq.symm= to create
|
||
a proof term for =0 = f y=. Finally, transitivity is used to combine the proofs
|
||
for =f x = 0= and =0 = f y=.
|
||
|
||
In Lean, the existential quantifier can be written as =exists x : A, B
|
||
x= or =∃ x : A, B x=. Actually both versions are just
|
||
notational convenience for =Exists (fun x : A, B x)=. That is, the existential quantifier
|
||
is actually a constant defined in the file =logic.lean=.
|
||
This file also defines the =exists.intro= and =exists.elim=.
|
||
To build a proof for =∃ x : A, B x=, we should provide a term =w : A= and a proof term =Hw : B w= to =exists.intro=.
|
||
We say =w= is the witness for the existential introduction. In previous examples,
|
||
=nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw= was a proof term for =x = w=. Then, we can create a proof term
|
||
for =∃ a : nat, a = w= using
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
theorem nat_trans3i {a b c d : nat} (H1 : a = b) (H2 : c = b) (H3 : c = d) : a = d :=
|
||
eq.trans (eq.trans H1 (eq.symm H2)) H3
|
||
|
||
constants x y z w : nat
|
||
axiom Hxy : x = y
|
||
axiom Hzy : z = y
|
||
axiom Hzw : z = w
|
||
|
||
theorem ex_a_eq_w : exists a, a = w := exists.intro x (nat_trans3i Hxy Hzy Hzw)
|
||
check ex_a_eq_w
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
|
||
Note that =exists.intro= also has implicit arguments. For example, Lean has to infer the implicit argument
|
||
=P : A → Bool=, a predicate (aka function to Prop). This creates complications. For example, suppose
|
||
we have =Hg : g 0 0 = 0= and we invoke =exists.intro 0 Hg=. There are different possible values for =P=.
|
||
Each possible value corresponds to a different theorem: =∃ x, g x x = x=, =∃ x, g x x = 0=,
|
||
=∃ x, g x 0 = x=, etc. Lean uses the context where =exists.intro= occurs to infer the users intent.
|
||
In the example above, we were trying to prove the theorem =∃ a, a = w=. So, we are implicitly telling
|
||
Lean how to choose =P=. In the following example, we demonstrate this issue. We ask Lean to display
|
||
the implicit arguments using the option =pp.implicit=. We see that each instance of =exists.intro 0 Hg=
|
||
has different values for the implicit argument =P=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
check @exists.intro
|
||
constant g : nat → nat → nat
|
||
axiom Hg : g 0 0 = 0
|
||
theorem gex1 : ∃ x, g x x = x := exists.intro 0 Hg
|
||
theorem gex2 : ∃ x, g x 0 = x := exists.intro 0 Hg
|
||
theorem gex3 : ∃ x, g 0 0 = x := exists.intro 0 Hg
|
||
theorem gex4 : ∃ x, g x x = 0 := exists.intro 0 Hg
|
||
set_option pp.implicit true -- display implicit arguments
|
||
check gex1
|
||
check gex2
|
||
check gex3
|
||
check gex4
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
We can view =exists.intro= (aka existential introduction) as an information hiding procedure.
|
||
We are "hiding" what is the witness for some fact. The existential elimination performs the opposite
|
||
operation. The =exists.elim= theorem allows us to prove some proposition =B= from =∃ x : A, B x=
|
||
if we can derive =B= using an "abstract" witness =w= and a proof term =Hw : B w=.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import logic
|
||
check @exists.elim
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
In the following example, we define =even a= as =∃ b, a = 2*b=, and then we show that the sum
|
||
of two even numbers is an even number.
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
|
||
definition even (a : nat) := ∃ b, a = 2*b
|
||
theorem EvenPlusEven {a b : nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b) :=
|
||
exists.elim H1 (fun (w1 : nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1),
|
||
exists.elim H2 (fun (w2 : nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2),
|
||
exists.intro (w1 + w2)
|
||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : {Hw1}
|
||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : {Hw2}
|
||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : eq.symm !mul.distr_left)))
|
||
|
||
#+END_SRC
|
||
|
||
The example above also uses [[./calc.org][calculational proofs]] to show that =a + b = 2*(w1 + w2)=.
|
||
The =calc= construct is just syntax sugar for creating proofs using transitivity and substitution.
|
||
|
||
In Lean, we can use =obtain _, from _, _= as syntax sugar for =exists.elim=.
|
||
With this macro we can write the example above in a more natural way
|
||
|
||
#+BEGIN_SRC lean
|
||
import data.nat
|
||
open nat
|
||
definition even (a : nat) := ∃ b, a = 2*b
|
||
theorem EvenPlusEven {a b : nat} (H1 : even a) (H2 : even b) : even (a + b) :=
|
||
obtain (w1 : nat) (Hw1 : a = 2*w1), from H1,
|
||
obtain (w2 : nat) (Hw2 : b = 2*w2), from H2,
|
||
exists.intro (w1 + w2)
|
||
(calc a + b = 2*w1 + b : {Hw1}
|
||
... = 2*w1 + 2*w2 : {Hw2}
|
||
... = 2*(w1 + w2) : eq.symm !mul.distr_left)
|
||
#+END_SRC
|