5.8 KiB
- Introduction
- Big picture
- The logical framework
- Reasoning about abstractions
- Constructive and classical logic
- Lean interfaces
- Future work
- Future work (cont.)
- Example
Introduction
- Lean is a new automated/interactive theorem prover.
-
It is a powerful system for
- reasoning about complex systems
- reasoning about mathematics
- proving claims about both
- It aims to bring the automated and interactive theorem proving worlds together.
Big picture
-
Proving should be as easy as programming.
- We can teach logic to any kid that knows how to program.
-
Lean as a new engine for software verification tools.
- Lean offers a much richer language.
- We offer multiple APIs (C/C++, Lua, Lean, Javascript).
-
Impact on education.
- We want to have a "live" and formalized version of Euclid's Elements (book 1).
- Natural deduction style proofs are like flowcharts, they should be "eradicated".
- Revolutionize mathematics.
The logical framework
-
Lean's default logical framework is a version of the Calculus of Constructions with:
- an impredicative, proof irrelevant type `Prop` of propositions.
- a non-cumulative hierarchy of universes `Type 1`, `Type 2`, … above `Prop`
- universe polymorphism
- inductively defined types
-
Features
- the kernel is constructive
- smooth support for classical logic
- support for Homotopy Type Theory (HoTT)
Reasoning about abstractions
- At CMU, Jeremy Avigad, Floris van Doorn and Jakob von Raumer are formalizing Category theory and Homotopy type theory using Lean.
-
Why this relevant?
- It is stressing all lean major components.
- If we can do it, then we can do anything.
- Test if we can reason about higher-level abstractions.
- In CS, we also want to reason about higher-level abstractions.
Constructive and classical logic
- Almost everything we do is constructive, but we want to support classical users
smoothly.
inductive decidable [class] (p : Prop) : Type :=
inl : p → decidable p,
inr : ¬p → decidable p
- `decidable` is the type class of decidable propositions.
- The excluded middle is a theorem for decidable propositions.
theorem em (p : Prop) [H : decidable p] : p ∨ ¬p :=
induction_on H (assume Hp, or.inl Hp) (assume Hnp, or.inr Hnp)
- The `[…]` instructs lean that `H : decidable p` is an implicit argument,
and it should be synthesized automatically using type-class instantiation
- We have populated the lean standard library with many decidability results.
Example: the conjunction of two decidable propositions is decidable
variables p q : Prop
definition and_decidable [instance] (Hp : decidable p) (Hq : decidable q) : decidable (p ∧ q) :=
rec_on Hp
(assume Hp : p, rec_on Hq
(assume Hq : q, inl (and.intro Hp Hq))
(assume Hnq : ¬q, inr (and.not_right p Hnq)))
(assume Hnp : ¬p, inr (and.not_left q Hnp))
definition decidable_eq (A : Type) := Π (a b : A), decidable (a = b)
protected definition nat.has_decidable_eq [instance] : decidable_eq ℕ :=
take n m : ℕ,
...
- We define `if-then-else` expressions as
definition ite (c : Prop) [H : decidable c] {A : Type} (t e : A) : A :=
decidable.rec_on H (assume Hc, t) (assume Hnc, e)
notation `if` c `then` t:45 `else` e:45 := ite c t e
Lean will only allow us to use `if-then-else` for decidable propositions. By default, it will try to prove decidability using type-class resolution. If we write
import standard
open nat decidable
variables a b : nat
check if a = b ∧ a > 0 then a else b
Lean automatically synthesizes the implicit argument `H : decidable c`.
``` (and_decidable (nat.has_decidable_eq a b) (ge_decidable a (succ 0))) ```
- When we import the classical axioms, then we can prove that all propositions are decidable.
theorem prop_decidable [instance] (a : Prop) : decidable a
Moreover, we can write arbitrary `if-then-else` expressions.
if riemman_hypothesis then t else e
Lean interfaces
…
Future work
- Definitional package: convert "recursive equations" into recursors.
The user wants to write
append : list A → list A → list A
append nil t = t
append (x :: l) t = x :: (append l t)
instead of
definition append (s t : list A) : list A :=
rec_on s
t
(λx l u, x::u)
-
Automation
- Simplifier
- SMT-like engines
- Arithmetic
Future work (cont.)
- Next semester, we will have a course on theorem proving based on Lean at CMU
- Tutorial at CADE
Example
import algebra.category
open eq.ops category functor natural_transformation
variables {ob₁ ob₂ : Type} {C : category ob₁} {D : category ob₂} {F G H : C ⇒ D}
-- infix `↣`:20 := hom
-- F G H are functors
-- η θ are natural transformations
-- A natural transformation provides a way of transforming one functor
-- into another while respecting the internal structure.
-- A natural transformation can be considered to be a "morphism of functors".
-- http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Natural_transformation
definition nt_compose (η : G ⟹ H) (θ : F ⟹ G) : F ⟹ H :=
natural_transformation.mk
(take a, η a ∘ θ a)
(take a b f, calc
H f ∘ (η a ∘ θ a) = (H f ∘ η a) ∘ θ a : !assoc
... = (η b ∘ G f) ∘ θ a : {naturality η f}
... = η b ∘ (G f ∘ θ a) : !assoc⁻¹
... = η b ∘ (θ b ∘ F f) : {naturality θ f} -- {@naturality _ _ _ _ _ _ θ _ _ f}
... = (η b ∘ θ b) ∘ F f : !assoc)
-- check nt_compose
-- check @nt_compose
exit
set_option pp.implicit true
set_option pp.full_names true
set_option pp.notation false
set_option pp.coercions true
-- set_option pp.universes true
print definition nt_compose