2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
(** Formal Reasoning About Programs <http://adam.chlipala.net/frap/>
|
|
|
|
* Supplementary Coq material: proof by reflection
|
|
|
|
* Author: Adam Chlipala
|
|
|
|
* License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/
|
|
|
|
* Much of the material comes from CPDT <http://adam.chlipala.net/cpdt/> by the same author. *)
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 19:05:46 +00:00
|
|
|
Require Import Frap.
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Set Implicit Arguments.
|
|
|
|
Set Asymmetric Patterns.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Our last "aside" on effective Coq use (in IntroToProofScripting.v)
|
|
|
|
* highlighted a very heuristic approach to proving. As an alternative, we will
|
|
|
|
* study a technique called proof by reflection. We will write, in Gallina (the
|
|
|
|
* logical functional-programming language of Coq), decision procedures with
|
|
|
|
* proofs of correctness, and we will appeal to these procedures in writing very
|
|
|
|
* short proofs. Such a proof is checked by running the decision procedure.
|
|
|
|
* The term _reflection_ applies because we will need to translate Gallina
|
|
|
|
* propositions into values of inductive types representing syntax, so that
|
|
|
|
* Gallina programs may analyze them, and translating such a term back to the
|
|
|
|
* original form is called _reflecting_ it. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Proving Evenness *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Proving that particular natural number constants are even is certainly
|
|
|
|
* something we would rather have happen automatically. The Ltac-programming
|
|
|
|
* techniques that we learned last week make it easy to implement such a
|
|
|
|
* procedure. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Inductive isEven : nat -> Prop :=
|
|
|
|
| Even_O : isEven O
|
|
|
|
| Even_SS : forall n, isEven n -> isEven (S (S n)).
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac prove_even := repeat constructor.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem even_256 : isEven 256.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
prove_even.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Set Printing All.
|
|
|
|
Print even_256.
|
|
|
|
Unset Printing All.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Here we see a term of Coq's core proof language, which we don't explain in
|
|
|
|
* detail, but roughly speaking such a term is a syntax tree recording which
|
|
|
|
* lemmas were used, and how their quantifiers were instantiated, to prove a
|
|
|
|
* theorem. This Ltac procedure always works (at least on machines with
|
|
|
|
* infinite resources), but it has a serious drawback, which we see when we
|
|
|
|
* print the proof it generates that 256 is even. The final proof term has
|
|
|
|
* length super-linear in the input value, which we reveal with
|
|
|
|
* [Set Printing All], to disable all syntactic niceties and show every node of
|
|
|
|
* the internal proof AST. The problem is that each [Even_SS] application needs
|
|
|
|
* a choice of [n], and we wind up giving every even number from 0 to 254 in
|
|
|
|
* that position, at some point or another, for quadratic proof-term size.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* It is also unfortunate not to have static typing guarantees that our tactic
|
|
|
|
* always behaves appropriately. Other invocations of similar tactics might
|
|
|
|
* fail with dynamic type errors, and we would not know about the bugs behind
|
|
|
|
* these errors until we happened to attempt to prove complex enough goals.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* The techniques of proof by reflection address both complaints. We will be
|
|
|
|
* able to write proofs like in the example above with constant size overhead
|
|
|
|
* beyond the size of the input, and we will do it with verified decision
|
|
|
|
* procedures written in Gallina. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint check_even (n : nat) : bool :=
|
|
|
|
match n with
|
|
|
|
| 0 => true
|
|
|
|
| 1 => false
|
|
|
|
| S (S n') => check_even n'
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* To prove [check_even] sound, we need two IH strengthenings:
|
|
|
|
* - Effectively switch to _strong induction_ with an extra numeric variable,
|
|
|
|
* asserted to be less than the one we induct on.
|
|
|
|
* - Express both cases for how a [check_even] test might turn out. *)
|
|
|
|
Lemma check_even_ok' : forall n n', n' < n
|
|
|
|
-> if check_even n' then isEven n' else ~isEven n'.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct n; simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
linear_arithmetic.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
cases n'; simplify.
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
cases n'; simplify.
|
|
|
|
propositional.
|
|
|
|
invert H0.
|
|
|
|
specialize (IHn n').
|
|
|
|
cases (check_even n').
|
|
|
|
constructor.
|
|
|
|
apply IHn.
|
|
|
|
linear_arithmetic.
|
|
|
|
propositional.
|
|
|
|
invert H0.
|
|
|
|
apply IHn.
|
|
|
|
linear_arithmetic.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem check_even_ok : forall n, check_even n = true -> isEven n.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
assert (n < S n) by linear_arithmetic.
|
|
|
|
apply check_even_ok' in H0.
|
|
|
|
rewrite H in H0.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* As this theorem establishes, the function [check_even] may be viewed as a
|
|
|
|
* _verified decision procedure_. It is now trivial to write a tactic to prove
|
|
|
|
* evenness. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac prove_even_reflective :=
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- isEven ?N] => apply check_even_ok; reflexivity
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem even_256' : isEven 256.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
prove_even_reflective.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Set Printing All.
|
|
|
|
Print even_256'.
|
|
|
|
Unset Printing All.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Notice that only one [nat] appears as an argument to an applied lemma, and
|
|
|
|
* that's the original number to test for evenness. Proof-term size scales
|
|
|
|
* linearly.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* What happens if we try the tactic with an odd number? *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem even_255 : isEven 255.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
(*prove_even_reflective.*)
|
|
|
|
Abort.
|
|
|
|
(* Coq reports that [reflexivity] can't prove [false = true], which makes
|
|
|
|
* perfect sense! *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Our tactic [prove_even_reflective] is reflective because it performs a
|
|
|
|
* proof-search process (a trivial one, in this case) wholly within Gallina. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * Reifying the Syntax of a Trivial Tautology Language *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We might also like to have reflective proofs of trivial tautologies like
|
|
|
|
* this one: *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem true_galore : (True /\ True) -> (True \/ (True /\ (True -> True))).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print true_galore.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* As we might expect, the proof that [tauto] builds contains explicit
|
|
|
|
* applications of deduction rules. For large formulas, this can add a linear
|
|
|
|
* amount of proof-size overhead, beyond the size of the input.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* To write a reflective procedure for this class of goals, we will need to get
|
|
|
|
* into the actual "reflection" part of "proof by reflection." It is impossible
|
2018-03-07 01:29:57 +00:00
|
|
|
* to case-analyze a [Prop] in any way in Gallina. We must _reify_ [Prop] into
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
* some type that we _can_ analyze. This inductive type is a good candidate: *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* begin thide *)
|
|
|
|
Inductive taut : Set :=
|
|
|
|
| TautTrue : taut
|
|
|
|
| TautAnd : taut -> taut -> taut
|
|
|
|
| TautOr : taut -> taut -> taut
|
|
|
|
| TautImp : taut -> taut -> taut.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We write a recursive function to _reflect_ this syntax back to [Prop]. Such
|
|
|
|
* functions are also called _interpretation functions_, and we have used them
|
|
|
|
* in previous examples to give semantics to small programming languages. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint tautDenote (t : taut) : Prop :=
|
|
|
|
match t with
|
|
|
|
| TautTrue => True
|
|
|
|
| TautAnd t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 /\ tautDenote t2
|
|
|
|
| TautOr t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 \/ tautDenote t2
|
|
|
|
| TautImp t1 t2 => tautDenote t1 -> tautDenote t2
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* It is easy to prove that every formula in the range of [tautDenote] is
|
|
|
|
* true. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem tautTrue : forall t, tautDenote t.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct t; simplify; propositional.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* To use [tautTrue] to prove particular formulas, we need to implement the
|
|
|
|
* syntax-reification process. A recursive Ltac function does the job. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac tautReify P :=
|
|
|
|
match P with
|
|
|
|
| True => TautTrue
|
|
|
|
| ?P1 /\ ?P2 =>
|
|
|
|
let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
|
|
|
let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
|
|
|
constr:(TautAnd t1 t2)
|
|
|
|
| ?P1 \/ ?P2 =>
|
|
|
|
let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
|
|
|
let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
|
|
|
constr:(TautOr t1 t2)
|
|
|
|
| ?P1 -> ?P2 =>
|
|
|
|
let t1 := tautReify P1 in
|
|
|
|
let t2 := tautReify P2 in
|
|
|
|
constr:(TautImp t1 t2)
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* With [tautReify] available, it is easy to finish our reflective tactic. We
|
|
|
|
* look at the goal formula, reify it, and apply [tautTrue] to the reified
|
|
|
|
* formula. Recall that the [change] tactic replaces a conclusion formula with
|
|
|
|
* another that is equal to it, as shown by partial execution of terms. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac obvious :=
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- ?P ] =>
|
|
|
|
let t := tautReify P in
|
|
|
|
change (tautDenote t); apply tautTrue
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We can verify that [obvious] solves our original example, with a proof term
|
|
|
|
* that does not mention details of the proof. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem true_galore' : (True /\ True) -> (True \/ (True /\ (True -> True))).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
obvious.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Set Printing All.
|
|
|
|
Print true_galore'.
|
|
|
|
Unset Printing All.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* It is worth considering how the reflective tactic improves on a pure-Ltac
|
|
|
|
* implementation. The formula-reification process is just as ad-hoc as before,
|
|
|
|
* so we gain little there. In general, proofs will be more complicated than
|
|
|
|
* formula translation, and the "generic proof rule" that we apply here _is_ on
|
|
|
|
* much better formal footing than a recursive Ltac function. The dependent
|
|
|
|
* type of the proof guarantees that it "works" on any input formula. This
|
|
|
|
* benefit is in addition to the proof-size improvement that we have already
|
|
|
|
* seen.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* It may also be worth pointing out that our previous example of evenness
|
|
|
|
* testing used a test [check_even] that could sometimes fail, while here we
|
|
|
|
* avoid the extra Boolean test by identifying a syntactic class of formulas
|
|
|
|
* that are always true by construction. Of course, many interesting proof
|
|
|
|
* steps don't have that structure, so let's look at an example that still
|
|
|
|
* requires extra proving after the reflective step. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(** * A Monoid Expression Simplifier *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Proof by reflection does not require encoding of all of the syntax in a goal.
|
|
|
|
* We can insert "variables" in our syntax types to allow injection of arbitrary
|
|
|
|
* pieces, even if we cannot apply specialized reasoning to them. In this
|
|
|
|
* section, we explore that possibility by writing a tactic for normalizing
|
|
|
|
* monoid equations. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Section monoid.
|
|
|
|
Variable A : Set.
|
|
|
|
Variable e : A.
|
|
|
|
Variable f : A -> A -> A.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Infix "+" := f.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hypothesis assoc : forall a b c, (a + b) + c = a + (b + c).
|
|
|
|
Hypothesis identl : forall a, e + a = a.
|
|
|
|
Hypothesis identr : forall a, a + e = a.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We add variables and hypotheses characterizing an arbitrary instance of the
|
|
|
|
* algebraic structure of monoids. We have an associative binary operator and
|
|
|
|
* an identity element for it.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* It is easy to define an expression-tree type for monoid expressions. A
|
|
|
|
* [Var] constructor is a "catch-all" case for subexpressions that we cannot
|
|
|
|
* model. These subexpressions could be actual Gallina variables, or they
|
|
|
|
* could just use functions that our tactic is unable to understand. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Inductive mexp : Set :=
|
|
|
|
| Ident : mexp
|
|
|
|
| Var : A -> mexp
|
|
|
|
| Op : mexp -> mexp -> mexp.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Next, we write an interpretation function. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint mdenote (me : mexp) : A :=
|
|
|
|
match me with
|
|
|
|
| Ident => e
|
|
|
|
| Var v => v
|
|
|
|
| Op me1 me2 => mdenote me1 + mdenote me2
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We will normalize expressions by flattening them into lists, via
|
|
|
|
* associativity, so it is helpful to have a denotation function for lists of
|
|
|
|
* monoid values. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint mldenote (ls : list A) : A :=
|
|
|
|
match ls with
|
|
|
|
| nil => e
|
|
|
|
| x :: ls' => x + mldenote ls'
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* The flattening function itself is easy to implement. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint flatten (me : mexp) : list A :=
|
|
|
|
match me with
|
|
|
|
| Ident => []
|
|
|
|
| Var x => [x]
|
|
|
|
| Op me1 me2 => flatten me1 ++ flatten me2
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* This function has a straightforward correctness proof in terms of our
|
|
|
|
* [denote] functions. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Lemma flatten_correct' : forall ml2 ml1,
|
|
|
|
mldenote (ml1 ++ ml2) = mldenote ml1 + mldenote ml2.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induction ml1; simplify; equality.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Hint Rewrite flatten_correct'.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem flatten_correct : forall me, mdenote me = mldenote (flatten me).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induction me; simplify; equality.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now it is easy to prove a theorem that will be the main tool behind our
|
|
|
|
* simplification tactic. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem monoid_reflect : forall me1 me2,
|
|
|
|
mldenote (flatten me1) = mldenote (flatten me2)
|
|
|
|
-> mdenote me1 = mdenote me2.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
simplify; repeat rewrite flatten_correct; assumption.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We implement reification into the [mexp] type. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac reify me :=
|
|
|
|
match me with
|
|
|
|
| e => Ident
|
|
|
|
| ?me1 + ?me2 =>
|
|
|
|
let r1 := reify me1 in
|
|
|
|
let r2 := reify me2 in
|
|
|
|
constr:(Op r1 r2)
|
|
|
|
| _ => constr:(Var me)
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* The final [monoid] tactic works on goals that equate two monoid terms. We
|
|
|
|
* reify each and change the goal to refer to the reified versions, finishing
|
|
|
|
* off by applying [monoid_reflect] and simplifying uses of [mldenote]. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac monoid :=
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- ?me1 = ?me2 ] =>
|
|
|
|
let r1 := reify me1 in
|
|
|
|
let r2 := reify me2 in
|
|
|
|
change (mdenote r1 = mdenote r2);
|
|
|
|
apply monoid_reflect; simplify
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We can make short work of theorems like this one: *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem t1 : forall a b c d, a + b + c + d = a + (b + c) + d.
|
|
|
|
simplify; monoid.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Our tactic has canonicalized both sides of the equality, such that we can
|
|
|
|
* finish the proof by reflexivity. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
reflexivity.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* It is interesting to look at the form of the proof. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Set Printing All.
|
|
|
|
Print t1.
|
|
|
|
Unset Printing All.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* The proof term contains only restatements of the equality operands in
|
|
|
|
* reified form, followed by a use of reflexivity on the shared canonical
|
|
|
|
* form. *)
|
|
|
|
End monoid.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Extensions of this basic approach are used in the implementations of the
|
|
|
|
* [ring] and [field] tactics that come packaged with Coq. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 16:50:29 +00:00
|
|
|
(** * Set Simplification for Model Checking *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Let's take a closer look at model-checking proofs like from last class. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Here's a simple transition system, where state is just a [nat], and where
|
|
|
|
* each step subtracts 1 or 2. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Inductive subtract_step : nat -> nat -> Prop :=
|
|
|
|
| Subtract1 : forall n, subtract_step (S n) n
|
|
|
|
| Subtract2 : forall n, subtract_step (S (S n)) n.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Definition subtract_sys (n : nat) : trsys nat := {|
|
|
|
|
Initial := {n};
|
|
|
|
Step := subtract_step
|
|
|
|
|}.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Lemma subtract_ok :
|
|
|
|
invariantFor (subtract_sys 5)
|
|
|
|
(fun n => n <= 5).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
eapply invariant_weaken.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply multiStepClosure_ok.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
(* Here we'll see that the Frap libary uses slightly different, optimized
|
|
|
|
* versions of the model-checking relations. For instance, [multiStepClosure]
|
|
|
|
* takes an extra set argument, the _worklist_ recording newly discovered
|
|
|
|
* states. There is no point in following edges out of states that were
|
|
|
|
* already known at previous steps. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now, some more manual iterations: *)
|
|
|
|
eapply MscStep.
|
|
|
|
closure.
|
|
|
|
(* Ew. What a big, ugly set expression. Let's shrink it down to something
|
|
|
|
* more readable, with duplicates removed, etc. *)
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
(* How does the Frap library do that? Proof by reflection is a big part of
|
|
|
|
* it! Let's develop a baby version of that automation. The full-scale
|
|
|
|
* version is in file Sets.v. *)
|
|
|
|
Abort.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We'll specialize our representation to unions of set literals, whose elements
|
|
|
|
* are constant [nat]s. The full-scale version in the library is more
|
|
|
|
* flexible. *)
|
|
|
|
Inductive setexpr :=
|
|
|
|
| Literal (ns : list nat)
|
|
|
|
| Union (e1 e2 : setexpr).
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Here's what our expressions mean. *)
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint setexprDenote (e : setexpr) : set nat :=
|
|
|
|
match e with
|
|
|
|
| Literal ns => constant ns
|
|
|
|
| Union e1 e2 => setexprDenote e1 \cup setexprDenote e2
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Simplification reduces all expressions to flat, duplicate-free set
|
|
|
|
* literals. *)
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint normalize (e : setexpr) : list nat :=
|
|
|
|
match e with
|
|
|
|
| Literal ns => dedup ns
|
|
|
|
| Union e1 e2 => setmerge (normalize e1) (normalize e2)
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
(* Here we use functions [dedup] and [setmerge] from the Sets module, which is
|
|
|
|
* especially handy because that module has proved some key theorems about
|
|
|
|
* them. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Let's prove that normalization doesn't change meaning. *)
|
|
|
|
Theorem normalize_ok : forall e,
|
|
|
|
setexprDenote e = constant (normalize e).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct e; simpl. (* Here we use the more primitive [simpl], because [simplify]
|
|
|
|
* calls the fancier set automation from the book library,
|
|
|
|
* which would be "cheating." *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
pose proof (constant_dedup (fun x => x) ns).
|
|
|
|
repeat rewrite map_id in H.
|
|
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
rewrite IHe1, IHe2.
|
|
|
|
pose proof (constant_map_setmerge (fun x => x) (normalize e2) (normalize e1)).
|
|
|
|
repeat rewrite map_id in H.
|
|
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Reification works as before, with one twist. *)
|
|
|
|
Ltac reify_set E :=
|
|
|
|
match E with
|
|
|
|
| constant ?ns => constr:(Literal ns)
|
|
|
|
| ?E1 \cup ?E2 =>
|
|
|
|
let e1 := reify_set E1 in
|
|
|
|
let e2 := reify_set E2 in
|
|
|
|
constr:(Union e1 e2)
|
2018-03-07 01:29:57 +00:00
|
|
|
| _ => let pf := constr:(E = {}) in constr:(Literal [])
|
2017-03-08 16:50:29 +00:00
|
|
|
(* The twist is in this case: we instantiate all unification variables with
|
|
|
|
* the empty set. It's a sound proof step, and it so happens that we only
|
|
|
|
* call this tactic in spots where this heuristic makes sense. *)
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now the usual recipe for a reflective tactic, this time using rewriting
|
|
|
|
* instead of [apply] for the key step, to allow simplification deep within the
|
|
|
|
* structure of a goal. *)
|
|
|
|
Ltac simplify_set :=
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- context[?X \cup ?Y] ] =>
|
|
|
|
let e := reify_set (X \cup Y) in
|
2017-11-18 15:43:08 +00:00
|
|
|
let Heq := fresh in
|
|
|
|
assert (Heq : X \cup Y = setexprDenote e) by reflexivity;
|
|
|
|
rewrite Heq; clear Heq;
|
2017-03-08 16:50:29 +00:00
|
|
|
rewrite normalize_ok; simpl
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Back to our example, which we can now finish without calling [simplify] to
|
|
|
|
* reduces trees of union operations. *)
|
|
|
|
Lemma subtract_ok :
|
|
|
|
invariantFor (subtract_sys 5)
|
|
|
|
(fun n => n <= 5).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
eapply invariant_weaken.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply multiStepClosure_ok.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now, some more manual iterations: *)
|
|
|
|
eapply MscStep.
|
|
|
|
closure.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
(* Success! One subexpression shrunk. Now for the other. *)
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
(* Our automation doesn't handle set difference, so we finish up calling the
|
|
|
|
* library tactic. *)
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply MscStep.
|
|
|
|
closure.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply MscStep.
|
|
|
|
closure.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply MscStep.
|
|
|
|
closure.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify_set.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
model_check_done.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
linear_arithmetic.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
(** * A Smarter Tautology Solver *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now we are ready to revisit our earlier tautology-solver example. We want to
|
|
|
|
* broaden the scope of the tactic to include formulas whose truth is not
|
|
|
|
* syntactically apparent. We will want to allow injection of arbitrary
|
|
|
|
* formulas, like we allowed arbitrary monoid expressions in the last example.
|
|
|
|
* Since we are working in a richer theory, it is important to be able to use
|
|
|
|
* equalities between different injected formulas. For instance, we cannot
|
|
|
|
* prove [P -> P] by translating the formula into a value like
|
|
|
|
* [Imp (Var P) (Var P)], because a Gallina function has no way of comparing the
|
|
|
|
* two [P]s for equality. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* We introduce a synonym for how we name variables: natural numbers. *)
|
|
|
|
Definition propvar := nat.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Inductive formula : Set :=
|
|
|
|
| Atomic : propvar -> formula
|
|
|
|
| Truth : formula
|
|
|
|
| Falsehood : formula
|
|
|
|
| And : formula -> formula -> formula
|
|
|
|
| Or : formula -> formula -> formula
|
|
|
|
| Imp : formula -> formula -> formula.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now we can define our denotation function. First, a type of truth-value
|
|
|
|
* assignments to propositional variables: *)
|
|
|
|
Definition asgn := nat -> Prop.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint formulaDenote (atomics : asgn) (f : formula) : Prop :=
|
|
|
|
match f with
|
|
|
|
| Atomic v => atomics v
|
|
|
|
| Truth => True
|
|
|
|
| Falsehood => False
|
|
|
|
| And f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 /\ formulaDenote atomics f2
|
|
|
|
| Or f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 \/ formulaDenote atomics f2
|
|
|
|
| Imp f1 f2 => formulaDenote atomics f1 -> formulaDenote atomics f2
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
2020-02-02 22:16:19 +00:00
|
|
|
Require Import ListSet.
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
Section my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
Variable atomics : asgn.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now we are ready to define some helpful functions based on the [ListSet]
|
|
|
|
* module of the standard library, which (unsurprisingly) presents a view of
|
|
|
|
* lists as sets. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* The [eq_nat_dec] below is a richly typed equality test on [nat]s. We'll
|
2018-03-07 01:29:57 +00:00
|
|
|
* get to the ideas behind it in a later class. *)
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
Definition add (s : set propvar) (v : propvar) := set_add eq_nat_dec v s.
|
|
|
|
|
2018-03-07 01:29:57 +00:00
|
|
|
(* We define what it means for all members of a variable set to represent
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
* true propositions, and we prove some lemmas about this notion. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint allTrue (s : set propvar) : Prop :=
|
|
|
|
match s with
|
|
|
|
| nil => True
|
|
|
|
| v :: s' => atomics v /\ allTrue s'
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem allTrue_add : forall v s,
|
|
|
|
allTrue s
|
|
|
|
-> atomics v
|
|
|
|
-> allTrue (add s v).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct s; simplify; propositional;
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- context[if ?E then _ else _] ] => destruct E
|
|
|
|
end; simplify; propositional.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem allTrue_In : forall v s,
|
|
|
|
allTrue s
|
|
|
|
-> set_In v s
|
|
|
|
-> atomics v.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct s; simplify; equality.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Now we can write a function [forward] that implements deconstruction of
|
|
|
|
* hypotheses, expanding a compound formula into a set of sets of atomic
|
|
|
|
* formulas covering all possible cases introduced with use of [Or]. To
|
|
|
|
* handle consideration of multiple cases, the function takes in a
|
|
|
|
* continuation argument (advanced functional-programming feature that often
|
|
|
|
* puzzles novices, so don't worry if it takes a while to digest!), which will
|
|
|
|
* be called once for each case. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint forward (f : formula) (known : set propvar) (hyp : formula)
|
|
|
|
(cont : set propvar -> bool) : bool :=
|
|
|
|
match hyp with
|
|
|
|
| Atomic v => cont (add known v)
|
|
|
|
| Truth => cont known
|
|
|
|
| Falsehood => true
|
|
|
|
| And h1 h2 => forward (Imp h2 f) known h1 (fun known' =>
|
|
|
|
forward f known' h2 cont)
|
|
|
|
| Or h1 h2 => forward f known h1 cont && forward f known h2 cont
|
|
|
|
| Imp _ _ => cont known
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* A [backward] function implements analysis of the final goal. It calls
|
|
|
|
* [forward] to handle implications. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Fixpoint backward (known : set propvar) (f : formula) : bool :=
|
|
|
|
match f with
|
|
|
|
| Atomic v => if In_dec eq_nat_dec v known then true else false
|
|
|
|
| Truth => true
|
|
|
|
| Falsehood => false
|
|
|
|
| And f1 f2 => backward known f1 && backward known f2
|
|
|
|
| Or f1 f2 => backward known f1 || backward known f2
|
|
|
|
| Imp f1 f2 => forward f2 known f1 (fun known' => backward known' f2)
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
End my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Lemma forward_ok : forall atomics hyp f known cont,
|
|
|
|
forward f known hyp cont = true
|
|
|
|
-> (forall known', allTrue atomics known'
|
|
|
|
-> cont known' = true
|
|
|
|
-> formulaDenote atomics f)
|
|
|
|
-> allTrue atomics known
|
|
|
|
-> formulaDenote atomics hyp
|
|
|
|
-> formulaDenote atomics f.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct hyp; simplify; propositional.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply H0 with (known' := add known p).
|
|
|
|
apply allTrue_add.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply H0.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply IHhyp1 in H.
|
|
|
|
simplify; propositional.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHhyp2.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply andb_true_iff in H; propositional.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHhyp1.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply andb_true_iff in H; propositional.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHhyp2.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply H0.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Lemma backward_ok' : forall atomics f known,
|
|
|
|
backward known f = true
|
|
|
|
-> allTrue atomics known
|
|
|
|
-> formulaDenote atomics f.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
induct f; simplify; propositional.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
cases (in_dec Nat.eq_dec p known); propositional.
|
|
|
|
eapply allTrue_In.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
unfold set_In.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
equality.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply andb_true_iff in H; propositional.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHf1.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply andb_true_iff in H; propositional.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHf2.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
apply orb_true_iff in H; propositional.
|
|
|
|
left.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHf1.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
right.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHf2.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
eapply forward_ok.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
eapply IHf2.
|
|
|
|
eassumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem backward_ok : forall f,
|
|
|
|
backward [] f = true
|
|
|
|
-> forall atomics, formulaDenote atomics f.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
apply backward_ok' with (known := []).
|
|
|
|
assumption.
|
|
|
|
simplify.
|
|
|
|
propositional.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Find the position of an element in a list. *)
|
|
|
|
Ltac position x ls :=
|
|
|
|
match ls with
|
|
|
|
| [] => constr:(@None nat)
|
|
|
|
| x :: _ => constr:(Some 0)
|
|
|
|
| _ :: ?ls' =>
|
|
|
|
let p := position x ls' in
|
|
|
|
match p with
|
|
|
|
| None => p
|
|
|
|
| Some ?n => constr:(Some (S n))
|
|
|
|
end
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 19:05:46 +00:00
|
|
|
(* Compute a duplicate-free list of all variables in [P], combining it with
|
|
|
|
* [acc]. *)
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
Ltac vars_in P acc :=
|
|
|
|
match P with
|
|
|
|
| True => acc
|
|
|
|
| False => acc
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 /\ ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let acc' := vars_in Q1 acc in
|
|
|
|
vars_in Q2 acc'
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 \/ ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let acc' := vars_in Q1 acc in
|
|
|
|
vars_in Q2 acc'
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 -> ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let acc' := vars_in Q1 acc in
|
|
|
|
vars_in Q2 acc'
|
|
|
|
| _ =>
|
|
|
|
let pos := position P acc in
|
|
|
|
match pos with
|
|
|
|
| Some _ => acc
|
|
|
|
| None => constr:(P :: acc)
|
|
|
|
end
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
2017-03-08 19:05:46 +00:00
|
|
|
(* Reification of formula [P], with a pregenertaed list [vars] of variables it
|
|
|
|
* may mention *)
|
2017-03-08 15:44:25 +00:00
|
|
|
Ltac reify_tauto' P vars :=
|
|
|
|
match P with
|
|
|
|
| True => Truth
|
|
|
|
| False => Falsehood
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 /\ ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let q1 := reify_tauto' Q1 vars in
|
|
|
|
let q2 := reify_tauto' Q2 vars in
|
|
|
|
constr:(And q1 q2)
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 \/ ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let q1 := reify_tauto' Q1 vars in
|
|
|
|
let q2 := reify_tauto' Q2 vars in
|
|
|
|
constr:(Or q1 q2)
|
|
|
|
| ?Q1 -> ?Q2 =>
|
|
|
|
let q1 := reify_tauto' Q1 vars in
|
|
|
|
let q2 := reify_tauto' Q2 vars in
|
|
|
|
constr:(Imp q1 q2)
|
|
|
|
| _ =>
|
|
|
|
let pos := position P vars in
|
|
|
|
match pos with
|
|
|
|
| Some ?pos' => constr:(Atomic pos')
|
|
|
|
end
|
|
|
|
end.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Our final tactic implementation is now fairly straightforward. First, we
|
|
|
|
* [intro] all quantifiers that do not bind [Prop]s. Then we reify. Finally,
|
|
|
|
* we call the verified procedure through a lemma. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ltac my_tauto :=
|
|
|
|
repeat match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- forall x : ?P, _ ] =>
|
|
|
|
match type of P with
|
|
|
|
| Prop => fail 1
|
|
|
|
| _ => intro
|
|
|
|
end
|
|
|
|
end;
|
|
|
|
match goal with
|
|
|
|
| [ |- ?P ] =>
|
|
|
|
let vars := vars_in P (@nil Prop) in
|
|
|
|
let p := reify_tauto' P vars in
|
|
|
|
change (formulaDenote (nth_default False vars) p)
|
|
|
|
end;
|
|
|
|
apply backward_ok; reflexivity.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* A few examples demonstrate how the tactic works: *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem mt1 : True.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print mt1.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem mt2 : forall x y : nat, x = y -> x = y.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print mt2.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Crucially, both instances of [x = y] are represented with the same variable
|
|
|
|
* 0. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem mt3 : forall x y z,
|
|
|
|
(x < y /\ y > z) \/ (y > z /\ x < S y)
|
|
|
|
-> y > z /\ (x < y \/ x < S y).
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print mt3.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* Our goal contained three distinct atomic formulas, and we see that a
|
|
|
|
* three-element environment is generated.
|
|
|
|
*
|
|
|
|
* It can be interesting to observe differences between the level of repetition
|
|
|
|
* in proof terms generated by [my_tauto] and [tauto] for especially trivial
|
|
|
|
* theorems. *)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem mt4 : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False -> False.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
my_tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print mt4.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Theorem mt4' : True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ True /\ False -> False.
|
|
|
|
Proof.
|
|
|
|
tauto.
|
|
|
|
Qed.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Print mt4'.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(* The traditional [tauto] tactic introduces a quadratic blow-up in the size of
|
|
|
|
* the proof term, whereas proofs produced by [my_tauto] always have linear
|
|
|
|
* size. *)
|